Skip to main content
Log in

Interpreting rights and culture: ExtendingLaw's empire

  • Published:
Res Publica Aims and scope Submit manuscript

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

References

  1. See, e.g., Hurst Hannum,Autonomy, Sovereignty, and Self-Determination: The Accommodation of Conflicting Rights, rev'd. ed. (Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania, 1996).

    Google Scholar 

  2. For favourable evaluations of the need for aboriginal self-government powers in Canada see, for example, Patrick Macklem, “Normative Dimensions of an Aboriginal Right of Self-Government”,Queen's Law Journal 21 (1995), 173–219; Royal Commission on Aboriginal Peoples,Bridging the Cultural Divide: A Report on Aboriginal People and Criminal Justice in Canada (Ottawa: Royal Commission on Aboriginal Peoples, 1996); Jeremy Webber, “Individuality, Equality and Difference: justifications for a Parallel System of Aboriginal Justice”, in Royal Commission on Aboriginal Peoples,Aboriginal Peoples and the Justice System: Report of the National Round Table on Aboriginal Justice Issues (Canada: Minister of Supply and Services, 1993), 133–60.

    Google Scholar 

  3. These issues have been raised in a recent Supreme Court of Canada case:Native Women's Association of Canada et al. v.The Queen; Inuit Tapirisat of Canada et al., Interveners (1994) 119 D.L.R. (4th) 224. For different views on the applicability of human rights legislation to aboriginal self-governments, compare Ovide Mercredi and Mary Ellen Turpel,In the Rapids: Navigating the Future of First Nations (Toronto: Penguin Books Canada, 1993), 96–106, with Royal Commission on Aboriginal Peoples,Bridging the Cultural Divide, supra n.2,A Report on Aboriginal People and Criminal Justice in Canada (Ottawa: Royal Commission on Aboriginal Peoples, 1996) at 258–75.

  4. See, e.g., Amnesty International,Human Rights Are Women's Rights, Action/Technique Document ACT 77/001/1995 (1995), as available on http://www.amnesty.se/women/242e.htm accessed on 24 February 1997, at 58–59 (showing conflicts between theShari'a offence ofZina—extramarital sex—and Pakistan rape laws); Radhika Coomaraswamy, “To Bellow Like a Cow: Women, Ethnicity, and the Discourse of Rights”, inHuman Rights of Women: National and International Perspectives, ed. Rebecca J. Cook (Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania, 1994), 39–57.

  5. See, e.g., Arati Rao, “The Politics of Gender and Culture in International Human Rights Discouse”, inWomen's Rights, Human Rights: International Feminist Perspectives, ed. Julie Peters and Andrea Wolper (New York: Routledge, 1995), 167–75; Abdullahi Ahmed An-Na'im, “State Responsibility Under International Human Rights Law to Change Religious and Customary Laws”, in Cook,supra n.4, ed. Rebecca J. Cook (Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania, 1994), 39–57, at 167–88.

    Google Scholar 

  6. at 137.

    Google Scholar 

  7. E.g.,, at 114.

    Google Scholar 

  8. E.g.,.

    Google Scholar 

  9. , at 173–74; Ann Elizabeth Mayer, “Cultural Particularism as a Bar to Women's Rights: Reflections on the Middle Eastern Experience”, in Peters and Wolper,supra n.5, ed. Julie Peters and Andrea Wolper (New York: Routledge, 1995), 176–88, at 180; An-Na'im,supra n.5, Abdullahi Ahmed An-Na'im, “State Responsibility Under International Human Rights Law to Change Religious and Customary Laws”, in Cook,supra n.4, ed. Rebecca J. Cook (Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania, 1994), 39–57, at 167–88, at 174 and 181–85.

    Google Scholar 

  10. , at 174.

    Google Scholar 

  11. Ann Funder, “De Minimis Non Curat Lex: The Clitoris, Culture and the Law”,Transnational Law & Contemporary Problems 3 (1993), 417–67, at 441.

