Linked bibliography for the SEP article "Social Choice Theory" by Christian List
This is an automatically generated and experimental page
If everything goes well, this page should display the bibliography of the aforementioned article as it appears in the Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, but with links added to PhilPapers records and Google Scholar for your convenience. Some bibliographies are not going to be represented correctly or fully up to date. In general, bibliographies of recent works are going to be much better linked than bibliographies of primary literature and older works. Entries with PhilPapers records have links on their titles. A green link indicates that the item is available online at least partially.
This experiment has been authorized by the editors of the Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. The original article and bibliography can be found here.
- Arrow, K., 1951/1963, Social Choice and Individual Values. New York: Wiley. (Scholar)
- Austen-Smith, D. and J. S. Banks, 1996, “Information Aggregation, Rationality, and the Condorcet Jury Theorem.” American Political Science Review, 90: 34–45. (Scholar)
- Bartholdi, J. J., C. A. Tovey, and M. A. Trick, 1989, “The computational difficulty of manipulating an election.” Social Choice and Welfare, 6: 227–241. (Scholar)
- Ben-Yashar, R. and S. Nitzan, 1997, “The optimal decision rule for fixed-size committees in dichotomous choice situations: the general result.” International Economic Review, 38: 175–186. (Scholar)
- Berend, D. and J. Paroush, 1998, “When is Condorcet's Jury Theorem valid?” Social Choice and Welfare, 15: 481–488. (Scholar)
- Berend, D. and L. Sapir., 2007, “Monotonicity in Condorcet's Jury Theorem with dependent voters.” Social Choice and Welfare, 28: 507–528. (Scholar)
- Black, D., 1948, “On the Rationale of Group Decision-Making.” Journal of Political Economy, 56: 23–34. (Scholar)
- Blackorby, C., W. Bossert, and D. Donaldson, 1999, “Information Invariance in Variable-Population Social-Choice Problems.” International Economic Review, 40: 403–422. (Scholar)
- –––, 2005, Population Issues in Social Choice Theory, Welfare Economics, and Ethics,. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. (Scholar)
- Blau, J. H., 1975, “Liberal Values and Independence.” Review of Economic Studies, 42: 395–401. (Scholar)
- Boland, P. J., 1989, “Majority systems and the Condorcet jury theorem.” Statistician, 38: 181–189. (Scholar)
- Bossert, W. and J. A. Weymark, 1996, “Utility in social choice.” Handbook of Utility Theory, Volume 2. S. Barberà, P. J. Hammond and C. Seidel, (eds.). Boston: Kluwer. (Scholar)
- Bossert, W., C. X. Qi, and J. A. Weymark, 2013, “Extensive social choice and the measurement of group fitness in biological hierarchies.” Biology and Philosophy, 28: 75–98. (Scholar)
- Bovens, L. and W. Rabinowicz, 2006, “Democratic Answers to Complex Questions: An Epistemic Perspective.” Synthese, 150: 131–153. (Scholar)
- Brams, S. J. and A. D. Taylor, 1996, Fair Division: From Cake-Cutting to Dispute Resolution. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. (Scholar)
- Brandt, F., V. Conitzer, and U. Endriss, 2013, “Computational Social Choice.” Multiagent Systems. G. Weiss (ed.). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, pp. 213–283. (Scholar)
- Brighouse, H. and M. Fleurbaey, 2010, “Democracy and Proportionality.” Journal of Political Philosophy, 18: 137–155. (Scholar)
- Chapman, B., 2002, “Rational Aggregation.” Politics, Philosophy and Economics, 1: 337–354. (Scholar)
- Condorcet, Nicolas de, 1785, Essay sur l'Application de l'Analyse à la Probabilité des Décisions Rendue à la Pluralité des Voix. Paris. (Scholar)
- Conradt, L. and C. List, 2009, “Group decisions in humans and animals: a survey.” Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society, B 364: 719–742. (Scholar)
- Craven, J., 1982, “Liberalism and Individual Preferences.” Theory and Decision, 14: 351–360. (Scholar)
- Deschamps, R. and L. Gevers, 1978, “Leximin and utilitarian rules: A joint characterization.” Journal of Economic Theory, 17: 143–163. (Scholar)
- Dietrich, F., 2006, “Judgment Aggregation: (Im)Possibility Theorems.” Journal of Economic Theory, 126: 286–298. (Scholar)
- –––, 2007, “A generalised model of judgment aggregation.” Social Choice and Welfare, 28: 529–565.
