Skip to main content
Log in

Rawls, Sartre, and the Question of Camaraderie

  • Published:
Studies in Philosophy and Education Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

In his classic text, A Theory of Justice, John Rawls argues that the structural principles of a society are just when they issue from a procedure that is fair. One crucial feature that makes the procedure fair is that the persons who will be subjected to these principles choose them after they have deliberated together in a condition marked by a certain balance of knowledge and ignorance. In particular, these people know enough to consider principles that are workable, yet converse behind a “veil of ignorance,” unable to predict what their place in society will be and hence discouraged from slanting the principles toward any preferential interests. My paper questions whether this attempt to ensure the disinterestedness of the conversation of justice is feasible. I worry that when we approach this question practically, we discover that the education that furnishes us with the knowledge necessary to choose viable principles must at the same time preclude genuine ignorance about our social position and interests. As an alternative, I suggest that we convene the conversation of justice behind a “veil of existence.” In this condition, people possess knowledge about how their society works and even about their places in it; however, this knowledge does not foster preferential interests because all interests are subjected to the question of their existential meaning. As Jean-Paul Sartre explains in his essay, “Existentialism is a Humanism,” for our interests to be truly meaningful, they must be affirmed as free responses to our thrownness into existence. Yet how do we find the wherewithal to make such responsible choices rather than lapse into paralysis before their essentially arbitrary differences? My positive thesis is that we may do so by acknowledging how all of us in this existential predicament critically and mutually provoke each to commit oneself to depart from the others in specific ways. This process of provocation is thus educational. It broaches a conception of non-instrumental, non-mimetic, liberal study, one which I try to enact in a writing that employs direct address, regular returns to questions that put discourse at a loss, and expanding webs of association. In this manner, I hope to demonstrate that liberal study may deepen our appreciation of our communal nature, our camaraderie, and thus motivate us to participate unselfishly in the conversation of justice.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

References

  • Buck-Morss, S. (2010). The second time as farce…. Historical pragmatics and the untimely present. In S. Zizek (Ed.), The idea of communism (pp. 67–80). London: Verso.

    Google Scholar 

  • Emerson, R. W. (1983). The divinity school address. In J. Porte (Ed.), Essays and lectures (pp. 73–92). New York: Literary Classics of the United States.

    Google Scholar 

  • Felman, S. (1987). Jacques Lacan and the adventure of insight: Psychoanalysis in contemporary culture. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jackson, P. W. (1986). The mimetic and the transformative: Alternative outlooks on teaching. In The practice of teaching (pp. 115–145). New York: Teachers College Press.

  • Kierkegaard, S. (1983). Fear and trembling (H. V. Hong & E. H. Hong, Trans.). Princeton: Princeton University Press.

  • Lyotard, J.-F. (1988). The differend: Phrases in dispute (G. V. D. Abbeele, Trans.). Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.

  • McClintock, R. (1971). Toward a place for study in a world of instruction. Teachers College Record, 73(2), 161–205.

    Google Scholar 

  • Oakeshott, M. (1989). A place of learning. In T. Fuller (Ed.), The voice of liberal learning: Michael Oakeshott on education (pp. 17–42). New Haven: Yale University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rawls, J. (1971). A theory of justice. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rivette, J. (2001). Secret defense, DVD. Chatworth, CA: Image Entertainment.

    Google Scholar 

  • Salinger, J. D. (1961). Franny and Zooey. Boston: Little, Brown and Company.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sartre, J.-P. (2007). Existentialism is a humanism (C. Macomber, Trans.). New Haven: Yale University Press.

  • Taylor, C. (1989). Sources of the self: The making of the modern identity. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Whitman, W. (1958). Song of myself. In Leaves of grass (pp. 49–96). New York: The New American Library.

Download references

Acknowledgments

In addition to the editors, I would like to thank Erika Goble, Nigel Tubbs, and Rachel Wahl for helpful comments on earlier drafts of this essay.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to René V. Arcilla.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Arcilla, R.V. Rawls, Sartre, and the Question of Camaraderie. Stud Philos Educ 32, 491–502 (2013). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11217-012-9345-0

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11217-012-9345-0

Keywords

Navigation