Skip to main content
Log in

On Husserl’s Theory of Alien Experience in the Logical Investigations

  • Theoretical / Philosophical Paper
  • Published:
Human Studies Aims and scope Submit manuscript

    We’re sorry, something doesn't seem to be working properly.

    Please try refreshing the page. If that doesn't work, please contact support so we can address the problem.

Abstract

This paper tackles Husserl’s early analysis of alien experience and its relation to the methodological framework of the Logical Investigations (LI). Since intersubjectivity first becomes a central theme for Husserl in his writings of 1905 (Seefeld Blätter), less attention is usually paid to his analysis of our experience of other minds in the LI. In this context, I attempt to highlight both the fundamental insights gained by Husserl in this analysis that will also remain key for his later accounts of empathy, as well as the challenges alien experiences raises for the theoretical framework of LI. I begin by discussing the main relevant traits of the phenomenological project of LI as a preparatory endeavor for the elucidation of logical objectualities, and the radical way in which Husserl defines its domain, i.e., the sphere of immanent content. Then I analyse Husserl’s understanding of alien experience in terms of an indicative unity based on associative motivations. I argue that, in doing this, Husserl accounts for a non-inferential intuitive access to other minds and, at the same time, maintains their essential alienness. Finally, I show that this account rests on what I call an “intentional contamination” of Husserl’s reductive method of LI.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. LI I (1984: 6 [166]). Where an English translation is available, the original pages are first indicated, followed in square brackets by the pages of the translation.

  2. See Text nr. 1, Individualität von Ich und Icherlebnissen. Der Unterschied der Individuen (Seefeld 1905), in Hua XIII (1973: 1–20). For Husserl’s influences in turning toward this subject and his use of the concept of empathy, see Kern (1973: XXIV–XXXIII; 2019: 11f.), Ferencz-Flatz (2014: 91–95), Zahavi (2014: 125–132).

  3. For this, see Text nr. 6, Aus den Vorlesungen “Grundprobleme der Phänomenologie” Wintersemester 1910/11, as well as Text nr. 5, Vorbereitung zum Kolleg 1910/11, both in Hua XIII (1973: 77–235).

  4. Concerning Husserl’s exclusion of the relevance of intersubjective communication for his theory of significance in LI, see Bernet et al. (1996: 144f.).

  5. Be it inductive, deductive, or abductive.

  6. See LI I (1984: 8ff. [167 ff.]); HuaM III (2001: 61f.) On the task of phenomenology in LI, see also Benoist (2003); Peucker (2002: 160–168).

  7. “[…] eine etwas differenzierte Analyse der Wortbedeutungen,” as cited by Husserl in Zwei Fragmente zum Entwurf einer Vorrede zur zweiten Auflage der Logischen Untersuchungen (September 1913) (Hua XX/1, 2002: 311).

  8. See, in this respect, Brentano’s fourth habilitation thesis according to which the only true method of psychology is the method of natural science (Brentano, 1968: 137).

  9. In the first edition, §6, the third additional note began by saying “Phenomenology is descriptive psychology” (LI I, 1984: 24 [176]). More precisely, this statement was part of a possible argument which Husserl formulates and rejects in the same note, albeit he does not explicitly reject the denomination of “descriptive psychology,” adding only that “[...] it will be good if we rather speak of ‘phenomenology’ than of descriptive psychology”. (LI I, 1984: 24 [177]). Looking back on his endeavor of 1900/01, Husserl states in Zwei Fragmente…, that “[d]e facto waren die Analysen als Wesensanalysen durchgeführt, aber nicht überall in klarem reflektivem Bewusstsein” (Hua XX/1, 2002: 312). Concerning Brentano’s concept of descriptive psychology, see Kamitz (1987), Moran (2020), Tănăsescu (2021: 345–407). On the changes of Husserl’s concept of phenomenology between the first and the second edition of LI, see Peucker (2002: 168–181). Regarding Husserl’s complex critique of Brentanian descriptive psychology, see Bejinariu (2022a), Moran (2000), Rollinger (2004), Fisette (2010), Stepanians (2013), Tănăsescu (2021: 408–425).

