Linked bibliography for the SEP article "Rights" by Leif Wenar
This is an automatically generated and experimental page
If everything goes well, this page should display the bibliography of the aforementioned article as it appears in the Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, but with links added to PhilPapers records and Google Scholar for your convenience. Some bibliographies are not going to be represented correctly or fully up to date. In general, bibliographies of recent works are going to be much better linked than bibliographies of primary literature and older works. Entries with PhilPapers records have links on their titles. A green link indicates that the item is available online at least partially.
This experiment has been authorized by the editors of the Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. The original article and bibliography can be found here.
- Ackerly, B., 2013, “Feminist and Activist Approaches to
Human Rights,” in M. Goodhart (ed.), Human Rights: Politics
and Practice, Second ed., Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp.
28–43. (Scholar)
- Andersson, A-K., 2013, “Choices, Interests, and
Potentiality: What Distinguishes Bearers of Rights?” Journal
of Value Inquiry, 47: 175–90. (Scholar)
- Bentham, J., 1796, Anarchical Fallacies, in Waldron
1987a, pp. 46–76. (Scholar)
- Brett, A., 1997, Liberty, Right, and Nature, Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press. (Scholar)
- Campbell, T., 2006, Rights: A Critical Introduction, London: Routledge. (Scholar)
- Cornell, N., 2015, “Wrongs, Rights, and Third Parties,” Philosophy and Public Affairs, 43: 109–143. (Scholar)
- Cruft, R., 2004, “Why is it Disrespectful to Violate
Rights?” Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 113:
201–24. (Scholar)
- –––, 2010, “On the Non-Instrumental Value of Basic Rights,” Journal of Moral Philosophy, 7: 441–61. (Scholar)
- –––, 2019, Human Rights, Ownership, and the Individual, Oxford: Oxford University Press. (Scholar)
- Darwall, S., 2006, The Second-Person Standpoint, Cambridge: Harvard University Press. (Scholar)
- –––, 2012, “Bipolar Obligation,” in R. Shafer-Landau (ed.), Oxford Studies in Metaethics, 7: 333–357. (Scholar)
- Donahue, Jr., Charles, 2010, “Ius in Roman
Law,” in J. Witte, Jr. and F. Alexander (eds.), Christianity
and Human Rights, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp.
64–80. (Scholar)
- Dworkin, R., 1984, “Rights as Trumps,” in Waldron
1984, pp. 153–67. (Scholar)
- Edmundson, W., 2012, An Introduction to Rights,
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2nd edition. (Scholar)
- Enoch, D., 2002, “A Right to Violate One’s
Duty,” Law and Philosophy, 21: 376–78. (Scholar)
- Feinberg, J., 1970, “The Nature and Value of Rights,” Journal of Value Inquiry, 4: 243–257. (Scholar)
- –––, 1973, Social Philosophy, Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall. (Scholar)
- –––, 1980, Rights, Justice, and the Bounds
of Liberty, Princeton: Princeton University Press. (Scholar)
- Finnis, J., 1980, Natural Law and Natural Right, Oxford: Clarendon Press. (Scholar)
- Forst, R., 2012, The Right to Justification: Elements of a Constructivist Theory of Justice, J. Flynn (trans.), New York: Columbia University Press. (Scholar)
- –––, 2014, Justice, Democracy and the Right to Justification: Rainer Forst in Dialogue, London: Bloomsbury. (Scholar)
- –––, 2016, “The Justification of Basic Rights: A Discourse-Theoretical Approach,” Netherlands Journal of Legal Philosophy, 45: 7–28 (Scholar)
- Frederick, D., 2014, “Pro-Tanto Versus Absolute Rights,” Philosophical Forum, 45: 275–94. (Scholar)
- Frey R., 1985, “Act-Utilitarianism, Consequentialism, and
Moral Rights,” in R. Frey (ed.), Utility and Rights,
Oxford, Basil Blackwell, pp. 61–85. (Scholar)
- Frydrych, D., 2018, “The Theories of Rights Debate,” Jurisprudence, 9(3): 566–588. (Scholar)
- Gewirth, A., 1981, “Are There any Absolute Rights?” in Waldron 1984, pp. 81–109. (Scholar)
- Gilabert, P., 2010, “The Importance of Linkage Arguments for the Theory and Practice of Human Rights: A Response to James Nickel,” Human Rights Quarterly, 32: 425–38. (Scholar)
