Skip to main content
Log in

Focus on numbers

  • Published:
Linguistics and Philosophy Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

This paper contributes to the debate over the so-called “easy argument for numbers”, an argument that uses evidence from natural language to support the metaphysically significant claim that numbers exist. It presents novel data showing that critical examples in the literature are ambiguous between two readings, contrary to previous assumptions. It then accounts for these data using independently motivated linguistic theory. The account developed rescues the easy argument from the primary challenges leveled against it in the literature and sets the agenda for future work to determine whether or not the argument is valid.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

References

  • Bach, E. (1986). Natural language metaphysics. In R. Barcan Marcus, G. J. W. Dorn, & P. Weingartner (Eds.), Logic, methodology and philosophy of science VII, Studies in logic and the foundations of mathematics (Vol. 114, pp. 573–595). Amsterdam: North Holland.

  • Balcerak Jackson, B. (2013). Defusing easy arguments for numbers. Linguistics and Philosophy, 36(6), 447–461.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Balcerak Jackson, B. (2014). What does displacement explain, and what do congruence effects show? A response to Hofweber (2014). Linguistics and Philosophy, 37(3), 269–274.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bar-Hillel, Y. (1967). Review of Fodor and Katz 1964. Language, 43(2), 526–550.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Beaver, D., & Clark, B. (2003). Always and only: Why not all focus-sensitive operators are alike. Natural Language Semantics, 11(4), 323–362.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brogaard, B. (2007). Number words and ontological committment. The Philosophical Quarterly, 57(226), 1–20.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Büring, D. (2007). Semantics, intonation and information structure. In G. Ramchand & C. Reiss (Eds.), The Oxford handbook of linguistic interfaces (pp. 445–474). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Declerk, R. (1988). Studies on copular sentences, clefts, and pseudo-clefts. Louvain: Leuven University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Dummett, M. (1981). Frege: Philosophy of language. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Felka, K. (2014). Number words and reference to numbers. Philosophical Study, 168(1), 261–282.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Féry, C., & Samek-Lodovici, V. (2006). Focus projection and prosodic prominence in nested foci. Language, 82(1), 131–150.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Frege, G. (1884). The foundations of arithmetic: A logical-mathematical investigation into the concept of number. New York: Pearson Longman. Dale Jacquette, trans.

  • Geist, L. (2007). Predication and equation in copular sentences: Russian vs. English. In I. Comorovski & K. von Heusinger (Eds.), Existence: Semantics and syntax, studies in linguistics and philosophy (pp. 79–105). Berlin: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hale, B., & Wright, C. (2001). The Reason’s proper study: Essays toward a Neo-Fregean philosophy of mathematics. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Heycock, C., & Kroch, A. (2002). Topic, focus, and syntactic representations. In L. Mikkelsen & C. Potts (Eds.), WCCFL 21 Proceedings (pp. 141–165). Somerville, MA: Cascadilla Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Higgins, R. F. (1979). The Pseudo-cleft construction in English. New York: Garland.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hofweber, T. (2005). Number determiners, numbers, and arithmetic. Philosophical Review, 114(2), 179–225.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hofweber, T. (2007). Innocent statements and their metaphysically loaded counterparts. Philosophers Imprint, 7(1), 1–33.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hofweber, T. (2014). Extraction, displacement, and focus a reply to Balcerak Jackson (2013). Linguistics and Philosophy, 37(3), 263–267.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hofweber, T. (2016). Ontology and the ambitions of metaphysics. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Krifka, M. (2006). Can focus accenting be eliminated in favor of deaccenting Given constituents? In B. Gyuris, L. Kálmán, C. Piñón, & K. Varasdi (Eds.), Ninth symposium on logic and language (pp. 107–119). Budapest: Hungarian Academy of Sciences & Eötvös Loránd University.

    Google Scholar 

  • Krifka, M. (2007). Basic notions of information structure. In C. Féry, G. Fanselow, & M. Krifka (Eds.), Interdisciplinary studies on information structure (Vol. 6, pp. 13–55). Potsdam: Universitätsverlag Potsdam.

