1 The problem of defining disability

My goal is to defend a new account of disability: one that is indexed to an account of distributive justice, or what individuals are entitled to. Yet it may seem that determining how disability should be defined needs no further investigation. Most people have a clear sense of which conditions they consider disabling. Further, there is broad philosophical consensus on some central features of an account of disability. First, there is a widely accepted distinction between impairment as physical or cognitive features that cause deviation from a biological or statistical norm of species functioning, and disability as a restriction in our ability to perform tasks.Footnote 1 There is considerable agreement, too, that disability is caused in part by impairment, and in part by an individual’s social and political context, and the resources they have access to.Footnote 2

I do not intend to challenge the consensus on either point. Rather, I ask: if disability is the restriction in our ability to perform tasks, then which inabilities matter? In other words, which of the limitations that result from individuals’ impairments, in combination with their context and resources, should be considered disabling? We are all restricted by our bodies, and are all incapable of performing some tasks, but most of these inabilities are not considered disabilities. An account of disability is an essential prerequisite to formulating public policies that safeguard the just treatment of disabled individuals, and an account cannot form the basis of such policy if it simply concludes that ‘everyone is disabled’. If, then, we are to avoid the category of disability becoming overly broad—and thus politically and practically useless—we need some way of picking out which inabilities are relevant to defining disability. Only then can we identify and respond to the injustice, discrimination, and mistreatment to which so many disabled individuals are subject.

I begin, in Sect. 2, by considering and rejecting alternative accounts of which inabilities are disabling: those entailed by ‘normal’ species functioning (Buchanan et al. 2000; Daniels 1985), those that undermine well-being (Kahane and Savulescu 2009; Savulescu and Kahane 2009), and those considered relevant by disability activists (Barnes 2016a). I demonstrate that the latter approach leaves disability underspecified, whilst on the former two approaches disability will be ubiquitous. As such, all of these alternatives prove an inadequate basis for public policy, political campaigning, or activist movements. I argue, instead, that the relevant opportunity losses involve restrictions of individuals’ entitlements (Sect. 3). Thus, I define disability as the restriction in the ability to perform those tasks human beings are entitled to be able to perform as a matter of justice, as the result of the interaction between an individual’s impairment, their social and political context, and the resources they have available to them. This provides a framework account of disability. To determine whether an impairment is actually disabling will require an account of our distributive entitlements, but this is not a prerequisite to accepting the general claim that individuals are disabled when their access to these entitlements is restricted (as a result of their impairment and context). (As subsequent discussions will illustrate, the case of disability does give us some reason to favour particular accounts of distributive justice over others, but I will not attempt to mount a definitive defence of one particular approach here.)

In Sect. 4 I consider some possible objections to the definition I have sketched. First, it may seem that if being disabled means lacking what we are entitled to, then in cases where this cannot be rectified, this cannot be unjust. This implies individuals with serious impairments would not be considered disabled on my account. Second, in part to avoid the former objection, I adopt a broadly-specified and multiply-realisable conception of entitlements: for example, as opportunities for mobility, communication, or forming relationships. This leaves me vulnerable to the further worry that individuals will not be considered disabled, or entitled to assistance, even when unable to perform important functionings (walking, hearing, easily reading social cues) if they have more general capabilities in these domains. I respond to these objections in Sects. 5 and 6.

I finish, in Sect. 7, by considering the revisionary and counterintuitive implications of my account. It will, for example, imply that individuals with significant and visible impairments may not be disabled by them, that individuals with apparently minor or invisible impairments may be disabled, and that individuals’ status as disabled may change across time and context. However, I argue that far from giving us a reason to reject my approach, this is one its key benefits. The intuitions with which this approach may clash ought to be challenged: our understanding of disability should no longer focus on bodily difference or deviation from what we take to be the norm, and should instead reflect a concern with the opportunities that all individuals ought to have access to, and which are closed to so many.

2 What disability is not

2.1 Disability and impairment

In this section I outline and critique alternative accounts of disability. However, I do not challenge the distinction between disability and impairment, or the consensus that the cause of disability involves both individual impairment and wider context. This terminology is worth clarifying. Impairment can be understood as “departure from human normality” (Terzi 2008: 43) or atypical forms of physical or cognitive functioning, and might include blindness, deafness, and mobility impairments, as well as non-standard cognitive functionings experienced by individuals with autistic spectrum conditions (ASCs), Down’s syndrome, or Alzheimer’s. Disabilities are the “activity limitations, and participation restrictions” that may result (WHO 2017). There are various views on which such limitations are disabling. For example, those who subscribe to a species norm approach deem the relevant functioning restrictions to be those “that individuals in someone’s reference group (e.g. adults) are ordinarily able to do” (Buchanan et al. 2000: 286). The goal of the paper is to defend a different approach.

Distinguishing disability and impairment draws attention to the contingency of the connection between bodily and cognitive difference and having a disability, which also depends on context, resources, and personal features. Indeed, highlighting this contingency was a major motivation behind the development of the social model by the disability rights movement.Footnote 3 Further, as we will see, this distinction both allows us to campaign against disability, as restriction, without suggesting that we should seek to normalise human bodies and minds by eliminating impairments, and enables us to describe the shared experience of atypical functioning of those who have an impairment, whether they are disabled by it or not.

Nonetheless, objections may be raised against this terminology. First, whilst common among disability scholars and activists, outside this community this language might strike some as clumsy and counterintuitive. We are very used to calling people with impairments—of vision, mobility, cognitive function—disabled, without paying much attention to the restrictions in activity or participation they may or may not face. It may seem awkward to insist that an individual in a wheelchair—often the literal poster-child of disability—is merely impaired, and that this might not translate into a disability. Yet this discomfort is often grounded in the unexamined assumption that differences in physical and cognitive functionings must manifest themselves in restrictions of ability, and the associated belief that the impaired body or mind is, itself, the problem. These intuitions, however strong, ought to be questioned, as the disability rights movement has long argued.

A second, more serious worry concerns the potential normative implications of labelling individuals ‘impaired’. This is not intended to be an evaluative concept. It simply provides a way of distinguishing disability, which (partially) results from impairment, from other forms of disadvantage, such as that associated with some racial or gender identities, or sexual orientation.Footnote 4 Further, (almost) everyone in some way deviates from the norm; hence, has an impairment. Nonetheless, this term has connotations of deficiency, defect, and imperfection. It may, therefore, seem more apt to refer to ‘difference’, ‘diversity’, or ‘heterogeneity’. I do not do so only to avoid the proliferation of competing terminology. However, to emphasise, impairment is synonymous with difference rather than deficiency.

