Skip to main content
Log in

The machine-organism relation revisited

  • ORIGINAL PAPER
  • Published:
History and Philosophy of the Life Sciences Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

This article addresses some crucial assumptions that are rarely acknowledged when organisms and machines are compared. We begin by presenting a short historical reconstruction of the concept of “machine.” We show that there has never been a unique and widely accepted definition of “machine” and that the extant definitions are based on specific technologies. Then we argue that, despite the concept's ambiguity, we can still defend a more robust, specific, and useful notion of machine analogy that accounts for successful strategies in connecting specific devices (or mechanisms) with particular living phenomena. For that purpose, we distinguish between what we call “generic identity” and proper “machine analogy.” We suggest that “generic identity”—which, roughly stated, presumes that some sort of vague similarity might exist between organisms and machines—is a source of the confusion haunting many persistent disagreements and that, accordingly, it should be dismissed. Instead, we endorse a particular form of “machine analogy” where the relation between organic phenomena and mechanical devices is not generic but specific and grounded on the identification of shared “invariants.” We propose that the machine analogy is a kind of analogy as proportion and we elucidate how this is used or might be used in scientific practices. We finally argue that while organisms are not machines in a generic sense, they might share many robust “invariants,” which justify the scientists' use of machine analogies for grasping living phenomena.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. See, for example, Dijksterhuis (1950; De Solla Price, 1964; Merchant, 1990; Des Chene, 2000; Barryman 2003; Bertoloni Meli 2019; Roudaut 2022 among others).

  2. This is also why we use in this paper the notion of “machine analogy” and not “mechanistic” analogy.

  3. On Descartes' uses of analogies and metaphors, see Galison (1984).

  4. “The view that machines cannot give rise to surprises is due, I believe, to a fallacy to which philosophers and mathematicians are particularly subject. This is the assumption that as soon as a fact is presented to a mind all consequences of that fact spring into the mind simultaneously with it. It is a very useful assumption under many circumstances, but one too easily forgets that it is false”. (Turing, (1950), p. 451). See also Schaffer (1999).  

  5. There is a vast and thriving literature addressing the notion (or notions) of organism, which is impossible to list here entirely. For a good representative example see Huneman and Wolfe (2010). In this paper, we are not interested in defining the concept of organism, but to explore the way machine analogies reveal (or eventually hide) interesting organic properties. Insofar as we focus on the relation between organisms and machines, and, therefore, on the attempts to understand the former in terms of the latter, our attention is largely devoted to mechanical devices and, more generally, machine analogies.

  6. It would be interesting to have an empirical study listing the different ways most biologists define “machines”. Yet, what most biologists supposedly assume (or don’t) when they formulate machine analogies has no obvious or necessary import on how we should understand “machine analogies” in general. In other words, the fact that biologists might persist in using wrongheaded conceptions of machines does not necessarily undermine all possible uses of machine analogies. Moreover, the biologists' abuses of “machine analogies” would give us further reasons for having more theoretical and historical analyses that might inspire them to use those analogies more effectively.

  7. We are aware that there are many ways to be against machine analogies. There are several persuasive and non-exclusive “antimachinist” arguments that we cannot properly list here. What we are willing to question is not “anti-mechanism” in general (whatever it means). What we are challenging is the argument that if we can find one or more discontinuous properties between machines and organisms, then any kind of machine analogy would be necessarily doomed.

  8. Nicholson (2013), for instance, is pretty clear concerning the fact that machine metaphors can play a heuristic role in science.

  9. Borelli, D’Arcy Thompson, and Istrail et al. could even believe that the artifacts they describe are somewhat “identical” to their epistemic targets. If so, for our perspective, their belief would be philosophically and epistemically flawed. But here we are not concerned with what those figures really believed. We are interested in how machine analogies might work in principle and be epistemically defensible. To the extent that Istrail et al. argue that organisms are just computers, for instance, we consider the claim as an abusive use of a machine analogy.