- Gilbert, M., 2004, “Scanlon on Promissory Obligation: The Problem of Promisees’ Rights,” The Journal of Philosophy, 101: 83–109. (Scholar)
- –––, 2013, Joint Commitment: How We Make the Social World, New York: Oxford University Press. (Scholar)
- –––, 2018, Rights and Demands: A Foundational Inquiry, Oxford: Oxford University Press. (Scholar)
- Gilligan, C., 1993, In a Different Voice, Cambridge:
Harvard University Press. (Scholar)
- Glendon, M., 1991, Rights Talk: The Impoverishment of Political Discourse, New York: Free Press. (Scholar)
- Glick, J., 2010, “Justification and the Right to Believe,” Philosophical Quarterly, 60: 532–44. (Scholar)
- Graham, P. and N. Pedersen (eds.), 2012, Epistemic Entitlement, Oxford: Oxford University Press. (Scholar)
- Griffin, J., 1989, Well-Being: Its Meaning, Measurement, and Moral Importance, Oxford: Oxford University Press. (Scholar)
- Gutmann, A., 1985, “Communitarian Critics of
Liberalism,” Philosophy and Public Affairs, 14:
308–322. (Scholar)
- Halpin, A., 2017, “The Value of Hohfeldian Neutrality when Theorising about Legal Rights,” in McBride (ed.) 2017, pp. 1–30. (Scholar)
- Harel, A., 2005, “Theories of Rights,” in M. Golding and W. Edmundson (eds.), Blackwell’s Guide to the Philosophy of Law and Legal Theory, pp. 191–206. (Scholar)
- Hart, H., 1961, The Concept of Law, Oxford: Oxford University Press. (Scholar)
- –––, 1982, Essays on Bentham: Studies in Jurisprudence and Political Theory, Oxford: Clarendon Press. (Scholar)
- Hayward, T., 2013, “On Prepositional Duties,” Ethics, 123: 264–91. (Scholar)
- Herstein, O., 2012, “Defending a Right to Do Wrong,” Law and Philosophy, 31: 343–65. (Scholar)
- –––, 2013, “A Legal Right to Do Legal Wrong,” Oxford Journal of Legal Studies, 34: 1–25. (Scholar)
- Hohfeld, W., 1919, Fundamental Legal Conceptions, W. Cook
(ed.), New Haven: Yale University Press. (Scholar)
- Holmes, S., and C. Sunstein, 1999, The Costs of Rights,
New York: W.W. Norton. (Scholar)
- Ignatieff, M., 2003, “Human Rights, Sovereignty, and
Intervention,” in N. Owen (ed.), Human Rights and Human
Wrongs: The Oxford Amnesty Lectures 2001, Oxford: Oxford
University Press. (Scholar)
- Ivison, D., 2007, Rights, Montreal: McGill-Queen’s University Press. (Scholar)
- James, W., 1897, The Will to Believe; page references in the text are to W. James, The Will to Believe and Human Immortality, New York: Dover, 1956. (Scholar)
- Jones, P., 1994, Rights, New York: St. Martin’s
Press. (Scholar)
- Kamm, F., 1992, “Non-Consequentialism, the Person as an End-in-Itself, and the Significance of Status”, Philosophy and Public Affairs, 21: 354–89. (Scholar)
- –––, 2002, “Rights,” in J. Coleman and S. Shapiro (eds.), The Oxford Handbook of Jurisprudence and Philosophy of Law, Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 486–513. (Scholar)
- –––, 2007, Intricate Ethics, Oxford: Oxford University Press. (Scholar)
- Kramer, M., 2001, “Getting Rights Right”, in M. Kramer
(ed.), Rights, Wrongs, and Responsibilities, London:
Macmillan, pp. 28–95. (Scholar)
- –––, 2013, “Some Doubts about Alternatives
to the Interest Theory,” Ethics, 123:
245–63. (Scholar)
- –––, 2017, “In Defence of the Interest Theory of Right-Holding: Rejoinders to Leif Wenar on Rights,” in McBride (ed.) 2017, pp. 49–84. (Scholar)
- Kramer, M., N. Simmonds, and H. Steiner, 1998, A Debate Over Rights, Oxford: Oxford University Press. (Scholar)
- Kramer, M., and H. Steiner, 2007, “Theories of Rights: Is There a Third Way?” Oxford Journal of Legal Studies, 27: 281–310. (Scholar)
- Kurki, V., 2018, “Rights, Harming, and Wronging: A Restatement of the Interest Theory,” Oxford Journal of Legal Studies, 38: 430–50. (Scholar)
- Liberto, H., 2014, “The Moral Specification of Rights: A Restricted Account,” Law and Philosophy, 33: 175–206. (Scholar)
- Lisska, A. and B. Tierney, 2015, “Philosophy of Law in the
Later Middle Ages,” in F. Miller and C.-A. Biondi (eds.), A
History of the Philosophy of Law from the Ancient Greeks to the
Scholastics, second edition, Dordrecht: Springer, pp.