    Google Scholar 

  12. See, e.g., Eugene Kamenka, “Human Rights, Peoples' Rights”, inThe Rights of Peoples, ed. James Crawford (Oxford: Clarendon, 1988) 127–39, at 127–30 (social context, specificity, and contextual development of rights).

    Google Scholar 

  13. , at 442–43.

    Google Scholar 

  14. , at 463 and 467.

    Google Scholar 

  15. In any event, it should be noted that applying an international human rights critique is alsounavoidable, as all modern governments, including the proposed aboriginal governments, are bound by international human rights norms: Douglas Sanders, “Developments at the United Nations: 1994”,Canadian Native Law Reporter 4 [1994], 12–16, at 14.

    Google Scholar 

  16. , at 183.

    Google Scholar 

  17. This point raises important questions about interpretation and meaning, a full discussion of which is beyond the scope of this article. For a good introduction to these questions from an interpretive perspective, see generally Ronald Dworkin,Law's Empire (Cambridge, Ma.: Belknap Press of Harvard University, 1986) [hereafter “Dworkin,LE”]. For present purposes, by the term “implementation” I mean the act of translating the more abstract values underpinning rights into actual rules and procedures in our everyday world. Cf. John Finnis,Natural Law and Natural Rights (Oxford: Clarendon, 1980), 284–90 (providing a good example of this process in the context of describing how natural law can be the basis for such commonplace rules as those governing the use of roads).

    Google Scholar 

  18. Ronald Dworkin, “Is Law a System of Rules?” inThe Philosophy of Law, ed. R.M. Dworkin, (Oxford: Oxford University 1977), 37–65; Dworkin,, at 96, 152, and 244.

    Google Scholar 

  19. , at 87 and 410 (law as form of interpretation), and 52–53 (constructive interpretation);.

    Google Scholar 

  20. , at 65–66.

    Google Scholar 

  21. , at 65–68, 230–31, and 285.

    Google Scholar 

  22. Principles are used to incline a decision one way or another (e.g., in the case where no rule seems to apply directly), and provide the underpinning that makes rules binding:, 37–65; Dworkin,LE, supra n. 17 at 55–59. Additionally, they provide the core of Dworkin's concept of integrity (as integrity is “consistency in principle”): at 167.

    Google Scholar 

  23. Note that Dworkin includes the potential for a certain degree of relaxation of fit in order to make interpretation more broadly applicable, but that fit cannot be completely elastic, and sometimes the interpreter will have to abandon the project if it is not satisfied:. at 230–31, 237.

    Google Scholar 

  24. , at 88–89. Also, all interpretation is done within the constraining ambit of thepurpose of the practice as understood by the legal community (the “interpretive community”).

    Google Scholar 

  25. , at 49–53.

    Google Scholar 

  26. , at 228–38 (chain novel metaphor).

    Google Scholar 

  27. Dworkin, “Law, Philosophy,”,, at 469; , at 58–59.

    Google Scholar 

  28. Dworkin, “Law, Philosophy”,, at 471, 474, and , at 98, respectively. Cf. , 92–96.

    Google Scholar 

  29. , at 413. Note however that Dworkin isnot saying that law is identical to politics, merely fitting his theory within the broader political context.

    Google Scholar 

  30. , at 248–49; cf.., 301. Stephen Guest, inRonald Dworkin (Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press, 1992), at 38, argues that “Dworkin's theory is that legal practices are only to make sense against the background of a moral theory based on the idea of equality,” Dworkin himself understands that law, when faced with its most difficult challenges, must refer to the structure of the political community as part of its process of interpretation: “Judges who accept the interpretive ideal of integrity decide hard cases by trying to find, in some coherent set of principles about people's rights and duties, the best constructive interpretation of the political structure and legal doctrine of their community,”, at 255.

    Google Scholar 

  31. , at 243; see generally,, chs. 6 and 7. Integrity also has a transformative function as, in Dworkin's view, a community that works under a vision of integrity will develop and encourage greater responsibility, participation and commitment on the part of its citizens:., 189–90.

