Skip to main content

Robustness and Autonomy in Biological Systems: How Regulatory Mechanisms Enable Functional Integration, Complexity and Minimal Cognition Through the Action of Second-Order Control Constraints

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Biological Robustness

Part of the book series: History, Philosophy and Theory of the Life Sciences ((HPTL,volume 23))

Abstract

Living systems employ several mechanisms and behaviors to achieve robustness and maintain themselves under changing internal and external conditions. Regulation stands out from them as a specific form of higher-order control, exerted over the basic regime responsible for the production and maintenance of the organism, and provides the system with the capacity to act on its own constitutive dynamics. It consists in the capability to selectively shift between different available regimes of self-production and self-maintenance in response to specific signals and perturbations, due to the action of a dedicated subsystem which is operationally distinct from the regulated ones. The role of regulation, however, is not exhausted by its contribution to maintain a living system’s viability. While enhancing robustness, regulatory mechanisms play a fundamental role in the realization of an autonomous biological organization. Specifically, they are at the basis of the remarkable integration of biological systems, insofar as they coordinate and modulate the activity of distinct functional subsystems. Moreover, by implementing complex and hierarchically organized control architectures, they allow for an increase in structural and organizational complexity while minimizing fragility. Finally, they endow living systems, from their most basic unicellular instances, with the capability to control their own internal dynamics to adaptively respond to specific features of their interaction with the environment, thus providing the basis for the emergence of minimal forms of cognition.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

eBook
USD 16.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Hardcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. 1.

    An alternative way to address biological robustness, closer to engineering approaches, would be to focus on individual behaviours and mechanisms, and on the maintenance of specific functions or performances .

  2. 2.

    As argued by Cornish-Bowden (2006), among others, most engineering approaches “often seem to imply little more than reductionist biology applied on a large scale ” while a “systemic approach to biology ought to put the emphasis on the entire system”. A somehow similar categorization is proposed by Dupré and O’Malley (2005), who distinguish between ‘pragmatic systems biologists’ – who find it useful to refer to some systems properties in terms of interactions and of integration of data – and ‘systems-theoretic biologists’ – who focus on the investigation of general systems principles. An interesting case is that of Robert Rosen, whose contributions include both engineering (Rosen 1967, 1970) and system-oriented approaches (Rosen 1972, 1985, 1991), and who saw the former as inadequate to capture the distinctive features of living organisms as systems (Rosen 1991).

  3. 3.

    For different ways to achieve biological robustness through stability see for example Rosen (1970), a classic textbook in dynamical systems theory.

  4. 4.

    The coupling between these subsystems is realised by means of supply and demand of metabolites necessary for the production of the components in the different subsystems (metabolic complementarity). The subsystems provide the necessary substrates for the internal processes of production taking place in the others and, in turn, consume the metabolites supplied by the others.

  5. 5.

    Dynamic stability is the capability to counterbalance the displacement of the system from a certain initial state, provoked by a perturbation, and end up in the same final state (Rosen 1970). It is a widespread property in the natural world , instantiated by any system whose dynamic behavior is characterized by the presence of at least one stable attractor . When realized collectively, dynamic stability is a distributed property of a whole network of reactions - it cannot be attributed to any single transformation , or to a partial subset of transformations.

  6. 6.

    See Bich et al. (2016) for a discussion of dynamic stability in models of minimal living organizations.

  7. 7.

    These favorable conditions might also include the presence of most of the necessary building blocks for early living systems, as claimed for example by the heterotrophic models of the origin of life (see for example Mansy et al. 2008).

  8. 8.

    It does not imply that different forms of robustness, based respectively on dynamic stability , and modular and hierarchical control mechanisms cannot coexist in the same system or subsystem.

  9. 9.