311–33. (Scholar)
- Louden, R., 1983, “Rights Infatuation and the Impoverishment of Moral Theory,” Journal of Value Inquiry, 17: 87–102. (Scholar)
- Lyons, D., 1970, “The Correlativity of Rights and Duties,” Noûs, 4: 45–57. (Scholar)
- –––, 1994, Rights, Welfare and Mill’s Moral
Theory, Oxford: Oxford University Press. (Scholar)
- MacCormick, N., 1977, “Rights in Legislation”, in P.
Hacker and J. Raz, (eds.), Law, Morality and Society: Essays in
Honour of H.L.A Hart, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1977, pp.
189–209. (Scholar)
- –––, 1982, Legal Right and Social Democracy, Oxford: Oxford University Press. (Scholar)
- Mackie, J., 1979, “Can There be a Rights-Based Moral Theory?” in Waldron 1984, pp. 168–81. (Scholar)
- Martin, R., 1993, A System of Rights, Oxford: Oxford
University Press. (Scholar)
- –––, 1985, Rawls and Rights, Lawrence, Kansas: University Press of Kansas. (Scholar)
- Marx, K., 1844, “On the Jewish Question”; page
reference in the text is to the reprint in Waldron 1987a, pp.
137–50. (Scholar)
- May, S., 2012, “Moral Status and the Direction of Duties,” Ethics, 123: 113–28. (Scholar)
- –––, 2015, “Directed Duties,” Philosophy Compass, 10: 523–32. (Scholar)
- McBride, M. (ed.), 2017, New Essays on the Nature of
Rights, London: Bloomsbury. (Scholar)
- Mill, J., 1859, On Liberty; page reference in the text is to the reprint in J. Mill, On Liberty and Other Essays, S. Collini (ed.), Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1989. (Scholar)
- –––, 1861, Utilitarianism; page reference in the text is to the reprint in J. Mill, Utilitarianism, G. Sher (ed.), Indianapolis: Hackett, 2002. (Scholar)
- Montague, P., 2015, “Specification and Moral Rights,” Law and Philosophy, 34: 241–56. (Scholar)
- Mulhall, S., and Swift, A., 1992, Liberals and Communitarians, Oxford: Blackwell. (Scholar)
- Mullins, R., forthcoming, “Moral Conflict and the Logic of Rights,” Philosophical Studies, first online 14 November 2018. doi.org/10.1007/s11098-018-1197-1 (Scholar)
- Nagel, T., 2002, Concealment and Exposure, Oxford: Oxford University Press. (Scholar)
- Narveson, J., 2001, The Libertarian Idea, Peterborough,
Ontario: Broadview. (Scholar)
- Nickel, J., 2008, “Rethinking Indivisibility: Towards a
Theory of Supporting Relations between Human Rights,” Human
Rights Quarterly 30: 984–1001. (Scholar)
- –––, 2010, “Indivisibility and Linkage
Arguments: A Reply to Gilabert,”, Human Rights
Quarterly, 32: 439–46. (Scholar)
- –––, 2016, “Can a Right to Health Care be Justified by Linkage Arguments?” Theoretical Medicine and Bioethics, 37: 293–306. (Scholar)
- Oberdiek, J., 2008 “Specifying Rights Out of Necessity,” Oxford Journal of Legal Studies, 28: 127–46. (Scholar)
- O’Neill, O., 1996, Toward Justice and Virtue: A Constructive Account of Practical Reasoning, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. (Scholar)