    Google Scholar 

  32. , at 167. As pointed out by Guest,, at 40, integrity requires more than simple consistency because the law must be able to correct itself rather than blindly follow past mistakes: “Bare consistency ... is an impossible requirement because we all accept, as properly characteristic of legal argument, that some previous decisions are mistaken.”

    Google Scholar 

  33. at 339 and note 8. Dworkin calls this “textual integrity” and allows it to embrace “fairness” (roughly meaning respect for democratically expressed public opinion), as well as the legislative history of statutes (although only as “political decisions”):, 338–43.

    Google Scholar 

  34. , at 405–406. Dworkin takes this point further by arguing that consistency in principle can be seen as an independent value (“commitment to consistency in principle valued for its own sake”), and thus that integrity can provide a vantage point from which to adjudicate between the competing political virtues of fairness, justice and procedural due process:, 164–67 and 176–78.

    Google Scholar 

  35. , at 226.

    Google Scholar 

  36. , at 401–406. Thus, as argued by Guest,, at 41, integrity is a constraining feature of Dworkin's theory: “[Integrity's] function is to constrain states in the real world, where decisions are often injust but fair”.

    Google Scholar 

  37. Jack Donnelly, for example, inUniversal Human Rights in Theory and Practice (London: Cornell University Press, 1989), 16–19, examines the source of human rights and states (at 17) that “[h]uman rights represent a social choice of a particular moral vision of human potentiality, which rests on a particular substantive account of the minimum requirements of a life of dignity.” Note howver that “human dignity” is itself a strongly contested concept, as illustrated by the debates about Dworkin's use of the term in his work,Life's Dominion (London: Harper Collins, 1993). See, e.g., Bradley W. Miller, “A Time to Kill: Ronald Dworkin and the Ethics of Euthanasia”,Res Publica 2 (1996) 31–61, at 50–51.

    Google Scholar 

  38. , at 266–75.

    Google Scholar 

  39. E.g.,, at 219–24 (integrity as also bringing flexibility).

    Google Scholar 

  40. Note that this problem may arise withinany community. If all social practices or communities continually re-interpret and re-constitute themselves, as suggested earlier, this conflict of purpose, as pointed out by Emilios A. Christodoulidis in “The Suspect Intimacy Between Law and Political Community: The Case ofLaw's Empire”, Archiv für Rechts-und Sozialphilosophie 80 (1994), 1–18, at 14, “may turn a process of self-revision into a process of breakdown and disintegration of communities”, (citations omitted).

  41. Ronald Dworkin, “Indeterminacy and Law”, inPositivism Today, ed. Stephen Guest (Aldershot: Dartmouth, 1996), 1–9, at 2, states: “A belief in indeterminacy is a positive claim, and it needs a positive reason or assumption to support it. There are three possible views I might take about the abortion issue, excluding uncertainy, but I am as much (or as little) in need of an argument for the third view—indeterminacy—as I am of an argument for either of the other two.” Inibid., Ronald Dworkin, “Indeterminacy and Law”, inPositivism Today, ed. Stephen Guest (Aldershort: Dartmouth, 1996), 1–9 at 8, when discussing the level of difficulty in proving indeterminacy he says: “Someone defending the view that no such reason can in fact tip the balance either way in any controversial case faces an enormously difficult task, much more difficult than faced by someone who wants to argue for one decision rather than another in a particular case.” This is why, inLaw's Empire, supra n.17, This point raises important questions about interpretation and meaning, a full discussion of which is beyond the scope of this article. For a good introduction to these questions from an interpretive perspective, see generally Ronald Dworkin,Law's Empire (Cambridge, Ma.: Belknap Press of Harvard University, 1986) [hereafter “Dworkin,LE”]. For present purposes, by the term “implementation” I mean the act of translating the more abstract values underpinning rights into actual rules and procedures in our everyday world. Cf. John Finnis,Natural Law and Natural Rights (Oxford: Clarendon, 1980), 284–90 (providing a good example of this process in the context of describing how natural law can be the basis for such commonplace rules as those governing the use of roads). at 271–75 (and end notes), Dworkin criticises the contention of critical legal studies scholars that law displays “fundamental contradictions in principle” without offering proof of any such contradictions.