  10. The reflexive turning away from worldly objects does not entail something like the negation of their experience. On the contrary, Husserl’s aim is to access the immanent sphere of their constitution which has a fundamentally different character than that of the world, being a sphere of cogitationes (see Hua III/1, 1976: 77ff.). This means that the objects of our reflexive acts are no longer worldly objects but those precise acts in which the worldly objects are themselves constituted. The necessary reflexive shift of the phenomenological gaze from the level of constituted intentional objectivities to the real (reell), the descriptive level is also the source of a significant difficulty of the phenomenological endeavor that Husserl mentions in his Introduction to the second volume of LI as concerning the communication of the analysis’s results: “Completely self-evident truths of essence, established by the most exact analysis, must be expounded by way of expressions whose rich variety does not compensate for the fact that they only fit familiar natural objects, while the experiences in which such objects become constituted for consciousness, can be directly referred to only by way of a few highly ambiguous words such as ‘sensation,’ ‘perception,’ ‘presentation’ etc” (LI I, 1984: 15 [171]). This difficulty aside, reflexion proper cannot maintain more or less tacitly any sort of transcendent orientation, since its source of evidence and precision is an adequate immanent perception in which “[…] perception and perceived form essentially an unmediated unity, that of a single concrete cogitatio. Here the perceiving includes its Object in itself in such a manner that it only can be separated abstractively […]” (Hua III/1, 1976: 78 [79]). This centering of the analysis in the immanent sphere is nothing else than a first formulation of what Husserl will later call the “principle of all principles” (Hua III/1, 1976: 43f. [44 f.]) to which he explicitly connects it in Zwei Fragmente…: “Es gilt für den Philosophen, sich radikal zum ‘Prinzip aller Prinzipien’ zu bekennen, das an ihn, der ja ‘absolute’ Erkenntnis anstrebt […] die Forderung stellt, eben nicht von oben her zu konstruieren, sondern alle Erkenntnis auf die letzte Quelle, auf das ‘Sehen’ zurückzuführen” (Hua XX/1, 2002: 280).

  11. LI II (1984: 368 [352, note 6]).

  12. LI II (1984: 413 [354, note 26]).

  13. I follow in this respect Lohmar (2012) who rightfully showed that “Die jetzt gegebenen reellen Bestände bilden in den Logischen Untersuchungen weitgehend das letzte und grundlegende, rechtgebende Erfahrungsfeld” (Lohmar, 2012: 7). However, Lohmar (2012) also offers a reading of this reduction that may come forth as too strong: “Das Resultat bzw. das Residuum der Reduktion ist ein Fluss von reellen Beständen (empiristisch gedeutet: sinnliche Eindrücke und Empfindungen) in allen Sinnesfeldern” (Lohmar, 2012: 10). It is however not clear that, for Husserl, the flux of real constituents is comprised exclusively of sensations or sense-data since, besides the sensible contents of acts, among the real (reell) constituents there are also the acts themselves (LI II, 1984: 356ff. [82 ff.]; HuaM III, 2001: 235f.), act-characters and moments (HuaM III, 2001: 101f., 237), time-sensations (LI II, 1984: 369 [88]), etc.

  14. For a detailed account of the relation between logic objectivities and subjectivity, see Bernet (2002).

  15. On Husserl’s concept of apperception, see Lohmar (1993); Dwyer (2007). For a discussion concerning the content-apperception scheme in the context of Husserl’s theory of time-consciousness, see De Warren (2009: 111–117, 134–180). A critical take on Husserl’s interpretative account of perception and a concurrent understanding of sensations as presentative contents are developed in Hopp (2008).

  16. See LI II (1984: 646ff. [260ff.]) and HuaM III (2001: 129).

  17. For an account of association as the origin of indication in LI, see Brudzińska (2019: 30–34).

  18. Though recently it has been argued that phenomenology makes use of some sort of abductive reasoning or inference to the best explanation in its hypothesis generation and justification practices (see Reynolds 2022), Husserl’s way of conceiving indication in LI excludes all types of inference, not only the deductive or inductive ones that generate necessary or infinitely probable conclusions. To be sure, his claim is that reflection on the indicative connection shows that there are no subjective acts of judgment or inferring that would instantiate objective reasoning patterns. In the case of indication, we are no longer situated, as Husserl holds, under an “ideal jurisdiction,” because we are dealing with connections between convictions. Or, in the case of abductive reasoning or inference to the best explanation, there are, of course, involved acts of judgment that instantiate an “ideal” content, i.e, objective propositions regarding the probability of the explanation. Hence, in Husserl’s words: “one thing is sure, that to talk of an indication is not to presuppose a definite relation to considerations of probability” (LI I, 1984: 35 [186]).

