Skip to main content
Log in

Justification as a loaded notion

  • Published:
Synthese Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

The problem of skepticism is often understood as a paradox: a valid argument with plausible premises whose conclusion is that we lack justification for perceptual beliefs. Typically, this conclusion is deemed unacceptable, so a theory is offered that posits conditions for justification on which some premise is false. The theory defended here is more general, and explains why the paradox arises in the first place. Like Strawson’s (Introduction to logical theory, Wiley, New York, 1952) “ordinary language” approach to induction, the theory posits something built into the very notion of justification: it is loaded with a bias towards the proposition that we are not massively deceived. Beyond the paradox, remaining skeptical problems consist of metaphysical and practical questions: whether we are massively deceived, or why we should use our loaded notion rather than some other. Such challenges have profound epistemological significance, but they are not problems that an a priori theory of justification can solve.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. The term ‘notion’ is intended to be synonymous with ‘concept’ while carrying a salient implication—especially in the context of a discussion of skepticism—that the thing of which we have a notion may not actually exist. See Merriam Webster’s Dictionary of Synonyms for an explanation of the subtle differences between ‘notion’, ‘concept’, and some other related terms.

  2. On the relation between closure and underdetermination, see Brueckner (1994), Cohen (1998), Vogel (2004), and Pritchard (2005).

  3. See Bergmann (2000) on externalist, and Schiffer (2004) on contextualist solutions to the paradox.

  4. I use italics for emphasis, to introduce a new term, and, in other cases, such as this, to denote the notion expressed by the italicized term.

  5. See, for example, Putnam (1981) for an a priori argument for ~(sk). Peacocke (2004) seems to consider inference to the best explanation approaches to be a priori, while Alston (1993) refers to such arguments as “empirical.” See Vogel (2005) and Fumerton (2005) for further discussion.

  6. For example, Alston (1986) and Pryor (2004).

  7. Alston (1993) surveys many of these difficulties.

  8. For example, Avnur (2012).

  9. For example, Pryor (2004).

  10. See Cohen (2016) and Alston (2005) for critical discussion of various attempts to explain ‘epistemic’. Also see Wright (2014) for a defense of the view that some sorts of “pragmatic” justification have direct relevance to the epistemic justification at issue in skepticism.

  11. There is another, Wittgenstein-inspired approach to the paradox, recently termed ‘hinge epistemology” (see Coliva and Moyal-Sharrock 2016; Avnur 2018 for some discussions), according to which propositions that are relevantly like ~sk (“hinge” propositions) get special treatment by our general epistemic principles. On this view, the way we use the notion of justification implies that it cannot apply to ~sk. It is not clear to me how exactly this relates to the claim, defended here, that justification favors ~sk. One might think that hinge epistemology does not posit a bias in favor of ~sk (thanks to Annalisa Coliva for helpful discussion here). Rather, on such views, it makes no sense at all to assess whether or not belief that ~sk is justified; ~sk is entirely left out of the picture. If so, then the theory developed here is an alternative to a hinge epistemological, Wittgenstein-inspired approach to justification. Two important developments of the “hinge” approach to the paradox are Coliva (2015) and Pritchard (2016). I myself have defended this kind of view in Avnur (2012). One advantage of developing the loadedness approach I favor here is that most other theories of justification can be seen as versions of loadedness, but not of hinge epistemology. So, loadedness should have broader appeal.

  12. Thanks to an anonymous referee for pressing this point.

  13. Cohen cites Strawson in a footnote there, but doesn’t explicitly detail the connection.

  14. This idea is inspired by Brandom (2000, pp. 69–71), though we need not buy into his inferentialism about concepts in order to accept this way of understanding loadedness. Lange (2008) critically discusses a similar interpretation of Strawson’s ordinary language solution to induction.

  15. See McCullagh (2011) for an alternative version of inferentialism, which does not require endorsement of any inference as a necessary condition on concept possession.

  16. Of course, loading the notion of justification, even in this externalist way, does not make our perceptual beliefs true or objectively probably true. In a world in which sk is true, this externalist sort of loaded notion will have no extension, presumably. So, such a strategy does not answer the question whether sk is true, or whether our perceptual beliefs are generally or probably true. Rather, it shows that our notion of justification does not commit us to a paradox or contradiction, which is what the skeptical paradox challenges us to do. Below, in Sects. 4 and 5, I address the relation of this challenge to the challenge of establishing whether, in fact, our perceptual beliefs are objectively likely to be true.

  17. For example, Silins (2005) holds that, while our perceptual justification is immediate, we also have default justification to believe ~sk.

  18. Thanks to Dustin Locke for helpful discussion on this point.

  19. What follows is a brief discussion of Goldman’s view, as an example of a theory according to which justification is loaded. The idea that what we believe about things determines the meaning of term we use to refer to them needs more discussion than can be offered here for a full defense. A major issue is how to decide which beliefs about a thing determine the meaning of the relevant term. Admittedly, on the way of understanding loadedness under discussion, this will be a major commitment and so the details will be important. For one recent approach to this question, applies to the problem of free will, see Turner (2013, section 3) on ‘conceptions’.

  20. See Wright (2007) for discussion of the distinction between having and claiming justification, or warrant, for a belief in the context of Moore’s “proof” of an external world.

  21. This is often discussed in terms of “transmission-failure” or “epistemic circularity,” which divides dogmatists (or “liberals”) and conservatives. Wright (2002) and Pryor (2004) are the classic examples of conservative and liberal views on transmission failure, respectively. Wright’s (2004) version of the view concerns the broader notions of “acceptance” and “trust,” instead of belief, but he is widely interpreted to hold that the relevant beliefs have a default warrant. There is also a third option, sometimes called ‘Moderatism’ (a term coined by Coliva 2012) which is defended in Avnur (2012) and Coliva (2012). This involves rejecting (2) in the paradox. The idea that justification is a loaded notion is neutral on all of these debates, and yet it still can explain why the inference from a simple perceptual premise to ~sk seems to fail (even if on reflection, we decide that it does not fail).

  22. I have in mind both classic a priori approaches such as Descartes (1990) or Putnam (1981), as well as appeals to substantive principles concerning explanation, such as BonJour and Sosa (2003) and Vogel (2005).

  23. One might think that, since justification is loaded with a bias towards ~sk, it is the wrong notion to use when evaluating the skeptical argument, which crucially involves ~sk. Why do epistemologists use such a notion, given their aims? Answer: the argument concerns justification. Appealing to our loaded notion of justification is not an option that epistemologists choose when confronting the paradox. Rather, the paradox, or skeptical argument, is about our notion of justification, which is loaded with a bias towards ~sk.

  24. This is exactly what happens when Goldman and Cohen theorize, as we’ve seen above.

  25. Above, I noted the most obvious exceptions to this, namely those who present an a priori argument for ~sk. They do not attempt to solve the paradox by appealing to a theory of justification. Many, though, are not in this camp. This includes some externalists, such as Goldman (1986, 1993) since even on that account, what counts as a “normal world,” or what assumptions we make about which faculties are reliable, while knowable from the armchair, does not constitute an argument that ~sk is true. This point is made by Stich (1990, p. 95). Beyond discussion of Goldman, Stitch call theories of justification as I am understanding them “analytic epistemology,” and his discussion is similar to this one in some ways, though the aim is different (Stitch 1990, pp. 91–93).

  26. Alston (1993) reaches a similar conclusion.

References

  • Alston, W. P. (1986). Epistemic circularity. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 47(1), 1–30.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Alston, W. P. (1993). The reliability of sense perception. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Alston, W. (2005). Beyond justification: Dimensions of epistemic evaluation. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Avnur, Y. (2012). Closure reconsidered. Philosophers’ Imprint, 12(9), 1–16.

    Google Scholar 

  • Avnur, Y. (2018). Review of Annalisa Coliva, Danièle Moyal-Sharrock: Hinge epistemology. Philosophical Investigations, 41(3), 366–370.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bergmann, M. (2000). Externalism and skepticism. Philosophical Review, 109(2), 159–194.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • BonJour, L. (1998). Defense of pure reason. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • BonJour, L., & Sosa, E. (2003). Epistemic justification: Internalism vs. externalism, foundations vs. virtues. Hoboken: Blackwell Pub.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brandom, R. (2000). Articulating reasons: An introduction to inferentialism. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brueckner, A. (1994). The structure of the skeptical argument. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 54(4), 827–835.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cohen, S. (1998). Two kinds of skeptical argument. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 58(1), 143–159.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cohen, S. (2010). Bootstrapping, defeasible reasoning, and a priori justification. Philosophical Perspectives, 24(1), 141–159.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cohen, S. (2016). Theorizing about the epistemic. Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy, 59(7–8), 839–857.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Coliva, A. (2012). Moore’s Proof, liberals, and conservatives: Is there a (Wittgensteinian) third way? In C. Wright & A. Coliva (Eds.), Mind, meaning, and knowledge: Themes from the philosophy of Crispin Wright. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Coliva, A. (2015). Extended rationality: A hinge epistemology. Basingstoke: Palgrave-Macmillan.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Coliva, A., & Moyal-Sharrock, D. (Eds.). (2016). Hinge epistemology. Leiden: Brill.

    Google Scholar 

  • Descartes, R. (1990). Descartes: Selected philosophical writings. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dogramaci, S. (2012). Reverse engineering epistemic evaluations. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 84(3), 513–530.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dummett, M. (1973). Frege: Philosophy of language. London: Duckworth.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fumerton, R. (2005). The challenge of refuting skepticism. In S. Matthias & S. Ernest (Eds.), Contemporary debates in epistemology (pp. 85–97). Hoboken: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Goldman, A. I. (1986). Epistemology and cognition. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Goldman, A. I. (1993). Epistemic folkways and scientific epistemology. Philosophical Issues, 3, 271–285.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kripke, S. A. (1980). Naming and necessity. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lange, M. (2008). Hume and the problem of induction. In D. Gabbay, S. Hartmann, & J. Woods (Eds.), Handbook of the history and philosophy of logic, vol. 10: Inductive logic. Hoboken: Elsevier. (forthcoming).

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. (1972). How to define theoretical terms. Journal of Philosophy, 67, 427–446.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McCullagh, M. (2011). How to use a concept you reject. Philosophical Quarterly, 61(243), 293–319.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Peacocke, C. (2004). The realm of reason. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Plantinga, A. (1993). Warrant: The current debate. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Pritchard, D. (2005). The structure of sceptical arguments. Philosophical Quarterly, 55(218), 37–52.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pritchard, D. (2016). Epistemic angst: Radical skepticism and the groundlessness of our believing. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Pryor, J. (2000). The skeptic and the dogmatist. Noûs, 34(4), 517–549.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pryor, J. (2004). What’s wrong with Moore’s argument? Philosophical Issues, 14(1), 349–378.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Putnam, H. (1962). It ain’t necessarily so. Journal of Philosophy, 59(22), 658–671.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Putnam, H. (1981). Reason, truth, and history. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Ramsey, F. P. (1929). Theories. In R. B. Braithwaite (Ed.), Foundations of mathematics (1931). London: Routledge and Kegan Paul.

    Google Scholar 

  • Salmon, W. C. (1957). Should we attempt to justify induction? Philosophical Studies, 8(3), 33–48.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schafer, K. (2014). Doxastic planning and epistemic internalism. Synthese, 191(12), 2571–2591.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schiffer, S. (2004). Skepticism and the vagaries of justified belief. Philosophical Studies, 119(1–2), 161–184.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Silins, N. (2005). Deception and evidence. Philosophical Perspectives, 19(1), 375–404.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Skyrms, B. (1975). Choice and chance: An introduction to inductive logic. Co: Dickenson Pub.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stitch, S. (1990). The fragmentation of reason: Preface to a pragmatic theory of cognitive evaluation. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Strawson, P. F. (1952). Introduction to logical theory. New York: Wiley.

    Google Scholar 

  • Turner, J. (2013). (Metasemantically) Securing free will. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 91(2), 295–310.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Unger, P. K. (1984). Philosophical relativity. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Vogel, J. (2004). Skeptical arguments. Philosophical Issues, 14(1), 426–455.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Vogel, J. (2005). The refutation of skepticism. In S. Matthias & S. Ernest (Eds.), Contemporary debates in epistemology (pp. 72–84). Hoboken: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • White, R. (2006). Problems for dogmatism. Philosophical Studies, 131(3), 525–557.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wright, C. (2002). (Anti-)sceptics simple and subtle: G. E. Moore and John McDowell. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 65(2), 330–348.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wright, C. (2004). Warrant for nothing (and foundations for free)? Aristotelian Society Supplementary, 78(1), 167–212.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wright, C. (2007). The perils of dogmatism. In S. Nuccetelli & G. Seay (Eds.), Themes from G. E Moore: New essays in epistemology. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wright, C. (2014). On epistemic entitlement (II): Welfare state epistemology. In D. Dodd & E. Zardini (Eds.), Scepticism and perceptual justification (pp. 213–247). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

For comments and discussion over many years on various versions of this paper, I would like to thank David James Barnett, Paul Boghossian, Annalisa Coliva, Kit Fine, Dustin Locke, James Pryor, Karl Schafer, Stephen Schiffer, Dion Scott-Kakures, and Rivka Weinberg, as well as other participants at a Skepticism conference at UC Irvine, the New Perspectives on External World Scepticism conference at the Munich Centre for Mathematical Philosophy, the European Epistemology Network Conference in Bologna, Italy, a seminar at New York University, and a Work in Progress seminar at the Claremont Colleges.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Yuval Avnur.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Avnur, Y. Justification as a loaded notion. Synthese 198, 4897–4916 (2021). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-019-02375-7

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-019-02375-7

Keywords

Navigation