    Google Scholar 

  42. Dworkin, “Indeterminacy and Law”,, at 4–5, offers his own example of such a justification for the indeterminacy position in the context of the question of whether Picasso is a greater genius than Beethoven.

    Google Scholar 

  43. Christodoulidis,supra n.40, Note that this problem may arise withinany community. If all social practices or communities continually re-interpret and re-constitute themselves, as suggested earlier, this conflict of purpose, as pointed out by Emilios A. Christodoulidis in “The Suspect Intimacy Between Law and Political Community: The Case ofLaw's Empire”, Archiv für Rechts- und Sozialphilosophie 80 (1994), 1–18, at 14, “may turn a process of self-revision into a process of breakdown and disintegration of communities” (citations omitted). at 17. I am indebted to William E. Conklin for his insight about the key role of pre-adjudicative agreement or, more broadly, a shared commitment to justice.

  44. See Dworkin,LE, supra n.17, Ronald Dworkin,Law's Empire (Cambridge, Ma.: Belknap Press of Harvard University, 1986), at 66–67, and 91–92, for the first four and the fifth points respectively.

    Google Scholar 

  45. This is confusing because even though the demands of integrity would seem to push us towards a uniform set of principles that would apply toall areas of law (i.e,, in tort, contract and criminal), the current divisions or separate categories of law (which Dworkin calls “departments”) must be accepted because integrity also requires general consistency with past practice. This is why Dworkin posits his general principle of “local priority” — which demands that interpretation work from the lowest, or most local department of law and only look beyond it when offered no choice (the image here being interpretation in concentric circles):, at 250–54 and 402–403.

    Google Scholar 

  46. , at 102 and 208, respectively.

    Google Scholar 

  47. Dworkin, “Law, Philosophy”,, at 473;accord; ibid. Dworkin, “Law, Philosophy”,Law's Empire (Cambridge, Ma.: Belknap Press of Harvard University, 1986), 470.

    Google Scholar 

  48. Dworkin, “Indeterminacy and Law”, at 7, cautions that “[i]t would be a serious mistake to export a justification designed for one domain... to another without very great care.”

    Google Scholar 

  49. For example,, at 185–86, when speaking about the relations of US states in a federal system, Dworkin states that “[i]ntegrity holdswithin political communities,not among them, so any opinion we have about the scope of the requirement of coherence makes assumptions about the size and character of these communities” (emphasis added). Thus there would seem to be no basis for comparison of the laws of each state. Dworkin gets round this problem at the latter page only by arguing that integrity holds at the federal level as well as state level (giving rise to the idea of integrity as applicable to all US law, not just the law of each state). He does not raise the possibility of integrity working at an international level. At another point,ibid., Ronald Dworkin,Law's Empire (Cambridge, Ma.: Belknap Press of Harvard University, 1986), 195–206, he deals with the kind of situation where the purpose of the community is not at issue, but the compatibility of a particularpractice with that purpose is. Dworkin looks at this in the context of obligations that may arise within different types of communities, and contrasts “bare” and “true” types of communities (the latter giving rise to obligations and the formet not doing so). The example he uses here is that of arranged marriages, an example which parallels the conflict at the centre of our discussion, that between individual rights and culture:ibid. Ronald Dworkin, Law's Empire (Cambridge, Ma.: Belknap Press of Harvard University, 1986), 204–205. The distinction he makes that allows internal criticism of the practice of arranging marriages becomes that between bare and true communities, with interpretation serving as the mechanism by which to distinguish the two, and only the latter giving rise to serious obligations. Interpretation in this case serves two roles, to determine the nature of the community (and hence the obligation), and then later, if a true community exists, to help decide the conflict between obligations owed to that community and other grounds of rights. But note that in examining this issue Dworkin always works within the context of ashared purpose towards which all interpretation can strive.

    Google Scholar 

  50. , at 113.

