Skip to main content
Log in

Must Skepticism Remain Refuted? Inheriting Skepticism with Cavell and Levinas

  • Published:
Topoi Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

This article defends Cavell and Levinas’ view that anti-skeptical arguments cannot attain universal assent. In the first half of the article, I argue that Conant’s reading of Cavell is mistaken in two respects: he ignores Cavell’s inheritance of Kant as well as the differences Cavell emphasizes between external world and other minds skepticism. In the second half of the paper, I examine affinities between Cavell and Levinas’ thought, viz., acknowledging the facticity of the other and their remarks on skepticism. I close the paper by noting three metaphysical and ethical truths that arise from Cavell’s way with skepticism.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. For discussions of, particularly, though not exclusively, modern skepticism see Descartes (1984), Hume (1960), Kant (1929), Peirce (1934), Moore (1993a, 1993b), Heidegger (1962), Austin (1962b), Clarke (1972), Rorty (1979), Burnyeat (1983), Stroud (1984), McGinn (1989), and Williams (1999).

  2. For discussions of skepticism in Levinas and Cavell see Critchley (1992, 2002), Putnam (2002), Hammer (2002), de Vries (2006), Morgan (2007), Overgaard (2007), and Stricker (2012). For discussions of Cavell and skepticism see Stone (2000, 2003), Witherspoon (2002), Minar (2004), Shieh (2006), Franks (2006), Moran (2011/2), Conant (2012), Macarthur (2014), and Bax (2013, 2015). For discussions of Levinas and skepticism see Bernasconi (1991), de Boer (1997), and Davies (2005).

  3. The cardinal difference between Cavell and Kripke’s respective skeptical readings of Wittgenstein is that whereas the latter’s view concerns conforming to rules, the former is worried with making one’s self intelligible to others and working to make sense of others see Kripke (1982) and Cavell (1990, 2005).

  4. For other passages where Cavell discusses Kant see Cavell (1969a, 1969b, 1969c, 1979). For discussions of Kant and Cavell see Franks (2006), Friedlander (2011), and Baz (2015).

  5. For Conant’s remarks on the difference between “varieties” and “variants” of skepticism see Conant (2012), pp. 6–7 footnote 9 and p. 18 footnote 14. One might point out that if one restricts, the variety of skepticism (e.g., Descartes, Kant, etc.) to a certain variant (e.g., perception, language, etc.), then there is nothing paradoxical about the skeptical thesis “it is true that we cannot know”. The problem with this is that restricting claims to know from a question about whether we can know in general to “can we know in this domain” is still a general claim about knowing in that domain. What is paradoxical about the skeptic’s claim that “we cannot know” is that they are making the epistemic claim (“it is true …”) of denying knowledge in general or some domain (“we cannot know …”). This is paradoxical because they are both claiming to know and not know. See Cavell’s remarks on the drive to speak outside of language games (Cavell 1979, pp. 189, 207, 224, 226, 471, 477). I would like to thank an anonymous reviewer for raising this question and stimulating my subsequent response.

  6. Cavell makes similar remarks in relation to moral disagreement (Cavell 1979, Part III) and aesthetic judgments (Cavell 1969c).

  7. See Levinas (1990), Putnam (2002), Charlier (2002), and Morgan (2007), pp. 336–414.

  8. For discussions of the differences between Levinas and Cavell’s interpretations of Descartes see Cavell (2005), de Vries (2006), and Stricker (2012).

  9. Cavell is quoting Levinas (1996b), pp. 136–8.

  10. See Derrida (1991), Irigaray (1986, 1991), and Guenther (2006).

  11. One might object that if a particular form of skepticism is refuted then what sense does it make to say it reappears? One might think that it is better to say the form of skepticism has never been refuted. Or perhaps that it has been refuted and the person expressing the skeptical thesis is confused or wrong. If one takes the first path––arguing that it is better to say no one has refuted the skeptical thesis––then there are one of two problems. First, if it was never been refuted, then skepticism is a genuine intellectual possibility such that it is a live option that we do not know the world. However, this would concede that there is an insight or truth in skepticism and motivate Cavell and Levinas respective projects to articulate that truth. Another problem with taking the first path is that it occludes the possibility that someone is simply wrong or confused (i.e., skepticism has been refuted and someone just does not get it or is stubborn, etc.) Maybe someone is wrong or confused, but maybe not. It is this last possibility, viz., the possibility that the person expressing the skeptical thesis is genuinely experiencing the skeptical as a live problem that motivates Cavell and Levinas’ distinctive concern with the “truth” of (other mind) skepticism, viz., to attend and respond to a unique, separate perspective (i.e., the person experiencing the world as meaningless). I would like to thank an anonymous reviewer for raising this question and stimulating my subsequent response.