Yet this neutral account of impairment may seem to leave my approach vulnerable to a third objection: that it will render the category of disability over-inclusive. As noted, part of the reason to accept the standard distinction between disability and impairment is that this helps to distinguish disability from other forms of socially-mediated disadvantage. However, if impairment implies mere atypicality (rather than deficiency) then it may still seem to include almost everyone: even individuals with better than normal functioning may count as impaired, in obvious tension with its usual meaning. The most straightforward response here is to note that accepting my general account of disability does not hang on accepting this view of impairment. It is possible to agree that individuals are disabled when they lack the opportunities they are entitled to, though to focus on cases in which this results from functioning in a ‘deficient’ or ‘unhealthy’ way.

More substantively, I believe both that there are positive reasons to adopt a neutral account of impairment, and that this will not render disability problematically over-inclusive, though I lack the space to fully defend either claim here.Footnote 5 To briefly tackle the over-inclusiveness worry: first, it is true that better functioning individuals will count as impaired (assuming functionings can meaningfully be described as simply ‘better’, as opposed to better suited to a particular context). However, describing Michael Phelps (to take Barnes’s (2016a: 14–15) oft-cited example) as impaired is hardly implausible if this just means he functions atypically. The important question is whether he is disabled—whether he lacks opportunities he is entitled to—and it is clear that he is not. A broad account of impairment does not necessitate a broad account of disability, then. Second, racial identity and sexual orientation will not count as impairments insofar as racial phenotypes and preferences cannot plausibly be described as functionings.Footnote 6 Sex-based differences may seem to present a harder case since there do seem to be differences in the functional capacities of average male and female-bodied persons, most obviously (though not only) relating to differences in their reproductive capacities. We do not need to accept the existence of a strict binary, or a metaphysically deep reason to appeal to reference classes based on sex categories, to allow that our assessment of typical functionings can be indexed to the capacities of biological females and males. Thus, a male is not impaired by their inability to bear young.Footnote 7 A neutral account of impairment, then, need not lead to the inclusion of other forms of disadvantage in the category of disability.

2.2 Species norm accounts

I therefore accept the distinction between disability and impairment, where the latter concept will make some reference to normal species functioning, but nonetheless reject accounts where disability itself comprises the loss of species-normal abilities. The most obvious worry is that these accounts will be over-inclusive since individuals depart from the species norm in many trivial (or even beneficial) ways. Raising an eyebrow might be a species-normal ability, but those who lack it surely are not disabled. Allen Buchanan et al. (2000: 285) attempt to avoid this problem by distinguishing “impairment of normal species functioning” from disability as the resulting inability to perform a significant range of tasks. To illustrate, they consider someone who cannot hear sound at a particular range of frequencies, yet in whose environment nothing “she is likely to be required to do or would benefit from doing” requires hearing sound in this range (Buchanan et al. 2000: 287). This individual thus has an impairment, but this does not translate into a disability.

However, this distinction between inabilities to perform species-normal functionings and species-normal tasks is difficult to draw—at least, without some additional account of which of these tasks are ‘significant’. Indeed, in describing their example, Buchanan et al. (2000: 287) make reference to what we might “be required” to do or “would benefit” from doing. By (implicitly) drawing on these ideas they can avoid the inclusion of trivial inabilities. However, this also suggests that their means of identifying relevant restrictions is not purely based on a species norm, and so is no longer a species norm approach.

Furthermore, this approach’s focus on ‘tasks’ may mean it is under-inclusive. Consider, for example, individuals who suffer from chronic pain, anxiety, or depression, but who are nonetheless high-functioning and able to perform all species-normal tasks (or those they are required to do, or that benefit them). These cases are analogous to the individual who cannot hear particular sound frequencies: they may not function as normal, but this does not translate into a restriction in their abilities. Yet it is implausible to suggest that individuals who struggle with pain, anxiety, and depression are not disabled until this manifests in an inability to perform tasks. Buchanan et al. could respond by adopting a more expansive understanding of tasks, and thus of disability. They might point out that performing tasks whilst suffering is not species-normal: we should not focus just on what people can achieve but on whether their method of achievement is normal. This response would, indeed, allow them to include individuals with chronic pain, depression, and so on, but would seem to come at the cost of also including their hearing-impaired person, and other trivial cases. After all, the species-normal way of performing the task of hearing includes, inter alia, not being in pain and hearing sound frequencies within a certain range. This fully inclusive approach is both implausible and contrary to their stated view. The route out would involve an appeal to which of the atypical ways of achieving a task are relevant or significant and this, as noted, takes us beyond the appeal to mere species norms. (As Sect. 6 will consider, this route is open to me since I am explicitly committed to a principle that identifies which of the various ways of performing atypical functionings are disabling.)

Accepting an account of impairment grounded in species norms does not raise the problems that plague this approach to disability. First, impairment should be an expansive category. Thus, we need not resist the inclusion of the individual with the mild hearing impairment, and those with anxiety, depression, and chronic pain—and even those who cannot raise an eyebrow, or Michael Phelps. This does not imply that disability must be similarly all-encompassing since, unlike Buchanan et al., I explicitly offer a criterion to identify which of the associated restrictions are disabling. Second, if impairment is normatively neutral—synonymous with difference, not defect—it is not vulnerable to a final objection often raised against species norm accounts of disability. This is the worry that focussing on an idealised conception of normal species functioning entails a corresponding disrespect of, and insult to, those who fail to meet this ideal. For example:

the whole ideology of normal functioning is seen as primarily constructed…to control and exclude disabled people from active and full participation in social and institutional arrangements which have no interest in accommodating them. (Terzi 2009: 90)

An account of impairment that is indexed to species norms merely acknowledges that many (or all) of us are not ‘normal’ in various ways and, whilst not problematic in itself, this can, in some circumstances, prevent us from having the opportunities we are entitled to. The same can be said of gender and racial identities and sexual orientation without implying any such identity is deficient.

2.3 Welfarist accounts

The second account of disability I will consider is the welfarist approach. This is most clearly and explicitly defined and defended by Kahane and Savulescu (2009: 53), according to whom disability is a:

stable physical or psychological property of subject S that tends to reduce S’s level of well-being in circumstances C, when contrasted with a realistic alternative, excluding the effect that this condition has on well-being that is due to prejudice against S.

Thus, the relevant inabilities, on this view, are those that reduce welfare.