- –––, 2002, A Question of Trust,
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. (Scholar)
- Osiel, M., 2019, The Right to Do Wrong: Morality and the Limits of Law, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. (Scholar)
- Otsuka, M., 2003, Libertarianism Without Inequality, Oxford: Oxford University Press. (Scholar)
- Pallikkathayil, J., 2016, “Revisiting the Interest Theory of
Rights: Discussion of The Morality of Freedom,” Jerusalem
Review of Legal Studies, 14: 147–57. (Scholar)
- Pettit, P., 1988, “The Consequentialist can Recognize Rights,” Philosophical Quarterly, 38: 42–55. (Scholar)
- Plamenatz, J., 1938, Consent, Freedom, and Political Obligation, Oxford: Oxford University Press. (Scholar)
- Quinn, W., 1993, Morality and Action, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press. (Scholar)
- Quong, J. and R. Stone, 2015, “Rules and Rights,” in
D. Sobel, P. Vallentyne, and S. Wall (eds.), Oxford Studies in
Political Philosophy (Volume 1), Oxford: Oxford University
Press. (Scholar)
- Rainbolt, G., 2006, The Concept of Rights, Dordrecht:
Springer. (Scholar)
- Rawls, J., 1971, A Theory of Justice, Cambridge: Harvard University Press. (Scholar)
- Raz, J., 1975, Practical Reason and Norms, London: Hutchinson. (Scholar)
- –––, 1986, The Morality of Freedom, Oxford: Oxford University Press. (Scholar)
- –––, 1995, Ethics in the Public Domain, (Revised Edition), Oxford: Oxford University Press. (Scholar)
- Sandel, M., 1982, Liberalism and the Limits of Justice, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. (Scholar)
- Scanlon, T., 1977, “Rights, Goals, and Fairness,” in Waldron 1984, pp. 137–52. (Scholar)
- –––, 2003, The Difficulty of Tolerance, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. (Scholar)
- –––, 2013, “Reply to Leif Wenar”, Journal of Moral Philosophy, 10: 400–05. (Scholar)
- Schaab, J., 2018, “Why is it Disrespectful to Violate Rights: Contractualism and the Kind-Desire Theory,” Philosophical Studies, 175: 97–116. (Scholar)
- Schauer, F., 1984, “Can Rights Be Abused?”
Philosophical Quarterly, 31: 225–30. (Scholar)
- Schneider, E., 1986, “The Dialectic of Rights and Politics:
Perspectives from the Women’s Movement,” New York
University Law Review, 14: 589–652. (Scholar)
- Sen, A., 1982, “Rights and Agency,” Philosophy and Public Affairs, 11: 3–39. (Scholar)
- Sen, A., 1999, Development as Freedom, Oxford: Oxford
University Press. (Scholar)
- Shafer-Landau, R., 1995, “Specifying Absolute Rights,”
Arizona Law Review, 37: 209–24. (Scholar)
- Shapiro, I., 1986, The Evolution of Rights in Liberal Theory:
An Essay in Critical Theory, Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press. (Scholar)
- Shue, H., 1996, Basic Rights: Subsistence, Affluence, and U.S.