  12. I would like to thank an anonymous reader for encouraging me in this direction.

  13. One could tell a more complicated story about Derrida and experience through his critical inheritance of phenomenology, but that would be a different essay. Here I have simply followed Cavell’s presentation of Derrida.

References

  • Austin J (1962a) How to do things with words. Harvard University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Austin J (1962b) Sense and sensibilia. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Bauer N (2015) How to do things with pornography. Harvard University Press, Cambridge

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Bax C (2013) Reading On Certainty through the lens of Cavell: scepticism, dogmatism, and the ‘groundlessness of our believing’. Int J of Philos Stud 21(4):515–533

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bax C (2015) Sceptics, heretics and human grounds: a Cavellian reading of On Certainty. In: Moyal-Sharrock, D, Munz V, and Coliva, A (eds) Mind, language, and action: proceedings of the 36th International Wittgenstein symposium. Walter de Gruyter, Berlin, 271–81

  • Baz A (2015) The sound of bedrock: lines of grammar between Kant, Wittgenstein, and Cavell. Eur J Philos 24(1):607–627

    Google Scholar 

  • Benjamin W (1996) On the program of the coming philosophy. In: Bullock, M and Jennings, M (eds) Selected Writings: Volume 1, 1913–1926, 100–10

  • Bernasconi R (1991) Skepticism in the face of philosophy. In: Bernasconi R, Critchley S (eds) Re-reading Levinas. Indiana University Press, Bloomington, pp 149–161

    Google Scholar 

  • Burnyeat M (ed) (1983) The skeptical tradition. University of California Press, Berkeley

    Google Scholar 

  • Cavell S (1969a) Must we mean what we say? Must we mean what we say?: A book of essays. Cambridge University Press, New York, pp 1–43

    Google Scholar 

  • Cavell S (1969b) The availability of Wittgenstein’s later philosophy. Must we mean what we say?: A book of essays. Cambridge University Press, New York, pp 44–72

    Google Scholar 

  • Cavell S (1969c) Aesthetic problems of modern philosophy. Must we mean what we say?: A book of essays. Cambridge University Press, New York, pp 73–96

    Google Scholar 

  • Cavell S (1969d) Knowing and acknowledging. Must we mean what we say?: A book of essays. Cambridge University Press, New York, pp 238–266

    Google Scholar 

  • Cavell S (1969e) The avoidance of love: a reading of King Lear. Must we mean what we say?: A book of essays. Cambridge University Press, New York, pp 267–353

    Google Scholar 

  • Cavell S (1979) The claim of reason: Wittgenstein, skepticism, morality, and tragedy. Oxford University Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Cavell S (1981) Pursuits of happiness: the Hollywood comedy of remarriage. Harvard University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Cavell S (1987) Disowning knowledge: in seven plays of Shakespeare. Cambridge University Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Cavell S (1988) In quest of the ordinary: lines of skepticism and romanticism. University of Chicago Press, Chicago

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Cavell S (1990) Conditions handsome and unhandsome: the constitution of Emersonian perfectionism. University of Chicago Press, Chicago

    Google Scholar 

  • Cavell S (1994) A pitch of philosophy: autobiographical exercises. Harvard University Press, Cambridge

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Cavell S (1995) Philosophical passages: Wittgenstein, Emerson, Austin, Derrida. Blackwell, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Cavell S (2005) Philosophy the day after tomorrow. Harvard University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Cavell S (2010) Little did I know: excerpts from memory. Stanford University Press, Stanford

    Google Scholar 

  • Cavell S (2022a) Benjamin and Wittgenstein: signals and affinities. In: Bauer N, Crary A, Laugier S (eds) Here and there. Harvard University Press, Cambridge, pp 120–131

    Google Scholar 

  • Cavell S (2022b) Remains to be seen: initial responses to the Arcades Project. In: Bauer N, Crary A, Laugier S (eds) Here and there. Harvard University Press, Cambridge, pp 132–137

    Google Scholar 

  • Cavell S (2022c) Finding words: Adam Phillips’s ordinary language psychoanalysis. In: Bauer N, Crary A, Laugier S (eds) Here and there. Harvard University Press, Cambridge, pp 138–152

    Google Scholar 

  • Cavell S (2022d) Notes mostly about empathy. In: Bauer N, Crary A, Laugier S (eds) Here and there. Harvard University Press, Cambridge, pp 164–180

    Google Scholar 

  • Charlier C (2002) Levinas and the Talmud. In: Critchley S, Bernasconi R (eds) The Cambridge companion to Levinas. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, pp 100–118

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Clarke T (1972) The legacy of skepticism. The J of Philoso 69(20):754–769

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Conant J (2012) Two varieties of skepticism. In: Abel G, Conant J (eds) Rethinking epistemology. Walter De Gruyter, Berlin, pp 1–73