Perhaps the most obvious problem with this account concerns the difficulties in developing an account of welfare. Whilst Kahane and Savulescu aim to remain neutral between alternative accounts, there are problems with any that might be incorporated. This reflects the more general difficulties with formulating a clear and satisfactory account of welfare, which cannot be rehearsed here.Footnote 8 However, in brief: first, a subjective account of welfare, relying on the individuals’ self-assessment, will inevitably raise reliability concerns. The various ways in which self-reported levels of happiness, contentment, or preference-satisfaction, can be misleading have been well-documented.Footnote 9 Yet moving toward a more objective understanding of welfare brings its own problems. For example, the difficulty of finding a non-arbitrary way of compiling a list of basic goods, or the worry that this list will entail the paternalist imposition of a perfectionist conception of the good, or that it will be elitist and exclusionary. Further, we may be sceptical about the implication that something can be considered good for someone independently of their attitudes towards it, and indeed, despite their own insistence to the contrary.

A further problem in the social justice context is the epistemic difficulty of assessing welfare in many cases. For example, Kahane and Savulescu (2009) discuss the ‘Ashley treatment’, named after a child with severe cognitive impairments who was given treatment to restrict her further growth and prevent puberty. They argue that though this treatment moved Ashley further from the species norm, it lessened her disability since it improved her welfare. This stands in stark contrast to, for example, Eva Feder Kittay’s discussion of the case, in part because Kittay employs a different understanding of Ashley’s welfare. She contends that “[w]e take pleasure and pride in our bodies as they grow and mature because…we do. Full stop. It needs no further justification. It is constitutive of a thriving life” (Kittay 2011: 621). Yet evidently Kahane and Savluescu do not recognise this value. These epistemic difficulties are especially intractable in cases such as Ashley’s where it can be hard to ascertain the view of the individual concerned, and far from clear that those who have not experienced this condition can understand what would be required for her to thrive.

Thus, Kahane and Savulescu’s definition does not determine who is disabled, but simply moves the debate to a new context: finding a satisfactory account of welfare. This is an important gap in their approach. However, the fact they have not filled it does not mean it cannot be satisfactorily filled (though given how long this debate has raged, scepticism regarding its speedy resolution seems justified). Further, a welfarist might respond that disability should not be easy to define, and that my own approach will face similar worries—there is, of course, no consensus on what justice demands. However, these epistemic worries are, perhaps, deeper for welfarist approaches—at least for those that include an element of subjectivity in their account of welfare—since they necessarily require a direct reliance on first person testimony. Moreover, whilst we may not have reached agreement on a complete theory of justice, it might be easier to agree on basic entitlements and so basic injustices than it is to identify core instances of welfare deficit. Further, we may need to agree on certain essentials of a theory of justice, unlike welfare, if we are to determine how the benefits and burdens of social cooperation are to be distributed (Rawls 1999: 5). For example, it is, perhaps, easier to agree that individuals are entitled to equal political participation, opportunities for mobility, and the ability to form relationships than it is to show that all these capabilities will make all individuals better-off, given the existence of the idiosyncratic preferences of the politically apathetic, sedentary, and misanthropic. Thus, disagreements about what makes life go well may be harder to settle even in apparently core cases, as examples like Ashley illustrate. Yet welfarists could doubtless disagree. As such, noting the lack of a widely-accepted account of welfare raises a worry that demands a response, rather than providing a decisive refutation of the welfarist view.

The deeper problem for this view is that, whatever account of welfare is used, disability will be ubiquitous, and this will prove problematic from the perspective of justice and public policy. As Kahane and Savulescu (2009: 30) openly acknowledge, disability will be a degree rather than a threshold concept. Thus, “everyone has disabilities of one kind or another”.Footnote 10 I agree that there can be a degree of arbitrariness in determining the boundaries of disability. I agree, too, that we have reasons to expand this category (as Sect. 7 discusses). Nonetheless, we should be cautious of expanding it so far that it becomes meaningless, as it will be if it is a category in which everyone is included.

If every stable physical or psychological property that lowers our welfare counts as disabling, then this definition does not seem to pick out the right cases—or, not only the right cases. At least, not in the context of social justice, where our concern is identifying disadvantage and determining how the state should appropriately respond. It is certainly worth emphasising that disability is a continuum, and that we are all restricted by the limitations of our bodies and minds. Nonetheless, when fighting against ableism and injustice, simply concluding that ‘we are all disabled’ is unhelpful. Similarly, we may wish to reject binaries of sexual orientation and gender identity, and deny that racial categorisation is possible, yet nonetheless find it useful to refer to ‘women’, and ‘gay people’, and ‘black people’ as a means of identifying, and fighting against, injustices against these groups. ‘Disability’, I contend, has value and meaning as a way of identifying, and responding to, disadvantage. The term has little function if entirely ubiquitous.Footnote 11

2.4 Barnes’s social constructionist approach

Barnes, like many others, rejects the social model’s exclusive focus on external causes of disability, and emphasises that our understanding of disability should be grounded in an assessment of individuals’ physical features—or, “what their body is (really) like” (Barnes 2016a: 38).Footnote 12 However, she also emphasises that particular qualities are considered significant not because of their objective features, but because of how we think about them. Barnes further argues that those best placed to determine which features should be considered disabling are disability activists. Thus, “disability just is whatever the disability rights movement is promoting justice for” (Barnes 2016a: 43). Inclusion in the category of disability therefore depends on “rule-based solidarity among people with certain kinds of bodies” (Barnes 2016a: 46).

However, there may be problems with relying on such rules. First, we should not unquestioningly accept the content of these rules. Whilst disabled individuals’ testimony should undoubtedly play an important role in developing an account of disability, it does not follow that the rules adopted by the disability rights movement will be free of bias. Individuals who already ‘count’ as disabled may have vested interests in excluding others from entering this group, and perhaps diluting the strength of their claims with the accretion of many others. This need not be a conscious process of exclusion. Individuals may simply tend to see their own impairments as the paradigm, and be less inclined to include those they are less familiar with. Thus, we should not assume that disabled individuals’ epistemically privileged position regarding their own experience extends to understanding the diverse experiences of all disabled people.Footnote 13 Nor can we assume that a group fighting against injustice will never unjustly exclude others. Consider, for example, the exclusion of asexual individuals by some in the LGBTQ + community, or the exclusion of trans women by some feminists. The point is not that such exclusion is unjust, but that the question is not resolved by observing that existing members of the community determined these boundaries.Footnote 14