- –––, 2008, “The premises of Condorcet's jury theorem are not simultaneously justified.” Episteme, 5: 56–73. (Scholar)
- Dietrich, F. and C. List, 2004, “A Model of Jury Decisions Where All Jurors Have the Same Evidence.” Synthese, 142: 175–202. (Scholar)
- –––, 2007a, “Judgment aggregation by quota rules: majority voting generalized.” Journal of Theoretical Politics, 19: 391–424. (Scholar)
- –––, 2007b, “Arrow's theorem in judgment aggregation.” Social Choice and Welfare, 29: 19–33. (Scholar)
- –––, 2007c, “Strategy-proof judgment aggregation.” Economics and Philosophy, 23: 269–300. (Scholar)
- –––, 2007d, “Opinion pooling on general agendas.” [Dietrich and List 2007d available online (pdf)] (Scholar)
- –––, 2008, “Judgment aggregation without full rationality.” Social Choice and Welfare, 31: 15–39. (Scholar)
- –––, 2010a, “Majority voting on restricted domains.” Journal of Economic Theory, 145: 512–543. (Scholar)
- –––, 2010b, “The aggregation of propositional attitudes: towards a general theory.” Oxford Studies in Epistemology, 3: 215–234. (Scholar)
- Dietrich, F. and P. Mongin, 2010, “The premise-based approach to judgment aggregation.” Journal of Economic Theory, 145: 562–582. (Scholar)
- Dietrich, F. and K. Spiekermann, 2013, “Epistemic Democracy with Defensible Premises.” Economics and Philosophy, 29(1): 87–120. (Scholar)
- Dokow, E. and R. Holzman, 2010a, “Aggregation of binary evaluations.” Journal of Economic Theory, 145: 495–511. (Scholar)
- –––, 2010b, “Aggregation of binary evaluations with abstentions.” Journal of Economic Theory, 145: 544–561. (Scholar)
- –––, 2010c, “Aggregation of non-binary evaluations.” Advances in Applied Mathematics, 45: 487–504. (Scholar)
- Dowding, K. and M. van Hees, 2003, “The Construction of Rights.” American Political Science Review, 97: 281–293. (Scholar)
- –––, 2008, “In Praise of Manipulation.” British Journal of Political Science, 38: 1–15. (Scholar)
- Dryzek, J. and C. List, 2003, “Social Choice Theory and Deliberative Democracy: A Reconciliation.” British Journal of Political Science, 33: 1–28. (Scholar)
- Elsholtz, C. and C. List, 2005, “A Simple Proof of Sen's Possibility Theorem on Majority Decisions.” Elemente der Mathematik, 60: 45–56. (Scholar)
- Elster, J., 2013, “Excessive Ambitions (II).” Capitalism and Society, 8, Issue 1, Article 1. (Scholar)
- Estlund, D., 1994, “Opinion Leaders, Independence, and Condorcet's Jury Theorem.” Theory and Decision, 36: 131–162. (Scholar)
- Feddersen, T. J. and W. Pesendorfer, 1998, “Convicting the Innocent.” American Political Science Review, 92: 23–35. (Scholar)
- Gaertner, W., 2001, Domain Conditions in Social Choice Theory. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. (Scholar)
- –––, 2005, “De jure naturae et gentium: Samuel von Pufendorf's contribution to social choice theory and economics.” Social Choice and Welfare, 25: 231–241. (Scholar)
- Gaertner, W., P. K. Pattanaik, and K. Suzumura, 1992, “Individual Rights Revisited.” Economica, 59: 161–177. (Scholar)
- Gaertner, W. and E. Schokkaert, 2012, Empirical Social Choice: Questionnaire-Experimental Studies on Distributive Justice. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. (Scholar)
- Gärdenfors, P., 2006, “An Arrow-like theorem for voting with logical consequences.” Economics and Philosophy, 22: 181–190. (Scholar)
- Gehrlein, W. V., 1983, “Condorcet's Paradox.” Theory and Decision, 15: 161–197. (Scholar)
- Genest, C. and J. V. Zidek, 1986, “Combining Probability Distributions: A Critique and Annotated Bibliography.” Statistical Science, 1: 113–135. (Scholar)
- Gibbard, A., 1969, “Social Choice and the Arrow Conditions.” Unpublished manuscript. [Gibbard 1969 available online (pdf)] (Scholar)
- –––, 1973, “Manipulation of voting schemes: a general result.” Econometrica, 41: 587–601. (Scholar)
- Gigliotti, G. A., 1986, “Comment on Craven.” Theory and Decision, 21: 89–95. (Scholar)
- Gilboa, I., D. Samet, and D. Schmeidler, 2004, “Utilitarian Aggregation of Beliefs and Tastes.” Journal of Political Economy, 112: 932–938. (Scholar)
- Goldman, A., 2004, “Group Knowledge versus Group Rationality: Two Approaches to Social Epistemology.” Episteme, A Journal of Social Epistemology, 1: 11–22. (Scholar)