    Google Scholar 

  • Critchley S (1992) The ethics of deconstruction: Derrida and Levinas. Edinburgh University Press, Edinburgh

    Google Scholar 

  • Critchley S (2002) Introduction. In: Critchley S, Bernasconi R (eds) The Cambridge companion to Levinas. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, pp 1–32

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Davies P (2005) Asymmetry and transcendence: on scepticism and first philosophy. Res in Pheno 35:118–140

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • De Boer T (1997) The rationality of transcendence: studies in the philosophy of Emmanuel Levinas. J.C. Gieben, Amsterdam

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • De Vries H (2006) From “ghost in the machine” to “spiritual automaton”: philosophical meditation in Wittgenstein, Cavell, and Levinas. Int J of Philoso of Rel 60(1/3):77–97

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Derrida J (1978) Violence and metaphysics: an essay on the thought of Emmanuel Levinas. Alan Bass (trans) Writing and difference. University of Chicago, Chicago, pp 79–153

    Google Scholar 

  • Derrida J (1988) In: Graff G (ed) Limited inc. Nothwestern University Press, Evanston

    Google Scholar 

  • Derrida J (1991) At this moment in this work here I am. In: Bernasconi R, Critchley S, Berezdivin R (eds) (trans.) Re-reading Levinas. Indiana University Press, Bloomington, pp 11–48

    Google Scholar 

  • Derrida J (2011) In: Lawlor L (ed) Voice and phenomenon: introduction to the problem of the sign in Husserl’s phenomenology. (trans) Northwestern University Press, Evanston

    Google Scholar 

  • Descartes R (1984) Mediations on first philosophy. In: Cottingham J, Stoothoff R, Murdoch D (eds) (trans) The philosophical writings of Descartes, vol II. Cambridge University Press, New York, pp 1–62

    Google Scholar 

  • Diamond C (1991) The realistic spirit: Wittgenstein, philosophy, and the mind. MIT Press, Cambridge

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Diamond C (2008) The difficulty of philosophy and the difficulty of reality. In: Wolfe C (ed) Philosophy and animal life. Columbia University Press, New York, pp 43–89

    Google Scholar 

  • Franks P (2006) The discovery of the other: Cavell, Fichte and skepticism. In: Crary A, Shih S (eds) Reading Cavell. Routledge, New York, pp 166–203

    Google Scholar 

  • Frege G (1950) The foundations of arithmetic: a logico-mathematical enquiry into the concept of number. In: Austin, J (trans) Blackwell, US

  • Friedlander R (2011) Meaning schematics in Cavell’s Kantian reading of Wittgenstein. Rev Int de Philos 65(2):183–199

    Google Scholar 

  • Guenther L (2006) Levinas and the politics of reproduction. State University of New York Press, Albany

    Google Scholar 

  • Hammer E (2002) Stanley Cavell: skepticism, subjectivity, and the ordinary. Polity Press, Malden, MA

    Google Scholar 

  • Heidegger M (1962) Being and time. In: Macquerrie, J and Robinson, E (trans) Harper Perennial, New York

  • Hume D (1960) A treatise of human nature. Clarendon Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Irigaray L (1986) The fecundity of the caress: a reading of Levinas, totality and infinity section IV, B, ‘The Phenomenology of Eros’. In: Cohen R (ed) Face to face with Levinas. State University of New York Press, Albany, pp 231–256

    Google Scholar 

  • Irigaray L (1991) Questions to Emmanuel Levinas: on the divinity of love. In: Bernasconi R, Critchley S, Whitford M (eds) (trans) Re-reading Levinas. Indiana University Press, Bloomington, pp 109–118

    Google Scholar 

  • Kant I (1929) In: Smith N (ed) Critique of pure reason. (trans) Palgrave Pacmillan, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Kripke S (1982) Wittgenstein on rules and private language. Harvard University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Laugier S (2013) In: Ginsburg D (ed) Why we need ordinary language philosophy. (trans) University of Chicago, Chicago

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Levinas E (1969) In: Lingis A (ed) Totality and infinity: an essay on exteriority. (trans) Duquesne University Press, Pittsburgh

    Google Scholar 

  • Levinas E (1978) In: Lingis A (ed) Existence and existents. (trans) Duquesne University Press, Pittsburgh

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Levinas E (1987) Philosophy and the idea of infinity. In: Lingis, A (ed) Collected philosophical papers, 47–59

  • Levinas E (1990) In: Hand S (ed) Difficult freedom: essays on Judaism. (trans) Johns Hopkins University Press, Baltimore

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Levinas E (1996a) Is ontology fundamental? In: Peperzak A, Critchley S, Bernasconi R (eds) Basic philosophical writings. Indiana University Press, Bloomington, pp 1–10