A related worry is that, given the heterogeneity that exists between and within such groups, disagreement about the content and application of the rules of inclusion seems likely, and difficult to resolve. Barnes (2016a: 49) acknowledges the diversity of disability rights movements, and allows that it may be “simply vague or indeterminate which social group is referred to…[as] ‘the disability rights movement’”. Her response is to insist that “this entire domain…is riddled with indeterminacy” (Barnes 2016a: 49), and that it would be “deeply implausible” if it turned out that “any aspect of our complex, multifaceted social reality had fully determinate boundaries” (Barnes 2016a: 50). It is true that any definition will likely include borderline cases. Indeed, an account that provides a firm and unequivocal distinction seems to have missed something important about the category of disability. Yet even if the boundaries are somewhat indeterminate, we still need some sense of where they lie, and I am sceptical that the implicit rules used by disability rights movements will be sufficient for this task.Footnote 15

Further, I believe there are deeper flaws in Barnes’s approach, which can be seen by considering two criteria Barnes (2016a: 10–13) sets out for a successful account of disability: first, that it should not prejudge normative issues and, second, that it should deliver the correct verdict about paradigm cases. These criteria will not be met by my account, but I contend that an account of disability need not—and, indeed, should not attempt to—fulfil these criteria. Considering the latter first, it is not clear why it would be a virtue of an account to be ‘correct’ about paradigm cases. Whilst we may worry about an approach that bears no relation to our understanding of disability—for example, an account that includes homosexuality—we should also be aware that our sense of the ‘paradigm’ is often informed by intuitions that are based on prejudice about, and misunderstanding of, disabled lives.Footnote 16 As noted, these worries may not be solved by allowing those who are already considered part of this ‘paradigm’ to be the arbiters of who else will be included.

Next, Barnes (2016a: 11) insists that “[i]t should not be built into the very definition of disability that disability is something that’s bad or suboptimal”. However, it is only important that disability be value-neutral if we follow Barnes in rejecting the distinction between impairment and disability.Footnote 17 If we accept this distinction, we can allow that disability is necessarily disadvantageous and still maintain a normatively neutral account of impairment, capturing the heterogeneity of human bodies and capacities, which may be disadvantageous in some contexts but need not be so. This does not undermine the possibility of being proud of our diverse bodies and minds. However, conflating these terms makes it near impossible to achieve the twin goals of recognising that diversity need not be negative, and that it can be correlated with disadvantage, which must be identified to be rectified.

Barnes meets her own criteria, and so argues that disability is a ‘mere difference’. Yet this does not mean it has no effect on individuals’ lives. On the contrary, it “may be good for you, it may be bad for you, it may be utterly indifferent for you” (Barnes 2016a: 98). Indeed, Barnes allows that being disabled may sometimes lower overall well-being, that some aspects of some disabilities are bad-differences (Barnes 2016a: 75), and even that some specific disabilities are bad simpliciter [something that makes “your life go worse in virtue of it specifically” (Barnes 2016a: 87; 102)]. By including diverse conditions within this wider category, it becomes true that disability is not necessarily a bad-difference, but this category still encompasses conditions (whether few or many) that are bad-differences.Footnote 18

Clearly, then, Barnes does not believe that “the positive effects [of disability] have to balance the negative ones”, and accepts that “in the world we inhabit, disability tends to significantly reduce one’s good options”—contra the claims of some of her critics (Kahane and Savulescu 2016: 777, 776).Footnote 19 Nonetheless, espousing a ‘value-neutral model’ or ‘mere-difference view’ of disability can be importantly misleading, especially if this is used to ground general claims about the kinds of policies that should be pursued with regards to disability. Certainly we should acknowledge that it is “simply untrue that, as a general rule, disabilities are bad for those who have them” (Campbell and Stramondo 2017: 176). Thus, claims rooted in  the general assumption that someone’s life will be worse simply because they have ‘a disability’ are unjustified.Footnote 20 However, we should also avoid grounding claims about policy on the assumption that all disabilities should be treated as neutral simply because this category incorporates conditions with good, bad, and neutral effects. For example, we may accept that disability is a mere-difference in Barnes’s sense, but still believe, contra Barnes (2014, 2016a), that it is sometimes wrong simpliciter to cause some disabilities.Footnote 21 Amalgamating all disability into a general ‘value-neutral model’, then, can obscure the disadvantage that can be associated with impairment.Footnote 22

How problematic this is may depend on the context in which our account of disability is employed. My focus here is relatively narrow: aiming to develop an account that can guide theory and policy that aims to identify and mitigate the disadvantage associated with physical and cognitive difference. Such policies should be nuanced and individualised, as I will argue. They must acknowledge that some impairments, for some people, in some contexts, are not neutral—or merely “a minority body” (Barnes 2016a: 1)—and should not be treated as such. Thus, in this context, at least, it seems unwise to remain committed to a unified category of disability so broadly construed.

Like the welfarist account, then, Barnes’s approach shifts the focus of the debate rather than settling it: determining how to respond to disability will require identifying which aspects of which disabilities are bad differences. Neither approach settles the question of when disability is a disadvantage of the kind the state should mitigate. Thus, neither approach can form the basis of public policy or political activism. Whilst we must have a value-neutral account of physical and cognitive difference (which I call impairment), we also need a concept that can play a role in political debates about when difference is disadvantageous, what constitutes injustice towards disabled individuals, and the policies that should be pursued to respond to this.

3 Which inabilities matter?

Not all restrictions in individuals’ capacity for activity and participation are disabilities: we are not disabled if we cannot sing, cannot stand on one leg, or cannot raise an eyebrow. This is so even if these abilities are species normal, and even if restrictions in them decrease our welfare. I argue that the relevant restrictions are in abilities that individuals are entitled to be able to perform. I will begin by considering a specific application of this approach: the case of deafness. The impairment here is the inability to hear, whilst the disability is the reduction in relevant opportunities that may arise when most people communicate via speech, such as difficulties in political participation, access to appropriate education, and forming meaningful relationships. Deaf individuals are not disabled on the basis that they are unable to hear music, or the voices of their loved ones. However, this need not be because opportunities for aesthetic experience or forming relationships are not considered central entitlements. On the contrary, they may well be central—we simply do not need to hear music or voices to have them. Being entitled to opportunities in a domain need not require having every opportunity. Thus, if deaf individuals have access to other aesthetic experiences, their inability to hear music is not a concern of justice. Indeed, if deaf individuals have all the opportunities they are entitled to, they are not disabled.