- –––, 2010, “Why Social Epistemology Is Real Epistemology.” Social Epistemology. A. Haddock, A. Millar, and D. Pritchard (eds.), Oxford: Oxford University Press. (Scholar)
- Goodin, R. E. and C. List, 2006, “A Conditional Defense of Plurality Rule: Generalizing May's Theorem in a Restricted Informational Environment.” American Journal of Political Science, 50: 940–949. (Scholar)
- Grofman, B., G. Owen, and S. L. Feld, 1983, “Thirteen theorems in search of the truth.” Theory and Decision, 15: 261–278. (Scholar)
- Guilbaud, G. T., [1952] 1966, “Theories of the General Interest, and the Logical Problem of Aggregation.” Readings in Mathematical Social Science. P. F. Lazarsfeld and N. W. Henry (eds.). Cambridge/MA: MIT Press, pp. 262–307. (Scholar)
- Harbour, D. and C. List, 2000, “Optimality Theory and the problem of constraint aggregation.” MIT Working Papers in Linguistics and Philosophy 1: The Linguistics/Philosophy Interface. R. Bhatt, P. Hawley, M. Hackl and I. Maitra (eds.). Cambridge, MA: MITWIPL, pp. 175–213. (Scholar)
- Harrison, G. W. and T. McDaniel, 2008, “Voting Games and Computational Complexity.” Oxford Economic Papers, 60: 546–565. (Scholar)
- Hausman, D., 1995, “The Impossibility of Interpersonal Utility Comparisons.” Mind, 104: 473–490. (Scholar)
- Hurley, S., 1985, “Supervenience and the Possibility of Coherence.” Mind, 94: 501–525. (Scholar)
- Inada, K.-I., 1964, “A Note on the Simple Majority Decision Rule.” Econometrica, 32: 525–531. (Scholar)
- Kanazawa, S., 1998, “A brief note on a further refinement of the Condorcet Jury Theorem for heterogeneous groups.” Mathematical Social Sciences, 35: 69–73. (Scholar)
- Knight, J. and J. Johnson, 1994, “Aggregation and Deliberation: On the Possibility of Democratic Legitimacy.” Political Theory, 22: 277–296. (Scholar)
- Konieczny, S. and R. Pino Pérez, 2002, “Merging Information Under Constraints: A Logical Framework.” Journal of Logic and Computation, 12: 773–808. (Scholar)
- Kornhauser, L. A. and L. G. Sager, 1986, “Unpacking the Court.” Yale Law Journal, 96: 82–117. (Scholar)
- Kroedel, T. and F. Huber, 2013, “Counterfactual Dependence and Arrow.” Noûs, 47(3): 453–466. (Scholar)
- Ladha, K., 1992, “The Condorcet Jury Theorem, Free Speech and Correlated Votes.” American Journal of Political Science, 36: 617–634. (Scholar)
- Lehrer, K. and C. Wagner, 1981, Rational Consensus in Science and Society. Dordrecht/Boston: Reidel. (Scholar)
- List, C., 2001, “A Note on Introducing a ‘Zero-Line’ of Welfare as an Escape-Route from Arrow's Theorem.” Pacific Economic Review, 6, special section in honour of Amartya Sen, 223–238. (Scholar)
- –––, 2003a, “The epistemology of special majority voting.” Working paper, London School of Economics. [List 2003a available online (pdf)] (Scholar)
- –––, 2003b, “Are Interpersonal Comparisons of Utility Indeterminate?” Erkenntnis, 58: 229–260. (Scholar)
- –––, 2003c, “A Possibility Theorem on Aggregation over Multiple Interconnected Propositions.” Mathematical Social Sciences, 45: 1–13 (with Corrigendum in Mathematical Social Sciences, 52: 109–110). (Scholar)
- –––, 2004a, “Multidimensional Welfare Aggregation.” Public Choice, 119: 119–142. (Scholar)
- –––, 2004b, “A Model of Path-Dependence in Decisions over Multiple Propositions.” American Political Science Review, 98: 495–513. (Scholar)
- –––, 2006, “The Discursive Dilemma and Public Reason.” Ethics, 116: 362–402. (Scholar)
- –––, 2011, “The Logical Space of Democracy.” Philosophy and Public Affairs, 39: 262–297. (Scholar)
- –––, 2012, “The Theory of Judgment Aggregation: An Introductory Review.” Synthese, 187: 179–207. (Scholar)
- List, C. and R. E. Goodin, 2001, “Epistemic Democracy: Generalizing the Condorcet Jury Theorem.” Journal of Political Philosophy, 9: 277–306. (Scholar)
- List, C., R. C. Luskin, J. S. Fishkin, and I. McLean, 2013, “Deliberation, Single-Peakedness, and the Possibility of Meaningful Democracy: Evidence from Deliberative Polls.” Journal of Politics, 75: 80–95. (Scholar)
- List, C. and P. Pettit, 2002, “Aggregating Sets of Judgments: An Impossibility Result.” Economics and Philosophy, 18(1): 89–110. (Scholar)
- –––, 2004, “Aggregating Sets of Judgments: Two Impossibility Results Compared.” Synthese, 140: 207–235. (Scholar)
- May, K. O., 1952, “A set of independent, necessary and sufficient conditions for simple majority decision.” Econometrica, 20: 680–684.