Foreign Policy, Princeton: Princeton University Press. (Scholar)
- Siedentop, L., 2014, Inventing the Individual, Cambridge: Harvard University Press. (Scholar)
- Sinnott-Armstrong, W., 1996, “Moral Dilemmas and
Rights”, in H. E. Mason (ed.), Moral Dilemmas and Moral
Theory, New York: Oxford University Press, pp. 48–65. (Scholar)
- Skorupski, J., 2010, The Domain of Reasons, Oxford: Oxford University Press. (Scholar)
- Sreenivasan, G., 2005, “A Hybrid Theory of Claim-Rights,” Oxford Journal of Legal Studies 25: 257–74. (Scholar)
- –––, 2010, “Duties and Their Direction,” Ethics, 120 (3): 465–494. (Scholar)
- Steiner, H., 1994, An Essay on Rights, Oxford, Blackwell. (Scholar)
- –––, 2013, “Directed Duties and Inalienable Rights,” Ethics, 123: 230–44. (Scholar)
- Sumner, L., 1987, The Moral Foundations of Rights, Oxford: Oxford University Press. (Scholar)
- Taylor, C., 1979, “Atomism,” in A. Kontos (ed.), Powers, Possessions, and Freedom, Toronto: University of Toronto Press. (Scholar)
- Thompson, M., 2004, “What is It to Wrong Someone? A Puzzle About Justice,” in R.J. Wallace, P. Pettit, S., Scheffler, and M. Smith (eds.), Reason and Value: Themes from the Moral Philosophy of Joseph Raz, Oxford: Clarendon. (Scholar)
- Thomson, J., 1990, The Realm of Rights, Cambridge: Harvard University Press. (Scholar)
- Tierney, B., 1997, The Idea of Natural Rights, Atlanta:
Scholars Press. (Scholar)
- Tushnet, M., 1984, “An Essay on Rights,” Texas Law
Review, 62: 1363–1403. (Scholar)
- Vallentyne, P., and H. Steiner (eds.), 2000, Left Libertarianism and its Critics: The Contemporary Debate, New York: Palgrave Macmillan. (Scholar)
- Van Duffel, S., 2012a, “In Defense of the Will Theory of Rights,” Res Publica, 18: 231–31. (Scholar)
- –––, 2012b, “The Nature of Rights Debate Rests on a Mistake,” Philosophical Quarterly, 93: 104–23. (Scholar)
- Waldron, J. (ed.), 1984, Theories of Rights, Oxford: Oxford University Press. (Scholar)
- –––, (ed.), 1987a, Nonsense Upon Stilts: Bentham, Burke, and Marx on the Rights of Man, London: Methuen. (Scholar)
- –––, 1987b, “Nonsense Upon Stilts?—A Reply,” in Waldron 1987a, pp. 151–209. (Scholar)
- –––, 1993, Liberal Rights: Collected Papers 1981–1991, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. (Scholar)
- Walen, A., 2019, The Mechanics of Claims and Permissible Killing in War, New York: Oxford University Press. (Scholar)
- Wellman, C., 1985, A Theory of Rights, Totowa, NJ: Rowman & Allanheld. (Scholar)
- –––, 1995, Real Rights, Oxford: Oxford University Press. (Scholar)
- –––, 1997, An Approach to Rights, Dordrecht: Kluwer. (Scholar)
- Wellman, C. H., 2017, Rights, Forfeiture, and Punishment, Oxford: Oxford University Press. (Scholar)
- Wenar, L., 2003, “Legal Rights and Epistemic Rights,”
Analysis, 63: 142–46. (Scholar)
- –––, 2005, “The Nature of Rights,” Philosophy and Public Affairs, 33: 223–53. (Scholar)
- –––, 2008, “The Analysis of Rights,” in M. Kramer, C. Grant, B. Colburn, and A. Hatzistavrou (eds.), The Legacy of H. L. A. Hart, Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 251–73. (Scholar)
- –––, 2013a, “Rights and What We Owe to Each Other,” Journal of Moral Philosophy, 10: 375–99. (Scholar)
- –––, 2013b, “The Nature of Claim-Rights,” Ethics, 123: 202–29. (Scholar)
- Whelan, D., 2010, Indivisible Human Rights: A History,
Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania Press. (Scholar)
- Williams, G., 1968, “The Concept of a Legal Liberty”,
in R. Summers (ed.), Essays in Legal Philosophy, Oxford:
Blackwell, pp. 121–44. (Scholar)