My claim, then, is that individuals are disadvantaged when their access to their entitlements is restricted, and disabled when this results from an impairment (in combination with context, resources, and personal characteristics).Footnote 23 Thus, individuals with the same impairments may not be identically disabled, and individuals’ status as disabled may change over time even if their impairment does not alter. Rightly, then, we cannot know whether an individual is disabled merely from information about their impairment. The account is intended to be a framework into which various theories of distributive justice can be incorporated. Accepting the general claim that individuals are disabled when their impairments restrict their access to forms of activity and participation they are entitled to does not require accepting a particular conception of entitlements.

However, there is (at least) one approach to distributive justice that cannot be incorporated. My account distinguishes what individuals are entitled to from what merely decreases their welfare. As such, it cannot accommodate those welfarist approaches that consider anything that lowers individuals’ welfare—whether state oppression or stubbing our toe—to constitute a relevant disadvantage. Subjective accounts, which do not distinguish the different reasons for a decrease in hedonic state or the different sorts of preferences individuals may care to have satisfied, would collapse into the welfarist accounts discussed in Sect. 2.3 and so face the same worries about over-inclusiveness and the ubiquity of disability raised there.Footnote 24 My approach relies on the general anti-welfarist intuition that “[s]ome deprivations of capabilities [or resources] express greater disrespect than others, in ways any reasonable person can recognize” (Anderson 1999: 332). This distinction is employed widely in the distributive justice literature, by theorists who disagree on much else, and has strong intuitive pull.Footnote 25 It is the suggestion that individuals should be entitled to vote in elections, to be mobile, and to access educational opportunities, but are not entitled to access every ride in an amusement park, or a sports car, or an expensive musical instrument—and that this is so even if they would prefer these latter opportunities, and they would have a greater positive impact on their welfare. In other words, this is the claim that only some domains of life are the concern of justice, and that the scope of these domains is not determined by individuals’ preferences.

Beyond this restriction, then, adopting a specific theory of justice is not a prerequisite to accepting my account of disability. However, it is difficult to defend this account in the abstract, and cumbersome to run through every possible way to cash out individual entitlements. Thus, I will talk in specific terms, employing an approach with three key features. First, I will assume individuals are entitled to capabilities, understood as control over certain domains of their life, rather than merely access to resources (Begon 2017). Second, our conception of entitlements should be relatively thick: not merely entailing the fulfilment of basic needs, but including access to opportunities such as forming social relationships, engaging in leisure activities, and enjoying aesthetic experiences. Finally, I assume that individuals are entitled to broadly specified opportunities, and not particular or identical functionings: for example, opportunities for aesthetic experiences, mobility, or communication, and not hearing music, walking, or talking.Footnote 26 These features have not been selected at random. I believe there are good reasons to opt for an account of distributive justice with these features, and that reflection on disability can help demonstrate why this is so, as much of the subsequent discussion will illustrate. However, I certainly cannot definitively refute all alternative understandings of entitlements here, so will leave it to their adherents to demonstrate how they can navigate the issues disability raises.

4 Feasibility, levelling-down, and thinning-out

I will now outline some possible objections to the account I have sketched, and in responding to them in subsequent sections will elucidate my account. First, it may be objected that if being disabled means lacking opportunities we are entitled to, then impairments that result in the loss of significant opportunities will not be considered disabling if we cannot prevent this loss, since we cannot be entitled to an opportunity it is impossible to provide. Thus, if, due to lack of medical or technological knowledge, or merely lack of resources, we cannot prevent individuals being rendered immobile, unable to communicate, or to form relationships, then they cannot be entitled to these opportunities, and cannot be considered disabled by their absence. If this were so, serious impairments—perhaps the most serious impairments—would not be considered disabling on my account. Clearly, this would be very counterintuitive.

Further, this understanding of our entitlements presents a dilemma. On the one hand, this may lead us to conclude that individuals with serious impairments should simply have different entitlements. That is, if some individuals can only be provided with a restricted set of opportunities, then their entitlements are correspondingly diminished. On the other hand, we may wish to resist this tiered, non-universal approach to entitlements, and insist instead that all humans are entitled to the same opportunities (though not, of course, to the same outcomes). Yet this seems to imply that the content of everyone’s entitlements should reflect the unavoidable constraints on some individuals’ functioning. In other words, that we can be entitled only to what can be provided to all. If we grasp this latter horn, the content of our entitlements might start to look rather thin. This is implausible in itself and will generate an implausible account of disability if my approach is employed. For example, if we cannot currently enable everyone to control their mobility then no one can be entitled to this opportunity, and individuals whose control over their mobility is impaired are not disabled by their inability.

However, this is an artificial dichotomy. If we reject an implausibly strict egalitarian view, according to which everyone must be enabled to perform an identical set of functionings, and instead consider individuals to be entitled to generalised opportunities—for example, mobility, not walking (i.e. the third criterion outlined above)—then it may seem that everyone can have the same entitlements. Thus, we can avoid a tiered approach without levelling-down our entitlements to include only those capabilities to function that can be universally provided. That is, we should recognise that capabilities are multiply-realisable, and treat different functionings as interchangeable and equally valuable. This will mean that many individuals with impairments can have the opportunities they are entitled to even if there are some functionings they cannot perform. Thus, even if we were to limit our entitlements to those that could be provided universally, this might eliminate less than it initially seems.

Nonetheless, this response will not prove fully satisfactory. First, even if the opportunities individuals are entitled to are generalised and multiply-realisable there will still be some cases in which they cannot be provided. Staying with the example of mobility: though individuals with many mobility impairments can be enabled to control their mobility, this may not be possible for individuals with locked-in syndrome. Further, the very focus on multiply-realisable capabilities may generate a further objection about the ‘thinning-out’ of individuals’ entitlements. It might seem that if those who use a wheelchair have sufficient opportunity to be mobile, then they have all they are entitled to. Thus, if, for example, it were possible to restore functioning to a paraplegic person’s legs, even at very little cost, they would neither be entitled to demand this from the state nor considered disabled if the treatment were not provided. This is an instance of the more general worry that sufficientarian approaches, by only ensuring individuals reach some threshold of achievement, may fail to eliminate radical, and potentially unjust, inequalities above this threshold. If capabilities can be experienced in various ways, then individuals are neither considered disabled by their inability to perform specific functionings (walking, talking, hearing, seeing) nor entitled to be enabled to perform them, just as long as they have more general capabilities (for mobility, communication, leisure, aesthetic experiences) at some appropriate level. I will now respond to these objections.