- –––, 1954, “Intransitivity, Utility, and the Aggregation of Preference Patterns.” Econometrica, 22: 1–13. (Scholar)
- McConway, K. J., 1981, “Marginalization and Linear Opinion Pools.” Journal of the American Statistical Association, 76: 410–414. (Scholar)
- McLean, I., 1990, “The Borda and Condorcet principles: Three medieval applications.” Social Choice and Welfare, 7: 99–108. (Scholar)
- McLean, I. and F. Hewitt (eds.), 1994, Condorcet: Foundations of Social Choice and Political Theory. Cheltenham: Edward Elgar Publishing. (Scholar)
- McLean, I. S., A. McMillan, and B. L. Monroe, 1995, “Duncan Black and Lewis Carroll.” Journal of Theoretical Politics, 7: 107–123. (Scholar)
- ––– (eds.), 1996, A Mathematical Approach to Proportional Representation: Duncan Black on Lewis Carroll. Dordrecht: Kluwer. (Scholar)
- McLean, I. and A. B. Urken (eds.), 1995, Classics of Social Choice. Ann Arbor: University of Michigan Press. (Scholar)
- Miller, D., 1992, “Deliberative Democracy and Social Choice.” Political Studies, 40 (special issue): 54–67. (Scholar)
- Miller, M. K. and D. Osherson, 2009, “Methods for distance-based judgment aggregation.” Social Choice and Welfare, 32: 575–601. (Scholar)
- Monjardet, B., 2005, “Social choice theory and the ‘Centre de Mathématique Sociale’: some historical notes.” Social Choice and Welfare, 25: 433–456. (Scholar)
- Mongin, P., 1995, “Consistent Bayesian aggregation.” Journal of Economic Theory, 66: 313–351. (Scholar)
- –––, 1997, “Spurious Unanimity and the Pareto Principle.” Paper presented at the Conference on Utilitarianism, New Orleans, March 1997. [Mongin 1997 available online (pdf)] (Scholar)
- –––, 2008, “Factoring Out the Impossibility of Logical Aggregation.” Journal of Economic Theory, 141: 100–113. (Scholar)
- Morreau, M., 2010, “It simply does not add up: Trouble with overall similarity.” Journal of Philosophy, 107: 469–490. (Scholar)
- –––, forthcoming, “Theory Choice and Social Choice: Kuhn Vindicated.” Mind. (Scholar)
- Moulin, H., 1980, “On Strategy-Proofness and Single Peakedness.” Public Choice, 35: 437–455. (Scholar)
- –––, 2004, Fair Division And Collective Welfare. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. (Scholar)
- Mueller, D. C., 2003, Public Choice III. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. (Scholar)
- Nehring, K., 2003, “Arrow's theorem as a corollary.” Economics Letters, 80: 379–382. (Scholar)
- Nehring, K. and C. Puppe, 2002, “Strategyproof Social Choice on Single-Peaked Domains: Possibility, Impossibility and the Space Between.” Unpublished manuscript, University of California at Davis. (Scholar)
- –––, 2007, “The structure of strategy-proof social choice—Part I: General characterization and possibility results on median spaces.” Journal of Economic Theory, 135: 269–305. (Scholar)
- –––, 2010, “Abstract Arrovian Aggregation.” Journal of Economic Theory, 145: 467–494. (Scholar)
- Okasha, S., 2009, “Individuals, groups, fitness and utility: multi-level selection meets social choice theory.” Biology and Philosophy, 24: 561–584. (Scholar)
- –––, 2011, “Theory Choice and Social Choice: Kuhn versus Arrow.” Mind, 120: 83–115. (Scholar)
- Ooghe, E. and L. Lauwers, 2005, “Non-dictatorial extensive social choice.” Economic Theory, 25: 721–743. (Scholar)
- Parfit, D., 1984, Reasons and Persons. Oxford: Oxford University Press. (Scholar)
- Pauly, M. and M. van Hees, 2006, “Logical Constraints on Judgment Aggregation.” Journal of Philosophical Logic, 35: 569–585. (Scholar)
- Pearl, J., 2000, Causality: models, reasoning, and inference. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. (Scholar)