  19. As Brudzinska (2019) argues, “[…] scheinen die Überlegungen Husserls bereits hier das Fundament für die spätere Egologisierung der Assoziation zu legen. Die egologische Möglichkeit zeichnet sich hier ab, indem es zum Aufmerken erster inhaltlicher, passiv fungierender Motivierungsrelationen und habitueller Bedingtheiten des subjektiven Lebens kommt. Die erwähnte Thematisierung der motivierenden Zusammenhänge, die in gestifteten Dispositionen oder Überzeugungen gründen, erlaubt es sogar–wenn auch die subjekt-genetischen Gesetzmäßigkeiten in dieser Phase noch nicht explizit thematisch werden–, von Vorboten einer genetisch-egologischen Perspektive zu sprechen” (Brudzinska, 2019: 33).

  20. For a complex discussion of the different facets of the relation between Husserl’s concept of empathy and intuitivity, see Ferencz-Flatz (2014).

  21. “Apperception is our surplus, which is found in experience itself, in its descriptive content as opposed to the raw existence of sense: it is the act-character which as it were ensouls sense and is in essence such as to make us perceive this or that object, see this tree, e.g., hear this ringing, smell this scent of flowers etc. etc.” (LI II, 1984: 399 [105]).

  22. On Husserl’s conception of objective meaning, see Benoist (2003), Beyer (1996), Soldati (2008).

  23. For a recent version of this argument with a focus on Husserl’s account of occasional expressions, see Ferencz-Flatz (2022).

  24. “Critically it may be remarked here that the concepts of the ‘intentive’ and the ‘cognitional essence’ which were established in the Logische Untersuchungen are indeed correct but are capable of a second interpretation since they can be essentially understood as expressions not only of noetic but also of noematic essences, and that the noematic interpretation, as carried through there one-sidedly in framing the concept of the judgment in pure logic is precisely not the one to be used in framing the judgment-concept of pure logic […]” (Hua III/1, 1976: 217 [228f.]). See also Hua III/1 (1976: 296 [308]) and Lohmar (2012: 13).

  25. To quote Husserl’s famous Panoptikum example in the Fifth Logical Investigation (see LI II, 1984: 458f. [137f.]).

References

  • Bejinariu, A. (2022a). Descriptive and intentional contents: Considerations on Husserl’s Logical investigations from Brentano’s empirical point of view. In I. Tănăsescu, A. Bejinariu, S.K. Gabriel, & C. Stoenescu (Eds.), Brentano and the positive philosophy of Comte and Mill: With translations of original writings on philosophy as science by Franz Brentano (pp. 371–400). De Gruyter. https://doi.org/10.1515/9783110734645-016

  • Bejinariu, A. (2022b). The intentionality of gestures and their role in monological thinking: Some remarks following Husserl. Tijdschrift voor Filosofie, 84(3), 435–456. https://doi.org/10.2143/TVF.84.3.3291500

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Benoist, J. (2003). Husserl’s Theory of Meaning in the First Logical Investigation. In D. O. Dahlstrom (Ed.), Husserl’s Logical Investigations (pp. 17–35). Kluwer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bernet, R. (2002). Different concepts of logic and their relation to subjectivity. In D. Zahavi, & F. Stjernfelt (Eds.), One Hundred Years of Phenomenology: Husserl’s Logical Investigations Revisited (pp. 19–29). Kluwer.

  • Bernet, R., Kern, I., & Marbach, E. (1996). Edmund Husserl: Darstellung seines Denkens. Felix Meiner.

  • Beyer, C. (1996). Von Bolzano zu Husserl: Eine Untersuchung über den Ursprung der phanomenologischen Bedeutungslehre. Kluwer.