5 Identifying distributive entitlements

I turn, first, to the objection that individuals with serious impairments will not be considered disabled if the opportunity loss associated with their condition cannot be avoided; and, further, that we will therefore face the dilemma of either decreasing entitlements for this subset of individuals or levelling-down entitlements generally. This is based on the assumption that the demands of distributive justice must be realisable: that if an individual is entitled to something, it must be feasible to provide it to them. However, we need not accept this assumption.Footnote 27 It is quite plausible to suggest that we are currently unable to rectify some instances of injustice. Thus, some individuals may not be able to access opportunities that justice requires they have. If a just state of affairs is not currently realisable then they cannot have a claim that anyone now provides these opportunities, though they do have a claim that we work towards a situation in which their provision is feasible. If, for example, we believe all humans are entitled to control over their mobility, then this cannot mean the state has an obligation to provide this to someone with locked-in syndrome if this is impossible. However, they do have an obligation to enable them to have such control if it were, and to work towards releasing this state of affairs. Further, the individual with locked-in syndrome is disabled because they cannot be provided with an opportunity that they should have access to: that they should be enabled to perform if this were possible.

A situation in which some individuals lack opportunities that everyone should be entitled to may be unjust, then, even if no one is guilty of causing this injustice and no one has a direct duty to rectify it. Some may find the suggestion that entitlements should be conditional in this sense implausible: how can we be entitled to something no one has a duty to provide? It is worth noting, first, that the alternative approach has similarly unappealing implications: if we want a universal list of entitlements and can only include items on this list when they can currently be provided to every individual, then we may not even have a general right to nourishment, say, if it is currently logistically impossible to ensure everyone has this opportunity. We may, therefore, accept that some entitlements should lack a feasibility constraint, but believe these conditional or proto-entitlements should be distinguished from entitlements proper, where the former are what all individuals are (conditionally) owed as a matter of justice and the latter are those claims that we can press against a specific duty-bearer. The former constitute part of the content of a theory of distributive justice: the list of capabilities (or primary goods or human rights) to which all individuals have a (conditional) entitlement, even if they temporarily cannot be provided with every item on this list. Indeed, this captures what seems so objectionable about situations in which individuals do not have the opportunities (or resources, or rights) we think they ought to: individuals may not be wronged when they cannot be mobile, or nourished, and so on, but they should have these opportunities if it were possible and we should work to make this so.

The important point is not the choice of terminology, but the general claim that the set of entitlements specified by a theory of distributive justice are, in a sense, owed to all, even when this obligation cannot feasibly be met. The sense in which they are owed is that these opportunities (resources, rights) should be provided if they can be, and that the state (or other relevant body) should not artificially limit the boundaries of the possible. This means that not all disability will be the result of unjust behaviour—though, of course, some will be. Sometimes the state may fail to fund research to develop technologies that increase impaired individuals’ functioning capacity, or design material infrastructure in avoidably exclusionary ways. Yet sometimes the restrictions to individuals’ entitlements may be ineliminable and unavoidable: perhaps due to natural obstacles, perhaps due to competing claims on a limited pool of resources, or to conflicts between different forms of accommodation (certain policies may render some impairments non-disabling (indeed, may be the only way to do so) whilst at the same time exacerbating others). Thus, the content of our (conditional) universal distributive entitlements should not be determined by what it is feasible to provide universally.

Understanding entitlements in this way means we need not grasp either horn of the above dilemma: we can have a universal set of entitlements that is not levelled-down to include only those opportunities that can be achieved by all. However, this does not imply that the content of our entitlements can or should take no account of feasibility whatsoever. We could, for example, take the view that humans should be entitled to the opportunities necessary for a decent life, where this will be informed by our reasonable expectations of what such a life entails. On this view, controlling our mobility might be central to such a life; the ability to fly would not be. Further, the content of our reasonable expectations for a decent life can be predicted to change over time, as technology improves. The point, here, is not to identify the specific content of our distributive entitlements, nor even to outline the method by which they would be determined. Rather, it is to note that this might depend on what it is possible for humans to do, and on what we think humans ought to be able to do, without implying that all these entitlements must currently be achievable for every human. In other words, entitlements can be indexed to what is feasible for most, without requiring that they can be provided to all (though we should strive to achieve this).

Two further objections may be raised against this response. First, if our entitlements depend to some extent on our reasonable expectations about a decent (or dignified, or flourishing) human life, and our expectations are informed by what humans, as a species, can generally do, then this might seem to collapse into a species norm approach. That is, our entitlements are simply identical to species-normal functionings. Yet this is not the case. Even without specifying the content of our entitlements we can see that they will be both narrower and broader than species-normal functionings. They will be narrower, first, because on any plausible view trivial human capabilities will not be central entitlements (the ability to roll our tongue, sing, or stand on one leg). Individuals who thus deviate from the species norm do not lack opportunities they are entitled to. Our entitlements are narrower, too, if understood as general opportunities, rather than the performance of specific functionings. An individual can have what they are entitled to (the capability for mobility, say), even if there is a species-normal functioning they cannot perform (walking using their own legs). Additionally, our entitlements will be broader, since we may be entitled to more opportunities than those that are ‘natural’ or normal for our species.Footnote 28 As medical, social, and technological progress expands the scope of human capacities, our reasonable expectations of a decent life and the opportunities we should be entitled to will surely reflect this.

A second objection concerns the potential ambiguity regarding when it is ‘feasible’ to provide an opportunity, given that this may require radical expense of time or resources. There are two forms of this worry. First, if we could all be enabled to fly, say—if the government were to divert all research funding to this project—then should this opportunity be an entitlement, which we are disabled in the absence of? Clearly the answer is no. When this is a mere abstract possibility, such a functioning is unlikely to feature in our reasonable conception of a decent life, or what we can reasonably expect from the state. However, I would concede that if a way of enabling humans to fly were discovered and made available to the majority, then we might expand our conception of our entitlements to include this.Footnote 29 In this imagined scenario this is no more a reduction ad absurdum of my approach than acknowledging that individuals’ capacity for mobility should take account of modern transportation and that, as such, someone who could only get around at the speed and distance walking and running would usually allow may not have what they are entitled to in this domain. To emphasise: insisting that we can be entitled to opportunities it is infeasible to provide universally does not mean our entitlements must be entirely unmoored from what is feasible for most.