    Google Scholar 

  51. , at 52–53 (constructive interpretation), 164–67, 176–78 and 405–407 (integrity).

    Google Scholar 

  52. A more abstract form of constructive interpretation, rather than a specifically legal one, is preferable. Cf. Christodoulidis,supra n. 40 Emilios A. Christodoulidis, in “The Suspect Intimacy Between Law and Political Community: The Case ofLaw's Empire”, Archiv für Rechts- und Sozialphilosophie 80 (1994), 1–18, at 15–17 (dangers of using law as a meta-narrative).

  53. Dworkin, “Law, Philosophy”,, at 471–72.

    Google Scholar 

  54. This distinction is similar to the one that Dworkin uses regarding the difference between a “concept” and a “conception” of law, with the former being the broader (unifying) purpose against which we interpret the subpurposes:, at 70–71.

    Google Scholar 

  55. Christodoulidis,supra n.40, Emilios A. Christodoulidis in “The Suspect Intimacy Between Law and Political Community: The Case ofLaw's Empire“, Archiv für Rechts- und Sozialphilosophie 80 (1994), 1–18, at 5.

  56. Cf. Christodoulidis,supra n. 40 Emilios A. Christodoulidis in “The Suspect Intimacy Between Law and Political Community: The Case ofLaw's Empire”, Archiv für Rechts- und Soziaphilosophie 80 (1994), 1–18, at 3–4 (centrality of community to interpretation).

  57. , at 52;accord: ibid. Ronald Dworkin,Law's Empire (Cambridge, Ma.: Belknap Press of Harvard University, 1986), 228.

    Google Scholar 

  58. , at 273.

    Google Scholar 

  59. , at 272–75.

    Google Scholar 

  60. , ch. 4.

    Google Scholar 

  61. This kind of vision is hinted at by Dworkin at the end of his work when he distinguishes between “inclusive” and “pure” integrity:, at 404–407. The former is the kind of integrity that is used to help decide how the law can best reflect the often incommensurable demands of justice, fairness and procedural due process by restricting its gaze to the institutions and compartments of law; the latter, pure form is the higher, more abstract vision of integrity that allows judges to make these kinds of calculations by “pursu[ing] coherence in the principles of justice that flow through and unite different departments of law”:ibid. Ronald Dworkin,Law's Empire (Cambridge, Ma.: Belknap Press of Harvard University, 1986), 406. This entails looking at the law from the perspective of the community as a whole, being a “purified interpretation speak[ing] ... directly to community personified”:ibid. Ronald Dworkin,Law's Empire (Cambridge, Ma.: Belnap Press of Harvard University, 1986), 407.

    Google Scholar 

  62. See, e.g., Catharine A. MacKinnon,Toward a Feminist Theory of the State (London: Harvard University Press, 1989), ch. 5 (consciousness raising); Maria Suarez Toro, “Popularizing Women's Human Rights at the Local Level: A Grassroots Methodology for Setting the International Agenda”, in Peters and Wolper,supra n.5, ed. Julie Peters and Andrea Wolper (New York: Routledge, 1995) at 189–94.

    Google Scholar 

  63. In looking for such a universal purpose underlying human rights we must not conflate thepurpose with the existing international human rightsframework, the latter merely being one conception of the former.

  64. Scott Davidson identifies these rights from a cross-comparison of theInternational Covenant on Civil and Political Rights, European, African and American human rights conventions. The same author goes on to argue that they also representjus cogens, making then non-derogable in both human rights law and international law in general: Davidson,Human Rights (Buckingham: Open University Press, 1993), at 40–41 and “Appendix 1: Comparative Table of the Rights and Freedoms Protected by the Major Human Rights Instruments”. See also the various lists discussed in: Donnelly,Universal Human Rights, supra n.37, Jack Donnelly, for example, inUniversal Human Rights in Theory and Practice (London: Cornell University Press, 1989) ch. 2; G.J.H. van Hoof, “Human Rights in a Multi-Cultural World: The Need for Continued Dialogue”, inEssays in Honour of Wang Tieya, ed. Ronald St. John MacDonald (Dordrecht: Martinus Nijhoff, 1994), 877–91. Both of the latter two authors offer their own core lists as well, at pages 24–25 and 890 respectively.