  10. What we propose here is in the spirit of what Brunet (2021) has recently put forward, namely, that machine analogies can be properly assessed only when specific technologies or machines are compared with specific organic phenomena.

  11. Philosophers can evade this last question in two ways, which are not particularly attractive. They can invent a new formal definition of “machine” and then demonstrate that this notion of “machine” is incompatible (or compatible) with the knowledge we have of living beings. Or they can engage in the desperate empirical and historical hunt for a general definition of machine encompassing all extant technologies in order to show that the organism is (or is not) that kind of abstract machine.

  12. We shall provide another, more caritative, interpretation of Nicholson (2019) in Sect. 5.

  13. That is, due to the fact that R holds between A and B as well as between C and D.

References

  • Ampère, A. M. (1834). Essai sur la philosophie des sciences, ou exposition analytique d’une classification naturelle de toutes les connaissances humaines. Vols. 1–2. Paris, 1834, 1843

  • Aristotle. (1936). Problems (Vol. 1–2). Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Barryman, S. (2003). Ancient automata and mechanical explanation. Phronesis, 48(4), 344–369.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bertoloni, M. D. (2019). Mechanism: A visual, lexical, and conceptual history. Pittsburgh University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Blackiston, D., Lederer, E., Kriegman, S., Garnier, S., Bongard, J., & Levin, M. (2021). A cellular platform for the development of synthetic living machines. Science Robotics, 6, eabf1571.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bongard, J., & Levin, L. (2021). Living things are not (20th Century) machines: Updating mechanism metaphors in light of the modern science of machine behavior. Frontiers in Ecology and Evolution, 9, 650726.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brunet, T. (2021). The machine–organism distinction (Doctoral thesis). https://doi.org/10.17863/CAM.72080

  • Burnett, D. G. (2009). Savage selection: Analogy and elision in on the origins of species. Endeavour, 33, 120–125.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cheng, H.-P., Deumens, E., Freericks, J. K., Li, C., & Sanders, B. A. (2020). Application of quantum computing to biochemical systems: A look to the future. Frontiers in Chemistry, 8, 587143.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • De Solla, P. D. (1964). Automata and the origins of mechanism and mechanistic philosophy. Technology and Culture, 5(1), 9–23.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Des Chene, D. (2000). Spirits and clocks: Machine and organism in Descartes. Cornell University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Des Chene, D. (2016). Automaton. In L. Nolan (Ed.), The Cambridge Descartes lexicon. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Di Pasquale, G. (2020). Le Macchine nel mondo antico. Carocci.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dijksterhuis, E. J. (1950). The mechanization of the world picture. Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dyakonov, M. I. (2019). When will we have a quantum computer? Solid-State Electronics. https://doi.org/10.48550/arXiv.1903.10760

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Galison, P. (1984). Descartes’s comparisons: From the invisible to the visible, ISIS, 75(2), 311–326. https://doi.org/10.1086/353484

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gardner, M. (1958). Logic machines and diagrams. McGraw-Hill.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gildenhuys, P. (2004). Darwin, Herschel, and the role of analogy in Darwin’s origin. Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Science, 35, 593–611.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Harris, J. (1708). Lexicon technicum, or, an universal English dictionary of arts and sciences. Dan Midwinter.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hawthorne, J. (2021). Inductive logic. In Zalta, E. N. (ed.): The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy (Spring 2021 Edition) https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2021/entries/logic-inductive/

  • Hesse, M. (1988). The cognitive claims of metaphor. Journal of Speculative Philosophy, 2(1), 1–16.

    Google Scholar 

  • Holt, L., Holm, S., & Serban, M. (2021). Introduction. In S. Holm & M. Serban (Eds.), Philosophical perspectives on the engineering approach in biology. Living machines? (pp. 1–20). Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Huneman, P., & Wolfe, C. (2010). The concept of organism: Historical philosophical, scientific perspectives. History and Philosophy of the Life Sciences, 32(2–3), 147.

