Skip to main content
Log in

Strengthening Weak Emergence

  • Original Research
  • Published:
Erkenntnis Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

I offer an improved version of Bedau’s influential (Philos Perspect 11:375–99, 1997) account of weak emergence in light of insights from information theory. Bedau analyzes weak emergence in terms of the non-derivability of a system’s macrostates from its microstates except by simulation. However, non-derivability alone does not guarantee that a system’s macrostates are weakly emergent. Rather, it is non-derivability plus the algorithmic compressibility of the system’s macrostates that makes them weakly emergent. I argue that the resulting information-theoretic picture provides a metaphysical account of weak emergence rather than a merely epistemic one.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Fig. 1

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Of course, there are limits to how far an analogy between the weak emergence demonstrated in a cellular automaton and the relationship between microstates and macrostates of a physical system in the real world can go. As Symons emphasizes, “CA simulations provide qualitative analogies to the natural systems in question rather than measurable quantities. These analogies can be extremely useful and may give us some insight into methods for controlling the phenomenon in question. However, in practice and in application, generalizations that we derive from these models will rest entirely on the analogy between the system under consideration and the simulation. This is one of the reasons that the success of a computational models is generally judged not by its predictive power, but by the degree to which it imitates the known behavior of a target system” (2008, 482). Thus, it is not a foregone conclusion whether the sort of weak emergence that Bedau outlines will have cognates in, for instance, the realm of mental phenomena. That will depend on whether the relevant relationship between the candidate phenomenon and its system’s microstates are present.

  2. Baker (2010, 3) offers another way to understand the notion of non-derivability except by simulation present in Bedau’s work. He suggests that the notion that Bedau is working with involves equating simulation with “’iterating the microdynamic’ of the given system. Thus, a weakly emergent property or behavior in the Game of Life would be one that can be derived only by iterating the update rules time step by time step.

  3. When ‘compressibility’ appears unmodified, take it to be shorthand for ‘algorithmic compressibility’.

  4. One could, of course, draw an arbitrary compressibility threshold higher than the bare minimum that must be met for a system’s states to be counted as weakly emergent. Another option is to simply take weak emergence to be a matter of degree, as Hovda (2008) does.

  5. They reserve commitment to other doctrines, such as causal efficacy, in part because they do not take them to be necessary to make sense of science nor demanded or even warranted by contemporary scientific theory or practice.

  6. For instance, Wilson (2013, 214) initially describes Bedau’s picture as follows: “The absence of analytic or otherwise ‘compressible’ means of predicting the evolution of such systems means that the only way to find out what this behavior will be is by ‘going through the motions’: Set up the system, let it roll, and see what happens. It is this feature—namely, algorithmic incompressibility—that serves as the basis for Bedau’s account of weak emergence.” Wilson takes the account to be one that identifies weak emergence with algorithmic incompressibility. While the notion of algorithmic incompressibility does not explicitly appear in Bedau’s (1997) original account, the fact that Bedau (2013) generally uses ‘incompressible’ interchangeably with the notion of non-derivability except by simulation makes Wilson’s interpretation of Bedau (1997) a plausible one. As I argue, however, such a direct identification of weak emergence with algorithmic incompressibility is too coarse-grained to capture the relationship between these two notions that is needed for a metaphysical account of weak emergence.

References

  • Baker, A. (2010). Simulation-based definitions of emergence. Journal of Artificial Societies and Social Simulation, 13(1). https://doi.org/10.18564/jasss.1531

  • Bedau, M. (1997). Weak emergence. Philosophical Perspectives, 11, 375–399.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bedau, M. (2003). Downward causation and the autonomy of weak emergence. Principia, 6(1), 5–50.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bedau, M. (2011). Weak emergence and computer simulation. In P. Humphreys & C. Imbert (Eds.), Models, simulations, and representations (pp. 91–114). London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bedau, M. (2013). Weak emergence drives the science, epistemology, and metaphysics of synthetic biology. Biological Theory, 8(4), 334–345.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chaitin, G. (1996). How to run algorithmic information theory on a computer: Studying the limits of mathematical reasoning. Complexity, 2(1), 15–21.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cover, T. M., & Thomas, J. A. (2006). Elements of information theory. Hoboken: Wiley-Interscience.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dennett, D. (1991). Real patterns. Journal of Philosophy, 88(1), 27–51.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Epstein, J. (1999). Agent-based computational models and generative social science. Complexity, 4(5), 41–60.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Grünwald, P. D., & Vitányi, P. M. B. (2003). Kolmogorov complexity and information theory. With an interpretation in terms of questions and answers. Journal of Logic, Language and Information, 12(4), 497–529.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hovda, P. (2008). Quantifying weak emergence. Minds and Machines, 18(4), 461–473.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hsieh, D. A. (1991). Chaos and nonlinear dynamics: Application to financial markets. The Journal of Finance, 46(5), 1839–1877.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Humphreys, P. (2008). Computational and conceptual emergence. Philosophy of Science, 75(5), 584–594.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Humphreys, P. (2009). The philosophical novelty of computer simulation methods. Synthese, 169(3), 615–626.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Imbert, C. (2005). Why diachronically emergent properties must also be salient. In C. Gershenson, D. Aerts, & B. Edmonds (Eds.), Worldviews, science, and us: Philosophy and complexity (pp. 99–116). Singapore: World Scientific.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kim, J. (1999). Making sense of emergence. Philosophical Studies, 95(1-2), 3–36.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ladyman, J., Lambert, J., & Wiesner, K. (2013). What is a complex system? European Journal for Philosophy of Science, 3(1), 33–67.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ladyman, J., Ross, D., Spurrett, D., & Collier, J. (2007). Every thing must go. Metaphysics naturalised. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Lovejoy, S. (1982). Area-perimeter relation for rain and cloud areas. Science, 216(4542), 185–187. https://doi.org/10.1126/science.216.4542.185.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Oestreicher, C. (2007). A history of chaos theory. Dialogues in Clinical Neuroscience, 9(3), 279–289.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Saremi, S., Mirajalili, S. M., & Mirajalili, S. (2014). Chaotic krill herd optimization algorithm. Procedia Technology, 12, 180–185.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Symons, J. (2008). Computational models of emergent properties. Minds and Machines, 18(4), 475–491.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Theurer, K. L. (2014). Complexity-based theories of emergence: Criticisms and constraints. International Studies in the Philosophy of Science, 28(3), 277–301.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wilson, J. (2013). Nonlinearity and metaphysical emergence. In S. Mumford & M. Tugby (eds.), Metaphysics and Science (pp. 201–229).

  • Wilson, J. (2019). Between scientism and abstractionism in the metaphysics of emergence. In S. Gibb, R. Hendry, & T. Lancaster (Eds.), Routledge handbook of emergence (pp. 157–176).

Download references

Acknowledgements

Thanks to the following people for their valuable feedback on earlier versions of this paper: Shamik Dasgupta, Nina Emery, Joshua Watson, Jessica Wilson, and two particularly helpful anonymous reviewers.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Nora Berenstain.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Berenstain, N. Strengthening Weak Emergence. Erkenn 87, 2457–2474 (2022). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10670-020-00312-6

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10670-020-00312-6

Navigation