Second, and perhaps more troubling, are cases in which an opportunity is available to most individuals, but can only be provided to a minority at great expense. For example, if an individual with locked-in syndrome can control their mobility only with an extremely expensive piece of equipment, are they entitled to it? No doubt there will be many difficult cases, but our approach to such questions must involve weighing up the capabilities provided to the minority against those lost by the majority. Thus, if the cost of providing this equipment meant others suffered premature death or significant impairment then the individual surely cannot be entitled to their mobility in the face of these costs. In this case, we can continue to say that it is impossible for the individual to be mobile and they are unavoidably disabled, since their entitlements cannot be provided at a reasonable cost.Footnote 30

6 Beyond minimal functionings

I now turn to the worry that understanding entitlements as general, multiply-realisable opportunities will mean that individuals will not be considered disabled even when they lack important opportunities. First, I consider Anita Silvers’s objection to what she takes to be capability theorists’ approach to educational provision for individuals with impairments. This, she claims, would only provide “educational opportunity adequate for a dignified life, which…may not even…rise to the level of average educational attainment” (Silvers 2009: 181). Silvers discusses a child with a hearing impairment, who struggles to catch all the information imparted in class due to the difficulty of lip-reading in this context. Nonetheless, she is denied a translator since her educational attainment is already above average (Silvers 2009: 177–182). Silvers objects that it is unfair that children with impairments are unable to fulfil their potential simply because their educational environment is not designed to support them. Further, it might seem that, on my view, these children would (implausibly) not be considered disabled by this restriction in their access to education, because ‘they already have what they’re entitled to’.

However, contra Silvers, a decent education surely requires more than the opportunity for some minimal educative outcome, such as passing grades.Footnote 31 More plausibly, this requires something like ‘the opportunity to develop our potential to a similar degree as our peers’. This must be at least part of the goal of education, and we would fail to show individuals equal concern and respect if we provided this to some and not others.Footnote 32 This does not mean that there will not be difficult cases, where the needs and requirements of different children pull in different directions, and limitations of resources mean that an ideal learning environment cannot be provided for everyone. However, as discussed, the fact that something cannot currently be universally provided does not mean that we cannot reasonably include this amongst our entitlements.

Yet it may be objected that education is a special case. Whilst the very goal of education involves enabling individuals to develop their talents and abilities, having opportunities for mobility, communication, or leisure surely does not require being able to fulfil our potential in these domains. It seems much more plausible to suggest that we are here entitled to something like acceptable options and the capacity to meaningfully choose between them. As such, individuals who achieve mobility with a wheelchair rather than by walking, or communicate using Sign rather than speech, or look at art because they are unable to listen to music, are not considered disabled by this restriction in their ability to function; nor would they be entitled to an operation to restore the use of their legs, or cochlear implants to restore their hearing, even if this would not be costly.

In these cases, I would bite the bullet—though with some important caveats. I would accept, then, that if we lived in circumstances in which individuals with impairments had all the opportunities they are entitled to then they should neither be considered disabled nor necessarily entitled to state assistance. For example, if an individual with a mobility impairment could control their mobility without being dependent on others, then they may not be entitled to be enabled to walk.Footnote 33 Similarly, a deaf individual who had access to leisure activities and aesthetic experiences (and every other capability they are entitled to) would not be entitled to cochlear implants to allow them to hear music. Nor would these individuals be considered disabled.

The caveats, though, are to point out, first, that often individuals with impairments do not have what they are entitled to. In many cases the restrictions in their capabilities are avoidable, and could be eliminated by changing social infrastructure and norms. However, this is not always so. In some instances, this is because we lack the technology or resources to prevent some impairments from restricting individuals’ opportunities. In others, this is because individuals’ needs conflict, and there is no way to structure the external environment that would eliminate all restrictions. For example, “[p]eople with mobility issues who do not use wheelchairs may find that steps are safer and easier for them than ramps…[w]heelchair users may have problems with tactile paving which gives locational cues to visually impaired people”, and so on (Shakespeare 2006: 46). These cases can prove as intractable as those in which we simply lack the ability to institute the relevant change. As such, the appropriate way to mitigate the disadvantage associated with an impairment may not be to change the environment, and this might be so even when the disadvantage is a result of that environment. Thus, to conclude that if an impairment were not disabling (did not result in relevant restrictions) an individual would not be entitled to state assistance does not imply that now, or in the near future, treatments that mitigate impairments would not be provided.

The second caveat is to note that suggesting that such treatments may not be a matter of entitlement does not imply that they are banned or restricted. Any liberal approach to distributive justice will aim to ensure both fairness in distribution, and individuals’ freedom to form and pursue their own conception of the good. Thus, if an individual desires to walk, or hear, or see, they will not be prevented from pursuing these goals. Indeed, in a situation in which individuals had access to all the central capabilities (or primary goods, or equality of Dworkinian resources) there would be sufficient resource equality that individuals would have the ability to achieve these goals (especially on the above assumption that these treatments are inexpensive). Indeed, my account does not even rule out state provision or subsidy of these options on the grounds of public choice, if the decision is procedurally just and does not divert resources from the satisfaction of actual entitlements.Footnote 34

One final sense in which our entitlements might seem too minimal on my approach relates to an objection earlier raised against the species norm approach. This is, that by focussing on what individuals are able to do, I take insufficient account of how much more difficult this may be when we have an impairment. Someone who uses a wheelchair, for example, may have the capability for mobility, but this will often be restricted by both the built and natural environment. Thus, they may find travelling much more physically demanding than, for example, walking a similar distance. Or, an individual in chronic pain may be able to perform all the functionings that a person without this condition can, yet they must struggle against the pain that accompanies every functioning they perform. I certainly want to resist the implication that the difficulty of performing tasks would not be considered a relevant dimension of disadvantage, and that individuals who experience such difficulty would not be considered disabled, nor entitled to assistance to mitigate it.

Whether this is indeed an implication of my approach depends on the sensitivity of our conception of distributive entitlements not just to what we can do, but also to the pain and effort that must be expended to do it. I would contend that such concerns should feature in our understanding of individuals’ entitlements.Footnote 35 Although I cannot provide an independent defence of this here, it is important to note that insisting that a theory of distributive justice is sensitive to these considerations is not merely a post hoc modification to ensure that my definition of disability remains plausible. On the contrary, the above examples give us reason to think that individuals should be entitled not just to the mere capacity to perform some functionings, but to be able to do so without associated pain, and without having to expend massively more energy than others to achieve the same outcome. Thus, the point is not that an account of our entitlements that ignored the pain and effort required to achieve them would generate an implausible account of disability if my framework is employed, but that this would be an independently implausible account of our entitlements.

7 What counts, who’s disabled?

I will finish by considering whether my account will prove to be too revisionary. Certainly, the impairments that would be considered disabling do not neatly cohere with our intuitions in a number of cases. As emphasised from the outset, my account will imply that individuals with visible impairments may not be disabled by them, that individuals with seemingly minor or invisible impairments may be disabled, and that individuals’ status as disabled may change across time and context. However, far from giving us reason to reject this approach, this is one of its key benefits. As Sect. 2.4 discussed, there is little point in devising a definition that captures all paradigm case when we have good reason to think the paradigm is informed by prejudice and misinformation.