    Google Scholar 

  • Iliadis, A. (2015). Mechanology: Machine typologies and the birth of the philosophy of technology in France (1932–1958). Systema: Connecting Matter, Life, Culture and Technology, 3(1), 131–144.

    Google Scholar 

  • Istrail, S., De-Leon, S., & Davidson, E. (2007). The regulatory genome and the computer. Developmental Biology, 310(2), 187–195.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Koenigs, G. (1903). Introduction a une théorie nouvelle des mechanisme, Paris, A. Hermann.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kriegman, S., Blackiston, D., Levin, M., & Bongard, J. (2020). A scalable pipeline for designing reconfigurable organisms. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences of the United States of America, 117, 1853–1859. https://doi.org/10.1073/pnas.1910837117

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kriegman, S., Blackiston, D., Levin, M., & Bongard, J. (2021). Kinematic self-replication in reconfigurable organisms. PNAS, 118(49), e2112672118.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lafitte, J. (1932). Réflexions sur la science des machines. Vrin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lakoff, G., & Johnson, M. (1980). Metaphors we live by. University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Merchant, C. (1990). The death of nature: Women, ecology and the scientific revolution. Harper & Row.

  • Militello, G., & Moreno, A. (2018). Structural and organisational conditions for being a machine. Biology & Philosophy, 33(5), 1–25.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nicholson, D. (2013). Organisms ≠ Machines. Studies in History and Philosophy of Biology and Biomedical Sciences, 44, 669–678.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nicholson, D. (2019). Is the cell really a machine? Journal of Theoretical Biology, 477, 108–126.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Reuleaux, F. (1876). Kinematics of machinery: Outlines of a theory of machines. London: Macmillan & Co. 

    Google Scholar 

  • Reynolds, A. (2022). Understanding metaphors in the life sciences. Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Roudaut, S. (2022). Clocks, automata, and the mechanization of nature (1300–1600). Philosophies, 7, 139.

  • Ruyer, R. (1954). La cybernétique et l’origine de l’information. Paris Flammarion, 155, 4–6.

  • Schaffer, S. (1999). OK computer. In M. Hagner (Ed.), Ecce Cortex: Beitraege zur Geschichte des modernen Gehirns (pp. 254–285). Wallstein Verlag.

    Google Scholar 

  • Thompson, D. W. (1917). On growth and form. Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Turing, A. (1950). Computing machinery and intelligence. Mind, LIX(236), 433-460

  • Vaccari, A. (2008). Legitimating the machine: The epistemological foundation of technological metaphor in the natural philosophy of René Descartes. In C. Zittel, R. Nanni, G. Engel, & N. Karafyllis (Eds.), Philosophies of technology: Francis Bacon and his contemporaries (2 vols.), (pp. 287-336). Brill.

  • Vitruvius (1914). The ten books on architecture, (R. H. Morgan, transl.). Harvard University Press.

  • Weiss, P. (1973). The science of life: The living system —a system for living. Futura Publishing.

    Google Scholar 

  • White, R. M., Hodge, M. J. S., & Radick, G. (2021). Darwin’s argument by analogy. From artificial to natural selection. Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Wiener, N. (1989). The human use of human beings: Cybernetics and society. Free Association Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wilson, M. (2000). Aristotle’s theory of the unity of science. University of Toronto Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

Download references

Funding

Funding was provided by FCT (Grant No. CEECIND/02290/2018 and Contract Nº DL57/2016/CP1479/CT0064).

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Maurizio Esposito.

Ethics declarations

Conflict of interest

There are no conflicts to declare.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Springer Nature or its licensor (e.g. a society or other partner) holds exclusive rights to this article under a publishing agreement with the author(s) or other rightsholder(s); author self-archiving of the accepted manuscript version of this article is solely governed by the terms of such publishing agreement and applicable law.

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Esposito, M., Baravalle, L. The machine-organism relation revisited. HPLS 45, 34 (2023). https://doi.org/10.1007/s40656-023-00587-2

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s40656-023-00587-2

Keywords

Navigation