Skip to main content

Regret, Sub-optimality, and Vagueness

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Vagueness and Rationality in Language Use and Cognition

Part of the book series: Language, Cognition, and Mind ((LCAM,volume 5))

Abstract

This paper concerns regret, where regretting is to be understood, roughly, as mourning the loss of a forgone good. My ultimate aim is to add a new dimension to existing debate concerning the internal logic of regret by revealing the significance of certain sorts of cases—including, most interestingly, certain down-to-earth cases involving vague goals—in relation to the possibility of regret in continued endorsement cases. Intuitively, it might seem like, in continued endorsement cases, an agent’s regret (if it is to make sense) must be tied to the idea that the forgone good is no better than the achieved good but is also not fully made up for by the achieved good because the goods are (too) different in kind. But this view is controversial. After describing a challenge to the view, as well as the main features of the debate regarding regret in which it figures, I appeal first to a fanciful case involving a set of ever-better options, and then to a more down-to-earth case involving a vague goal, to develop a defense of the opposing view that, even in continued endorsement cases, mourning the loss of a forgone good need not be tied to the idea that the loss of the good is not fully made up for by the gain of a preferred or incomparable good of a different kind.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

eBook
USD 16.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 16.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 139.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. 1.

    The quoted phrase is borrowed from Tenenbaum and Raffman’s discussion of vague projects in “Vague Projects and the Puzzle of the Self-Torturer” (2012).

  2. 2.

    For some relevant discussion, see, for example, (Williams 1973), (Hurley 1989: Chap. 9), (Stocker 1990: Chap. 8), and (Dancy 1993: Chap. 7).

  3. 3.

    Two goods are fungible if some amount of one figures as a “perfect substitute” for some amount of the other, in the way that, to borrow from Richard Yetter Chappell (2015: 326–7), two ten-dollar bills (typically) figure as a perfect substitute for one twenty-dollar bill.

  4. 4.

    In Nussbaum’s original version, the agent’s “rational principle” is to “maximize her bagel eating” (115).

  5. 5.

    For a way of understanding the optimizing conception of rationality that allows for this, see, for example, (Mintoff 1997: Sect. 4), wherein Mintoff argues that “the optimising theory does not imply…that if one knows there is a better alternative to some action, then one ought not to perform that action” (119).

  6. 6.

    I discuss many cases of the relevant sort in my prior work on temptation and choice over time. The case I will lay out here is a variation on my fun-size cakes case in (Andreou 2014).

  7. 7.

    For interesting discussion concerning the philosophical issues surrounding the idea of vague goals, see (Tenenbaum and Raffman 2012). That discussion provides compelling support for taking cases like the one I am now considering at face value. I will provide some additional support for taking the cases at face value below. Note that, as my parenthetical remark in the text is meant to flag, I think that overindulging can be properly understood as both vague and graded. In a Pea Soup post, Chappell (2016) suggests that goals or ends that are described as vague are usually better understood as simply graded. But his position is controversial (as suggested by some of the responses to his post), and he acknowledges that vague goals may indeed be possible, so considering the significance of vague goals in relation to rational regret is, I think, still very much in order.

  8. 8.

    In particular, knowing (for some given n and n+1) that there are other stopping points available does not eliminate or reverse your preference for eating a total of n+1 chips over eating a total of n chips, even if it complicates matters given that, as will become apparent, this preference combines with your preferences over other pairs of options in a way that can leave you stumped about where to stop.

  9. 9.

    For some relevant distinctions and reasoning, see Andreou (2007, 2015).

References

  • Andreou, C. (2016). Cashing out the money-pump argument. Philosophical Studies, 173, 1451–1455.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Andreou, C. (2015). The real puzzle of the self-torturer: Uncovering a new dimension of instrumental rationality. Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 45, 562–575.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Andreou, C. (2014). Temptation, resolutions, and regret. Inquiry, 57(3), 275–292.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Andreou, C. (2007). There are preferences and then there are preferences. In B. Montero & M. D. White (Eds.), Economics and the Mind (pp. 115–126). New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chappell, R. Y. (2016). Do we have vague projects? Pea Soup: Philosophy, Ethics, Academia. http://www.peasoup.us/2016/08/do-we-have-vague-projects/.

  • Chappell, R. Y. (2015). Value receptacles. Noûs, 49(2), 322–332.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dancy, J. (1993). Moral Reasons. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hurka, T. (1996). Monism, pluralism, and rational regret. Ethics, 106(3), 555–575.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hurley, S. (1989). Natural reasons. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mintoff, J. (1997). Slote on rational dilemmas and rational supererogation. Erkenntnis, 46(1), 111–126.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nussbaum, M. C. (1986). The fragility of goodness. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pollock, J. L. (1983). How do you maximize expectation value? Noûs, 17(3), 409–421.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stocker, M. (1990). Plural and conflicting values. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tenenbaum, S., & Raffman, D. (2012). Vague projects and the puzzle of the self-torturer. Ethics, 123, 86–112.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Williams, B. (1973). Ethical consistency. Problems of the Self. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

My thanks to Richard Dietz, Dan Lassiter, Mariam Thalos, and Mike White for helpful feedback on earlier drafts of this paper. I am also grateful for the helpful anonymous comments I received and for supporting research funds from the University of Utah and from the Charles H. Monson Esteemed Scholar Award.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Chrisoula Andreou .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2019 Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Andreou, C. (2019). Regret, Sub-optimality, and Vagueness. In: Dietz, R. (eds) Vagueness and Rationality in Language Use and Cognition. Language, Cognition, and Mind, vol 5. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-15931-3_4

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-15931-3_4

  • Published:

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Cham

  • Print ISBN: 978-3-030-15930-6

  • Online ISBN: 978-3-030-15931-3

  • eBook Packages: Social SciencesSocial Sciences (R0)

Publish with us

Policies and ethics