    Google Scholar 

  • Levinas E (1996b) God and philosophy. In: Peperzak A, Critchley S, Bernasconi R (eds) Basic philosophical writings. Indiana University Press, Bloomington, pp 129–148

    Google Scholar 

  • Levinas E (1998) In: Alphonso, Lingis (eds) Otherwise than being or beyond essence. (trans) Duquesne University Press, Pittsburgh

    Google Scholar 

  • Macarthur D (2014) Cavell on skepticism and the importance of not-knowing. Conversations: The J of Cavellian Stud 2(1):2–23

    Google Scholar 

  • McGinn M (1989) Sense and certainty: a dissolution of scepticism. Blackwell, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Minar E (2004) Living with the problem of the other: Wittgenstein, Cavell and other mind scepticism. In: McManus D (ed) Wittgenstein and scepticism. Routledge, London, pp 218–239

    Google Scholar 

  • Moi T (2017) Revolution of the ordinary: literary studies after Wittgenstein, Austin, and Cavell. University of Chicago, Chicago

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Moore G (1993a) A defense of common sense. In: Baldwin T (ed) G.E. Moore: selected writings. Routledge, New York, pp 106–133

    Google Scholar 

  • Moore G (1993b) Proof of an external world. In: Baldwin T (ed) G.E. Moore: selected writings. Routledge, New York, pp 147–170

    Google Scholar 

  • Moran R (2011) /2) Cavell on outsiders and others. Rev Int de Philos 256:239–254

    Google Scholar 

  • Morgan M (2007) Discovering Levinas. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Mulhall S (1994) Stanley Cavell: philosophy’s recounting of the ordinary. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Mulhall S (2001) Inheritance & originality: Wittgenstein, Heidegger, Kierkegaard. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Overgaard S (2007) Wittgenstein and other minds: rethinking subjectivity and intersubjectivity with Wittgenstein, Levinas, and Husserl. Routledge, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Peirce C (1934) The fixation of belief. In: Hartshorne C, Weiss P (eds) Collected papers. pragmatism and pragmaticism, vol 5. Balknap Press, Cambridge, pp 358–387

    Google Scholar 

  • Putnam H (2002) Levinas and Judaism. In: Critchley S, Bernasconi R (eds) The Cambridge companion to Levinas. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, pp 33–62

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Rorty R (1979) Philosophy and the mirror of nature. Princeton University Press, Princeton

    Google Scholar 

  • Russell F (2018) I want to know more about you: on knowing and acknowledging in Chinatown. In: Hagberg G (ed) Stanley Cavell on aesthetic understanding. Palgrave Macmillan, Cham, pp 1–35

    Google Scholar 

  • Russell F (2020) ‘How shall we put ourselves in touch with reality?’: on Baldwin, film, and acknowledgment. Soc Res 87(4):991–1021

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shieh S (2006) The truth of skepticism. In: Crary A, Shieh (eds) Reading Cavell. Routledge, New York, pp 131–165

    Google Scholar 

  • Stone S (2000) On Husserl and Cavellian scepticism. The Philos Q 50(1):1–21

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stone S (2003) Specific and generic objects in Cavell and Thomas Aquinas. Philos and Pheno Res 67(1):48–74

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stricker B (2012) Die ethische Bedeutung des Skeptizismus: Stanley Cavell und Emmanuel Lévinas. Phänomenologische forschungen:127–161

  • Stroud B (1984) The significance of philosophical scepticism. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Williams M (1999) Groundless belief: an essay on the possibility of epistemology. Princeton University Press, Princeton

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Witherspoon E (2002) Houses, flowers, and frameworks: Cavell and Mulhall on the moral of skepticism. Eur J Philos 10(2):196–208

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wittgenstein L, Hacker P, Schulte J (2009) (trans). Wiley-Blackwell, Chichester

Download references

Acknowledgements

I would like to thank Zed Adams, Anita Avramides, Simon Critchley, Juan Carlos González, John Greco, and Joe Milburn for discussing aspects of this paper. Further, I would like to thank the Graduate Faculty Student Senate of the New School for Social Research as well as the Richard J. Bernstein Endowed Prize Fellowship in Philosophy for providing funding that made this research possible.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Alexander Altonji.

Additional information

Publisher’s Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Springer Nature or its licensor (e.g. a society or other partner) holds exclusive rights to this article under a publishing agreement with the author(s) or other rightsholder(s); author self-archiving of the accepted manuscript version of this article is solely governed by the terms of such publishing agreement and applicable law.

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Altonji, A. Must Skepticism Remain Refuted? Inheriting Skepticism with Cavell and Levinas. Topoi 42, 61–72 (2023). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11245-022-09849-3

Download citation

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11245-022-09849-3

Keywords

Navigation