  • Bouckaert, B. (2002). The Puzzling Case of Alterity in Husserl’s Logical Investigations. In D. Zahavi, & F. Stjernfelt (Eds.), One Hundred Years of Phenomenology: Husserl’s Logical Investigations Revisited (pp. 185–198). Kluwer.

  • Brentano, F. (1968). Über die Zukunft der Philosophie. (O. Kraus & P. Weingartner (Eds.). Felix Meiner.

  • Brudzińska, J. (2019). Bi-Valenz der Erfahrung. Assoziation, Imaginäres und Trieb in der Genesis der Subjektivität bei Husserl und Freud. Springer.

  • CM = Husserl, E. (1973). Cartesianische Meditationen und Pariser Vorträge (S. Strasser, Ed.). Martinus Nijhoff. [(1960). Cartesian Meditations. An Introduction to Phenomenology (D. Cairns, Trans.). Springer.]

  • De Warren, N. (2009). Husserl and the promise of time: Subjectivity in transcendental phenomenology. Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Dwyer, J. D. (2007). Husserl’s appropriation of the psychological concepts of apperception and attention. Husserl Studies, 23, 83–118. https://doi.org/10.1007/s10743-007-9020-4

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ferencz-Flatz, C. (2014). Zur “Anschaulichkeit” der Einfühlung bei Husserl. Tijdschrift Voor Filosofie, 76, 87–118. https://doi.org/10.2143/TVF.76.1.3017241

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ferencz-Flatz, C. (2022). Gesten als Okkasionelle Bedeutungserfüllungen. Husserl Studies, 38, 1–16. https://doi.org/10.1007/s10743-021-09295-w

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fisette, D. (2010). Descriptive psychology and natural sciences: Husserl’s early Criticism of Brentano. In C. Ierna, H. Jacobs, & F. Mattens (Eds.), Philosophy, phenomenology, sciences (pp. 221–253). Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Hopp, W. (2008). Husserl on sensation, perception, and interpretation. Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 38(2), 219–246. https://doi.org/10.1353/cjp.0.0013

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hua III/1 = Husserl, E. (1976). Ideen zu einer reinen Phänomenologie und phänomenologischen Philosophie. Erstes Buch: Allgemeine Einführung in die reine Phänomenologie (K. Schumann, Ed.). Martinus Nijhoff. [(1983). Ideas Pertaining to a Pure Phenomenology and to a Phenomenological Philosophy (F. Kersten, Trans.). Martinus Nijhoff.]

  • Hua IV = Husserl, E. (1952) Ideen zu einer reinen Phänomenologie und phänomenologischen Philosophie. Zweites Buch: Phänomenologische Untersuchungen zur Konstitution (M. Biemel, Ed.). Martinus Nijhoff.

  • Hua XI = Husserl, E. (1966). Analysen zur passiven Synthesis. Aus Vorlesungs- und Forschungsmanuskripten 1918–1926 (M. Fleischer, Ed.). Martinus Nijhoff.

  • Hua XIII = Husserl, E. (1973). Zur Phänomenologie der Intersubjektivität: Texte aus dem Nachlass. Erster Teil: 1905–1920 (I. Kern, Ed.). Springer.

  • Hua XX/1 = Husserl, E. (2002). Logische Untersuchungen Ergänzungsband: Erster Teil: Entwürfe zur Umarbeitung der VI. Untersuchung und zur Vorrede für die Neuauflage der Logischen Untersuchungen (Sommer 1913) (U. Melle, Ed.). Springer.

  • Hua XX/2 = Husserl, E. (2005). Logische Untersuchungen Ergänzungsband: Zweiter Teil: Texte für die Neufassung der VI. Untersuchung. Zur Phänomenologie des Ausdrucks und der Erkenntnis (1893/941921) (U. Melle, Ed.). Springer.

  • HuaM III = Husserl, E. (2001). Allgemeine Erkenntnistheorie: Vorlesung 1902/03 (E. Schumann, Ed.). Springer.

  • Kamitz, R. (1987). Deskriptive Psychologie als unerlässliche Grundlage wissenschaftlicher Philosophie? Eine Darstellung und kritische Auseinandersetzung des Psychologismus Franz Brentanos. Conceptus, 21(53/54), 161–180.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kern, I. (1973). Einleitung des Herausgebers. In Hua XIII (pp. XVII–XLVIII).

  • Kern, I. (2019). Husserl’s phenomenology of intersubjectivity. In F. Kjosavik, C. Beyer, & C. Fricke (Eds.), Husserl’s phenomenology of intersubjectivity historical interpretations and contemporary applications (pp. 11–89). Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • LI I & II = Husserl, E. (1984). Logische Untersuchungen: Zweiter Band: Untersuchungen zur Phänomenologie und Theorie der Erkenntnis (U. Panzer, Ed.). Springer. [(1970). Logical Investigations (2 vols., J. N. Findlay, Trans.). Routledge and Kegan Paul.]

  • Lohmar, D. (1993). Grundzüge eines Synthesis-Modells der Auffassung: Husserl über den Ordnungsgrad sinnlicher Vorgegebenheiten und die Elemente einer Phänomenologie der Auffassung. Husserl Studies, 10, 111–141. https://doi.org/10.1007/BF01386953

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lohmar, D. (2012). Zur Vorgeschichte der transzendentalen Reduktion in den Logischen Untersuchungen: Die unbekannte “Reduktion auf den reellen Bestand.” Husserl Studies, 28, 1–24. https://doi.org/10.1007/s10743-011-9096-8

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Moran, D. (2000). Husserl’s Critique of Brentano in the Logical Investigations. Manuscrito, 23(2), 163–205.

    Google Scholar 

  • Moran, D. (2020). Brentano’s concept of descriptive psychology. In D. Fisette, G. Fréchette, & F. Stadler (Eds.), Franz Brentano and Austrian Philosophy (pp. 73–100). Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Peucker, H. (2002). Von der Psychologie zur Phänomenologie. Husserls Weg in die Phänomenologie der “Logischen Untersuchungen. Felix Meiner.

  • Reynolds, J. (2022). Phenomenology, abduction, and argument: Avoiding an ostrich epistemology. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 22, 557–574.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rollinger, R. D. (2004). Brentano and Husserl. In D. Jacquette (Ed.), The Cambridge Companion to Brentano (pp. 255–276). Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Sokolowski, R. (2002). Semiotics in Husserl’s Logical Investigations. In D. Zahavi & F. Stjernfelt (Eds.), One hundred years of phenomenology. Husserl’s Logical Investigations Revisited (pp. 171–183). Kluwer.

  • Soldati, G. (2008). Die Objektivität der Bedeutung (I. Logische Untersuchung, §§ 24–35). In V. Meyer (Ed.), Edmund Husserl: Logische Untersuchungen (pp. 61–75). Akademie Verlag.

  • Stepanians, M. (2013). “Es war mir nicht gegeben, Mitglied seiner Schule zu bleiben.”: Husserls Kritik an Brentano. In S. Centrone (Ed.), Versuche über Husserl (pp. 33–64). Felix Meiner.

  • Tănăsescu, I. (2021). Psychologie, Seiendes, Phantasie bei Franz Brentano. De Gruyter. https://doi.org/10.1515/9783110524550

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Zahavi, D. (2014). Self & other: Exploring subjectivity, empathy, and shame. Oxford.

Download references

Aknowledgement

I would like to thank Cristian Ciocan and the two anonymous reviewers for their valuable comments and suggestions on earlier versions of this article. Funding was provided by the Ministry of Research, Innovation and Digitization, CNCS/CCCDI—UEFISCDI (grant number PN-III-P1-1.1-PD-2021-0735).

Funding

This work was supported by Ministry of Research, Innovation and Digitization, CNCS/CCCDI—UEFISCDI (grant number PN-III-P1-1.1-PD-2021-0735).

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Alexandru Bejinariu.

Ethics declarations

Conflict of interest

The author has no competing interests to declare that are relevant to the content of this article.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Springer Nature or its licensor (e.g. a society or other partner) holds exclusive rights to this article under a publishing agreement with the author(s) or other rightsholder(s); author self-archiving of the accepted manuscript version of this article is solely governed by the terms of such publishing agreement and applicable law.

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Bejinariu, A. On Husserl’s Theory of Alien Experience in the Logical Investigations. Hum Stud (2023). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10746-023-09696-0

Download citation

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10746-023-09696-0

Keywords

Navigation