  • Ladd, D. R. (2008). Intonational phonology (2nd ed.). Cambridge: Cambridge Univesity Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Matushansky, O. (2000). The instrument of inversion: Instrumental case in the Russian copula. In R. Billerey & B. D. Lillehaugen (Eds.), Proceedings of the 19th West Coast conference on formal linguistics (pp. 288–301). Somerville, MA: Cascadilla Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mikkelsen, L. (2005). Copular clauses: Specification, predication, and equation. Amsterdam: John Benjamins.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Mikkelsen, L. (2011). Copular clauses. In K. von Heusinger, C. Maienborn, & P. Portner (Eds.), Semantics (pp. 1805–1829). Berlin: De Gruyter Mouton.

    Google Scholar 

  • Moltmann, F. (2013). Reference to numbers in natural language. Philosophical Study, 162(3), 499–536.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Moro, A. (1997). The raising of predicates: Predicative noun phrases and the theory of clause structure. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Partee, B. H. (1986). Ambiguous pseudoclefts with unambiguous be. In S. Berman, J.-W. Choe, & J. McDonough (Eds.), Proceedings of the North East Linguistic Society (NELS) XVI (pp. 354–366).

  • Partee, B. H. (1987). Noun phrase interpretation and type-shifting principles. In J. A. G. Groenendijk, D. de Jongh, & M. J. B. Stokhof (Eds.), Studies in discourse representation theory and the theory of generalized quantifiers (Vol. 8, pp. 115–143). Berlin: Walter de Gruyter.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pelletier, F. J. (2011). Descriptive metaphysics, natural language metaphysics, Sapier-Whorf, and all that stuff: Evidence from the mass-count distinction. In B. H. Partee, M. Glanzberg, & J. Skilters (Eds.), Formal semantics and pragmatics: Discourse, context, and models, volume 6 of The Baltic International Yearbook of Cognition, Logic, and Communication (pp. 1–46).

  • Pierrehumbert, J. B. (1980). The phonology and phonetics of English intonation, Ph.D. thesis. Cambridge: MIT.

  • Roberts, C. (1996/2012). Information structure in discourse: Towards an integrated formal theory of pragmatics. In J. H. Yoon, & A. Kathol (Eds.), Ohio State University Working Papers in linguistics (Vol. 49). Reprinted in the 1998 version with a new Afterword in Semantics and Pragmatics, 5(6), 1–69 (2012).

  • Roberts, C. (2008). Resolving focus. Columbus, OH: Ms., The Ohio State University.

  • Romero, M. (2005). Concealed questions and specificational subjects. Linguistics and Philosophy, 28(6), 687–737.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rooth, M. (1992). A theory of focus interpretation. Natural Language Semantics, 1(1), 75–116.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schlenker, P. (2003). Clausal equations (a note on the connectivity problem). Natural Language and Linguistic Theory, 21(1), 157–214.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schwarzschild, R. (1999). Givenness, AvoidF, and other constraints on the placement of accent. Natural Language Semantics, 7(2), 141–177.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Selkirk, E. O. (1984). Phonology and syntax: The relation between sound and structure. Current Studies in Linguistics. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

  • Snyder, E. (2017). Numbers and cardinalities: What’s really wrong with the easy argument for numbers? Linguistics and Philosophy, 40(4). doi:10.1007/s10988-017-9215-x.

  • Terken, J., & Hirschberg, J. (1994). Deaccentuation and persistence of grammatical function and surface position. Language and Speech, 37(2), 125–145.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Velleman, D., Beaver, D., Destruel, E., Bumford, D., Onea, E., & Coppock, L. (2012). It-clefts are it (inquiry terminating) constructions. In A. Chereches (Ed.), Proceedings of semantics and linguistic theory (SALT) (Vol. 22, pp. 441–460). Ithaka, NY: Cornell University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Yablo, S. (2005). The myth of the seven. In M. Kalderon (Ed.), Fictionalism in metaphysics (pp. 88–115). New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

I would like to thank Craige Roberts and Stewart Shapiro for inviting me to comment on Thomas Hofweber’s paper at the OSU Workshop on the Semantics of Cardinals in the spring of 2014. Commenting on that paper sparked my interest in this topic. I am also grateful to the other participants at that workshop, especially Thomas Hofweber and Stewart Shapiro, for discussion, and to Thomas Hofweber, Craige Roberts, Eric Snyder, and Judith Tonhauser for comments on an earlier draft. Finally, special thanks to Eric Snyder for extensive discussion of these and related issues. Funding was provided by National Science Foundation (Grant No. BCS-0952571).

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Jefferson Barlew.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Barlew, J. Focus on numbers. Linguist and Philos 40, 401–426 (2017). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10988-017-9217-8

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10988-017-9217-8

Keywords

Navigation