    Google Scholar 

  65. E.g., at 41 states: “All human rights are ‘basic rights’ in the fundamental sense that systematic violations ofany human right preclude realizing a life of full human dignity—that is, prevent one from enjoying the minimum conditions necessary for a life worthy of a human being.”

    Google Scholar 

  66. , at 2; see alsoidem, Jack Donnelly, for example, inUniversal Human Rights in Theory and Practice (London: Cornell University Press, 1989), at 23–25. The treaties and declaration referred to are theInternational Covenant on Civil and Political Rights, adopted 16 Dec. 1966, in force 23 Mar. 1976 and 28 Mar. 1979 (art. 41), 999 U.N.T.S. 171 and 1057 U.N.T.S. 407;International Covenant on Economic, Social and Cultural Rights, adopted 16 Dec. 1966, in force 3 Jan. 1976, 993 U.N.T.S. 3;Universal Declaration of Human Rights, adopted 10 Dec. 1948, G.A. Res. 217A (III), U.N. Doc. A/810, at 71 (1948).

    Google Scholar 

  67. , at 1–2; cf.ibid. Jack Donnelly, for example, inUniversal Human Rights in Theory and Practice (London: Cornell University Press, 1989), 23–27 and 60–65. This is a positivist form of universalism. But cf. Annie Bunting, “Theorizing Women's Cultural Diversity in Feminist International Human Rights Strategies”,Journal of Law & Society 20 (1993), 6–22, at 9 (summarising the different forms of universalism before strongly criticising them); Doris Elisabeth Buss, “Going Global: Feminist Theory, International Law, and the Public Private Divide”, inChallenging the Public/Private Divide: Feminism, Law, and Public Policy, ed. Susan B. Boyd (Toronto: University of Toronto Press, 1997), 360–84 (criticising universalising forms of feminist theory at the international level).

    Google Scholar 

  68. at 1; see also Jack Donnelly, “State Sovereignty and International Intervention: The Case of Human Rights”, inBeyond Westphalia? State Sovereignty and International Intervention, ed. Gene M. Lyons and Michael Mastanduno (Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press, 1995), 115–46, at 125. TheInternational Covenant on Civil and Political Rights has attracted 138 state parties, of which 58 are signatories, and theInternational Covenant on Economic, Social and Cultural Rights has attracted 136 state parties, of which 59 are signatories. When compared to the 185 states that are currently members of the United Nations, this means that almost three-quarters of the states in the UN are parties to each of these treaties. All statistics from United Nations,Multilateral Treaties Deposited with the Secretary-General, United Nations, New York ST/LEG/SER. E, status as at 23 June 1997, as available on http://www.un.org/Depts/Treaty, accessed on 2 July 1997.

    Google Scholar 

  69. , at ch.3.

    Google Scholar 

  70. at ch.6.

    Google Scholar 

  71. E.g., article 27 of theInternational Covenant on Civil and Political Rights, supra n.66.

  72. See generally, (discussing the complexity of rights and warning against the oversimplification or obfuscation of their ambiguities and conflicts).

    Google Scholar 

  73. Compare the CIA's figure of “266 nations, dependent areas, other and miscellaneous entries” to the mere 185 member states of the United Nations: US Central Intelligence Agency, “World”, inThe 1996 World Factbook, as available on http://www.odci.gov/cia/publications/nsolo/factbook/w.htm, accessed on 2 July 1997.

  74. See, e.g., Jean Bethke Elshtain, “Exporting Feminism”,Journal of International Affairs 48 (1995), 541–58 (revealing how feminists have used international human rights in a variety of innovative and unconventional ways to support their causes).

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Berry, D.S. Interpreting rights and culture: ExtendingLaw's empire . Res Publica 4, 3–28 (1998). https://doi.org/10.1007/BF02334930

Download citation

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/BF02334930

Navigation