Skip to main content

Part of the book series: Argumentation Library ((ARGA,volume 35))

Abstract

Virtue theories have lately enjoyed a modest vogue in the study of argumentation, echoing the success of more far-reaching programmes in ethics and epistemology. Virtue theories of argumentation (VTA) comprise several conceptually distinct projects, including the provision of normative foundations for argument evaluation and a renewed focus on the character of good arguers. Perhaps the boldest of these is the pursuit of the fully satisfying argument, the argument that contributes to human flourishing. This project has an independently developed epistemic analogue: eudaimonistic virtue epistemology. Both projects stress the importance of widening the range of cognitive goals beyond, respectively, cogency and knowledge; both projects emphasize social factors, the right sort of community being indispensable for the cultivation of the intellectual virtues necessary to each project. This paper proposes a unification of the two projects by arguing that the intellectual good life sought by eudaimonistic virtue epistemologists is best realized through the articulation of an account of argumentation that contributes to human flourishing.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 84.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    Virtue epistemologists are often distinguished between responsibilists, whose virtues mostly look like Aristotelian character virtues, and reliabilists, whose virtues are less obviously virtue-like: they are reliable cognitive processes (see, for example, Battaly, 2008, 644).

  2. 2.

    For a discussion of dog whistling in the context of VTA, see (Aberdein, 2018, 20).

  3. 3.

    Brogaard credits versions of this view to numerous epistemologists, including Ralph Wedgwood, Tyler Burge, and Christopher Peacocke.

  4. 4.

    At least if “⇒” is understood as encompassing defeasible as well as deductive inference. I follow Dutilh Novaes in broadening MacFarlane’s definition in this manner (Dutilh Novaes, 2015, 590).

References

  • Aberdein, A. (2010). Virtue in argument. Argumentation, 24(2), 165–179.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Aberdein, A. (2018). Virtuous norms for visual arguers. Argumentation, 32(1), 1–23.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Aikin, S. F. (2017). Fallacy theory, the negativity problem, and minimal dialectical adversariality. Cogency, 9(1), 7–19.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bailin, S. (2014). Commentary on: Moira Howes’s “Does happiness increase the objectivity of arguers?”. In D. Mohammed & M. Lewiński (Eds.), Virtues of Argumentation: Proceedings of the 10th International Conference of the Ontario Society for the Study of Argumentation (OSSA), May 22–25, 2013. Windsor, ON: OSSA.

    Google Scholar 

  • Battaly, H. (2008). Virtue epistemology. Philosophy Compass, 3(4), 639–663.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brogaard, B. (2014a). Intellectual flourishing as the fundamental epistemic norm. In J. Turri & C. Littlejohn (Eds.), Epistemic norms: New essays on action, belief, and assertion (pp. 11–31). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Brogaard, B. (2014b). Towards a eudaimonistic virtue epistemology. In A. Fairweather (Ed.), Virtue epistemology naturalized: Bridges between virtue epistemology and philosophy of science (pp. 83–102). Cham: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Brogaard, B. (2014c). Wide-scope requirements and the ethics of belief. In J. Matheson & R. Vitz (Eds.), The ethics of belief: Individual and social (pp. 130–145). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Clark, S. J. (2003). The character of persuasion. Ave Maria Law Review, 1(1), 61–79.

    Google Scholar 

  • Clark, S. J. (2011). What we make matter. Michigan Law Review, 109(6), 849–862.

    Google Scholar 

  • Clark, S. J. (2013). To teach and persuade. Pepperdine Law Review, 39(5), 1371–1399.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cohen, D. H. (2005). Arguments that backfire. In D. Hitchcock & D. Farr (Eds.), The uses of argument (pp. 58–65). Hamilton, ON: OSSA.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cohen, D. H. (2013). Virtue, in context. Informal Logic, 33(4), 471–485.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cohen, D. H., & Miller, G. (2016). What virtue argumentation theory misses: The case of compathetic argumentation. Topoi, 35(2), 451–460.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dutilh Novaes, C. (2014). Virtuous adversariality as a model for philosophical inquiry. Presented at Edinburgh Women in Philosophy Group Spring Workshop on Philosophical Methodologies.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dutilh Novaes, C. (2015). A dialogical, multi-agent account of the normativity of logic. Dialectica, 69(4), 587–609.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Govier, T. (1999). The philosophy of argument. Newport News, VA: Vale Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Grice, P. (1975). Logic and conversation. In P. Cole & J. L. Morgan (Eds.), Syntax and semantics (Vol. 3, pp. 41–58). New York, NY: Academic Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Howes, M. (2014). Does happiness increase the objectivity of arguers? In D. Mohammed & M. Lewiński (Eds.), Virtues of Argumentation: Proceedings of the 10th International Conference of the Ontario Society for the Study of Argumentation (OSSA), May 22–25, 2013. Windsor, ON: OSSA.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hundleby, C. (2013). Aggression, politeness, and abstract adversaries. Informal Logic, 33(2), 238–262.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hursthouse, R., & Pettigrove, G. (2018). Virtue ethics. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy. Stanford, CA: C.S.L.I.

    Google Scholar 

  • MacFarlane, J. (2004). In what sense (if any) is logic normative for thought. Online at https://johnmacfarlane.net/normativity_of_logic.pdf.

  • Noddings, N. (1984). Caring: A feminine approach to ethics and moral education. Berkeley, CA: University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Norlock, K. J. (2014). Receptivity as a virtue of (practitioners of) argumentation. In D. Mohammed & M. Lewiński (Eds.), Virtues of Argumentation: Proceedings of the 10th International Conference of the Ontario Society for the Study of Argumentation (OSSA), May 22–25, 2013. Windsor, ON: OSSA.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rooney, P. (2010). Philosophy, adversarial argumentation, and embattled reason. Informal Logic, 30(3), 203–234.

    Google Scholar 

  • Steenhagen, M. (2016). Against adversarial discussion. Collingwood and British Idealism Studies, 22(1), 87–112.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Andrew Aberdein .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2020 Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Aberdein, A. (2020). Eudaimonistic Argumentation. In: van Eemeren, F., Garssen, B. (eds) From Argument Schemes to Argumentative Relations in the Wild. Argumentation Library, vol 35. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-28367-4_7

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics