Skip to content
Licensed Unlicensed Requires Authentication Published online by De Gruyter April 13, 2024

A Chrysippean Modality

  • D. T. J. Bailey EMAIL logo

Abstract

In this paper, I attempt to explain one of the most controversial views attributed to the Stoic Chrysippus: that the impossible can follow from the possible. My solution finds in Chrysippus a distinction later made by the medieval logician John Buridan: that between being possible (there being a state of affairs that may occur) and being possibly-true (there being some proposition whose truth-conditions are that state of affairs). Buridan and Chrysippus have radically opposing views on the nature of propositions. What their conceptions share is the conclusion that at least some propositions must be contingent beings. They argue for this while maintaining a rigorous commitment to the view that propositions are strictly bivalent. In 2. I explain the Chrysippean passage in terms of a distinction Buridan makes explicitly. In 3. I show how the distinction follows implicitly from the Stoic theory of quantification. In 4. I compare the modality with other aspects of Stoic logic. In 5. I discuss how the distinction behaves in the future tense.

Acknowledgement

Many thanks to Yuval Avnur, Tyler Huismann, and the anonymous referees for the Archiv.

Bibliography

D. L. Hicks, R. 1925. Diogenes Laertius: Lives of Eminent Philosophers. The Loeb Classical Library 184–185. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.10.4159/DLCL.diogenes_laertius-lives_eminent_philosophers_book_x_epicurus.1925Search in Google Scholar

L&S Long, A. A. and Sedley, D. 1987. The Hellenistic Philosophers. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.10.1017/CBO9780511808050Search in Google Scholar

FDS Hülser, K. 1987–1988. Die Fragmente zur Dialektik der Stoiker. Neue Sammlung der Texte mit deutscher Übersetzung und Kommentaren. Stuttgart: Frommann-Holzboog.Search in Google Scholar

S. E. Bett, R. 2005. Sextus Empiricus: Against the Logicians. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.10.1017/CBO9780511815232Search in Google Scholar

SVF von Arnim, J. 1903–1924. Stoicorum veterum fragmenta. Leipzig: Teubner.Search in Google Scholar

Bailey, D. T. J. 2008. ‘Excavating Dissoi Logoi 4.’ Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 35, 249–264.10.1093/oso/9780199557790.003.0008Search in Google Scholar

Baldwin, T. 1979. ‘Interpretations of Quantifiers.’ Mind 88(350), 215–240.10.1093/mind/LXXXVIII.1.215Search in Google Scholar

Barnes, J. 2007. Truth, etc.: Six Lectures on Ancient Logic. Oxford/New York: Clarendon Press /Oxford University Press.Search in Google Scholar

—. 2012. ‘The Logical Investigations of Chrysippus.’ In M. Bonelli (ed.), Logical Matters. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 485–498.Search in Google Scholar

—. 2012. ‘Cicero on Logic.’ In M. Bonelli (ed.), Logical Matters. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 23–42.Search in Google Scholar

Bobzien, S. 1993. ‘Chrysippus’ Modal Logic and Its Relation to Philo and Diodorus.’ In K. Döring and T. Ebert (eds.), Dialektiker und Stoiker: Zur Logik der Stoa und ihrer Vorläufer. Symposium zur Logik der Stoiker und ihrer Vorläufer: Stuttgart: Franz Steiner Verlag, 63–84.Search in Google Scholar

—. 2021. ‘Frege Plagiarized the Stoics.’ In F. Leigh (ed.), Themes in Plato, Aristotle, and Hellenistic Philosophy, Keeling Lectures 2011–2018. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 149–206.Search in Google Scholar

Buridan, J. 1982. John Buridan on Self-reference: Chapter Eight of Buridan’s Sophismata. Ed. and trans. G. E. Hughes. Cambridge  /New York: Cambridge University Press.Search in Google Scholar

Bronowski, A. 2019. The Stoics on Lekta: All There is to Say. Oxford: Oxford University Press.10.1093/oso/9780198842880.001.0001Search in Google Scholar

De Lacy, P. 1978. Galen: On the Doctrines of Hippocrates and Plato. Berlin: Akademie-Verlag.Search in Google Scholar

Frege, G. [1918] 1997. ‘Thought.’ In M. Beaney (ed.). The Frege Reader. Oxford: Blackwell Publishers, 325–345.Search in Google Scholar

Hülser, K. 2012. ‘Pragmatics and the Idea of the Illocutionary in Stoic Language Theory.’ In R. Edmondson and K. Hülser (eds.), Politics of Practical Reasoning: Integrating Action, Discourse and Argument. Plymouth: Lexington Books, 39–64.Search in Google Scholar

Marrone, L. 1988. ‘Il mentitore nel PHerc. 307 (Questioni logiche di Crisippo).’ In B. G. Mandilavas (ed.), Proceedings of the 18th International Congress of Papyrology, vol. I. Athens: Greek Papyrlogical Society, 271–276.Search in Google Scholar

—. 1997. ‘Le Questioni Logiche di Crisippo (PHerc 307).’ Cronache Ercolanesi 27, 83–100.Search in Google Scholar

Nolan, D. 2016. ‘Stoic Trichotomies.’ Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 51, 207–230.10.1093/acprof:oso/9780198795797.003.0006Search in Google Scholar

Nuchelmans, G. 1973. Theories of the Proposition: Ancient and Medieval Conceptions of the Bearers of Truth and Falsity. Amsterdam: North-Holland Pub. Co.Search in Google Scholar

Prior, A. N. 1967. Past, Present and Future. Oxford: Clarendon Press.10.1093/acprof:oso/9780198243113.001.0001Search in Google Scholar

Quine, W. V. 1960. Word and Object. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Search in Google Scholar

Williamson, T. 2002. ‘Necessary Existents.’ In A. O’Hear (ed.), Logic, Thought and Language. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 233–251.10.1017/S1358246100008158Search in Google Scholar

Published Online: 2024-04-13

© 2024 Walter de Gruyter GmbH, Berlin/Boston

Downloaded on 21.5.2024 from https://www.degruyter.com/document/doi/10.1515/agph-2023-0052/html
Scroll to top button