First, many paradigm impairments, such as deafness, blindness, paraplegia, achondroplasia (a common form of dwarfism), ASCs, and Down’s syndrome need not be disabling on my account. If individuals have the opportunities they are entitled to—perhaps as a result of adequate infrastructure, access to resources, and lack of bias—they will not be considered disabled merely on the basis of their impairment. Disability does not consist in bodily or cognitive difference, but in specific opportunity losses that might result. This does not imply that we cannot campaign for the better treatment of individuals with impairments, or for their access to their entitlements. However, we should not assume that having an impairment, especially a visible impairment, must be disadvantageous. We should, instead, focus on the specifics of each case and determine whether an impairment is actually associated with restrictions in individuals’ activity and participation. The reality often will not accord with our unexamined intuitions.Footnote 36

My approach will also produce deviations from the paradigm in the other direction: many non-paradigm cases, such as depression and anxiety, and even obesity or shyness, might be disabling. Further, individuals who have body integrity identity disorder (the strong desire to amputate a healthy limb) may be disabled by being prevented from undergoing this amputation, insofar as living with a limb they disassociate from disrupts their access to capabilities: for example, making social interaction difficult.Footnote 37 I will consider perhaps the most controversial of these examples: obesity. I am aware that both disabled and obese individuals will likely object to this implication, given the unjustified stigma attached to both labels. It is worth emphasising, then, that though I consider an obese body an impairment (after all, it is a deviation from the species norm), I am not suggesting that it worse, or necessarily disadvantageous, to have such a body. However, this is a dimension of difference, like many others, that may be associated with disadvantage.Footnote 38

My focus is not the possible (and sometimes controversial) correlation between obesity and health conditions such as high blood pressure, diabetes, heart attack, or stroke. Even leaving these aside merely having an obese body can be disabling. Our built environment is made for human bodies of a particular size and weight. As Gay (2017: 184) says, “[t]here are very few spaces where bodies like mine fit”. One simple and important example is chairs: aeroplane seats, restaurant booths, lecture theatres, cinema seats. If these cannot accommodate individuals with larger bodies, this can be hugely restrictive to those who possess them, limiting opportunities to be mobile, to access education, or to engage in many leisure activities. In addition, an obese body may be restrictive independently of the design of material infrastructure, rendering “impossible” activities like standing for long periods or walking a mile uphill (Gay 2017: 16). Finally, the bias, stigma, and abuse obese individuals are often subject to, the commentaries on their bodies by friends, family, medical professionals, and strangers, and the assumptions made about their capacities may further limit their capabilities. Options may be closed to them because others assume they are incapable of exercising them (for example, not being offered certain jobs), or they may lack internal capabilities (for example, not feeling qualified to apply for these jobs in the first place).Footnote 39 In all these ways, obesity—like other forms of physical and cognitive difference—can be disabling.

The final counterintuitive implication is that what counts as a disability on my view will be contextualised, and may change over time. This can happen in at least three ways. First, as society becomes better able to accommodate impairments, and enable different forms of functioning, then these impairments will cease to be disabling. This is not because these impairments are ‘cured’, but because their link with disadvantage is severed. For example, if the oft-discussed examples of deafness and mobility impairments no longer lead to capability loss, then individuals with these impairments may not be disabled, though they still cannot hear or walk unaided. Whilst this may seem counterintuitive to some, it accords with the experience of many disabled individuals, who do not regret, or demand compensation for, the different ways they function. Consider, for example, Harriet McBryde Johnson’s (2003) account of the pleasures of wheelchair use, and the misperceptions of those who do not use one:

I used to try to explain the fact that I enjoy my life, that it’s a great sensual pleasure to zoom by power chair on these delicious muggy streets, that I have no more reason to kill myself than most people. But it gets tedious…they don’t want to know. They think they know everything there is to know just by looking at me. That’s how stereotypes work. They don’t know that they’re confused.

Second, as our capacity to provide opportunities changes, individuals may be entitled to more if the content of our entitlements depends on our reasonable expectations. For example, we now expect leisure time, aesthetic experiences, and a longer life than previously. Impairments that restrict access to these new entitlements will then count as disabling, though individuals’ actual abilities have not changed. One example here might be (some forms of) dyslexia. In a context in which many are illiterate, this is unlikely to be disabling. In a context in which a grasp of the written word is a prerequisite for many other opportunities, it would be. Thus, dyslexic individuals may become disabled over time, or by moving. Consider, for example, a dyslexic girl who emigrates from rural Gambia, where illiteracy is rife and educational infrastructure underdeveloped, to the UK, where she has better access to education, though her dyslexia is not fully accommodated. Whilst she is now less disadvantaged (she now has access to education), she may also become disabled insofar as it is now her impairment that restricts her access to education (where previously it may have been poverty or sexism). Again, this seems to be the right way to understand such cases.

Lastly, individuals who have impairments that involve periodic and perhaps unpredictable flare-ups, such as fatigue and pain conditions, may have a changeable disability status. Some will be disabled only during a flare-up, some may be disabled during periods when flare-ups are common, and for some the mere possibility of a flare-up may render them consistently disabled. For example, an individual with epilepsy may never be able to drive a car, or an individual with ME may struggle to retain employment if their impairment necessitates frequent absences.

8 Conclusion

It is a consequence of my approach that individuals are not categorised as disabled in the way we might expect, and that who is included in this category may change. Yet surely it is right to set aside our preconceptions about how bad some impairment must be and focus instead on the actual restrictions individuals face, and on which of these should be the focus of our concern. What matters—what is disabling—is that individuals are rendered (often contingently) unable to be mobile, unable to communicate or form social relationships, or unable to access education or meaningful work as a result of their impairments. Not that they are unable to walk, unable to listen to music, or unable to read emotional cues easily. Whatever account of distributive justice is used, then, my approach to disability will be revisionary and contrary to many common-sense intuitions about who is disabled. However, these implications constitute a feature, not a bug. Our present intuitions concerning what constitutes disability often reflect prejudice and bias, and should be altered. Further, our account of disability should change over time, and reflect what individuals are able to do, and what we think they ought to be able to do. The problem of disability is the problem of losing significant opportunities—and not the ‘problem’ of deviation from the species norm, or the loss of our irrelevant opportunities—and our understanding of disability should be reoriented to reflect this.