- Pettit, P., 2001, “Deliberative Democracy and the Discursive Dilemma.” Philosophical Issues, 11: 268–299. (Scholar)
- Pigozzi, G., 2006, “Belief merging and the discursive dilemma: an argument-based account to paradoxes of judgment aggregation.” Synthese, 152: 285–298. (Scholar)
- Poisson, S. D., 1837, Recherches sur la probabilité des jugements en matière criminelle et en matière civile: précédées des règles générales du calcul des probabilités. (Scholar)
- Rawls, J., 1971, A Theory of Justice. Cambridge/MA: Harvard University Press. (Scholar)
- Regenwetter, M., B. Grofman, A. A. J. Marley, and I. Tsetlin, 2006, Behavioral Social Choice. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. (Scholar)
- Riker, W., 1982, Liberalism against Populism. San Francisco: W.H. Freeman and Co. (Scholar)
- Roberts, K., 1995, “Valued Opinions or Opinionated Values: The Double Aggregation Problem.” Choice, Welfare and Development: A Festschrift in Honour of Amartya Sen. K. Basu, P. K. Pattanaik, and K. Suzumura (eds.), Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 141–165. (Scholar)
- Saari, D. G., 1990, “The Borda dictionary.” Social Choice and Welfare, 7: 279–317. (Scholar)
- Salles, M. (edited with introduction), 2005, “The history of Social Choice.” Special issue, Social Choice and Welfare, 25: 229–564. (Scholar)
- Satterthwaite, M., 1975, “Strategy-proofness and Arrow's conditions: existence and correspondence theorems for voting procedures and social welfare functions.” Journal of Economic Theory, 10: 187–217. (Scholar)
- Sen, A. K., 1966, “A Possibility Theorem on Majority Decisions.” Econometrica, 34: 491–499. (Scholar)
- –––, 1970a, “The Impossibility of a Paretian Liberal.” Journal of Political Economy, 78: 152–157. (Scholar)
- –––, 1970b, Collective Choice and Social Welfare. San Francisco: Holden-Day. (Scholar)
- –––, 1977, “On weights and measures: informational constraints in social welfare analysis.” Econometrica, 45: 1539–1572. (Scholar)
- –––, 1982, Choice, Welfare and Measurement. Oxford: Blackwell. (Scholar)
- –––, 1983, “Liberty and social choice.” Journal of Philosophy, 80: 5–28. (Scholar)
- –––, 1998, “The Possibility of Social Choice.” Nobel lecture, December 8, 1998, Stockholm. [Sen 1998 available online (pdf)] (Scholar)
- Shapley, L. and B. Grofman, 1984, “Optimizing group judgment accuracy in the presence of interdependencies.” Public Choice, 43: 329–343. (Scholar)
- Stegenga, J., 2013, “An impossibility theorem for amalgamating evidence.” Synthese, 190(2): 2391–2411. (Scholar)
- Suppes, P., 2005, “The pre-history of Kenneth Arrow's social choice and individual values.” Social Choice and Welfare, 25: 319–226. (Scholar)
- Thomson, W., 2000, “On the axiomatic method and its recent applications to game theory and resource allocation.” Social Choice and Welfare, 18: 327–386. (Scholar)
- Tsetlin, I., M. Regenwetter, and B. Grofman, 2003, “The Impartial Culture Maximizes the Probability of Majority Cycles.” Social Choice and Welfare, 21: 387–398. (Scholar)
- Vacca, R., 1921, “Opinioni Individuali e Deliberazioni Collettive.” Rivista Internazionale di Filosofia del Diritto,: 52–59. (Scholar)
- Ward, B., 1965, “Majority Voting and Alternative Forms of Public Enterprises.” The Public Economy of Urban Communities. J. Margolis (ed.). Baltimore: Johns Hopkins Press. (Scholar)
- Weymark, J., 2006, “The Normative Approach to the Measurement of Multidimensional Inequality.” Inequality and Economic Integration. F. Farina and E. Savaglio (eds.), London: Routledge, pp. 303–328. (Scholar)
- Wilson, R., 1975, “On the Theory of Aggregation.” Journal of Economic Theory, 10: 89–99. (Scholar)