    This issue is closely related to the debate on the relationship between mechanistic and network descriptions. Whereas mechanisms describe distinguishable parts which play different specific tasks, network descriptions focus on global properties and patterns of connectivity (Moreno et al. 2011). Finding ways to bring together network and mechanistic descriptions, apparently irreducible to each other, is on the of the challenges faced by complex systems theory. An attempt to develop an heuristic s to move between the two descriptive approaches has been proposed by Bechtel (2017a, 2017b). The basic idea is that clusters of interconnections in a network description are possible candidates for the parts of the mechanistic description of the same system. The limit of this approach is that patterns and network configurations derived from numbers of connections do not provide the same kind of information on the system as the identification of different types of contributions (e.g. in metabolism a complex hierarchy involving, metabolites, enzymes acting on metabolites, energy currencies, kinases acting on enzymes, etc.), but a complementary one.

  10. 10.

    See for example Rosen 1970; Hofmeyr and Cornish-Bowden 1991.

  11. 11.

    Given a particular thermodynamics process P, a molecular configuration C acts as a constraint upon P if: (1) at a time scale characteristic of P, C is locally unaffected by P; (2) at this time scale C exerts a causal role on P, i.e. there is some observable difference between free P, and P under the influence of C (Mossio et al. 2013, 164. A more detailed characterisation can be found in Montévil and Mossio 2015).

  12. 12.

    See Pattee 1972; Bich et al. 2016; Winning and Bechtel 2018, for a discussion of control in biological systems. See Arnellos et al. 2014 and Veloso 2017, for a discussion of inter-cellular control mechanisms in development.

  13. 13.

    See for example Mossio et al. 2016 for a characterisation of the role of mRNA as a constraint.

  14. 14.

    See Nghe et al. (2015) and Ruiz-Mirazo and Moreno (2004) for a discussion of the some of the key elements for the origin of these self-producing and self-maintaining networks in prebiotic conditions.

  15. 15.

    The requirement for a structure to be a constraint is to be locally unaffected by the process they are harnessing. But a constraint can be affected by other interactions in the system.

  16. 16.

    For example, the effects described by the law of mass action.

  17. 17.

    For a more detailed discussion of biological regulation as second-order control see Bich et al. (2016).

  18. 18.

    As argued by William Bechtel, “Although stoichiometric linkages between reactions are effective for insuring linkages between operations, they do not provide a means for varying the reactions independently. Such independent control can only be achieved by a property not directly linked to the critical stoichiometry of the system” (Bechtel 2007, 229).

  19. 19.

    The concentration of repressor proteins is usually low (proportional to the number of copies of the promoter sequence it regulates) and does not undergo variation in concentrations to bring forth its regulatory effect. The lac-operon system, a more complex example of genetic regulation, which coordinates the metabolism of two sugars (lactose and glucose) through the second-order control of the transcription step, follows the same logic (see Bich et al. 2016 for an analysis of regulatory decoupling in this latter case).

  20. 20.

    Specifically, the example relies on the analysis of glycogen synthesis in the rat gastrocnemius muscle provided in Schafer et al. (2005).

  21. 21.

    See also J. S. Hofmeyr and Cornish-Bowden (2000) for an analysis of this type of stoichiometrically dependent responses.

  22. 22.

    One of the effects of the release of insulin is the rapid change of the phosphorylation state of the enzyme glycogen synthase (GSase), which alters its kinetics. It is a clear case of second order control interaction, in which a regulatory subsystem acts on a first order control constraints (GSase) by activating (or inhibiting) it.

  23. 23.

    Another way to express the idea is that systems can be alive under very special stable conditions, without regulatory mechanisms , by relying only on the constitutive network. Regulation would then become necessary only when the system is immersed in changing environments and develops a higher internal differentiation.

  24. 24.

    Different subsystems might present different internal norms of operation, and need to be coordinated to ensure both their compatibility and their joint functional contribution to the maintenance of the system. Another relevant feature of biological cells is that they cannot synthesise all the possible molecules at the same time, due to energetic and spatial limits. Therefore, they have to exert some control over biosynthetic processes in order to produce the necessary components at the right times. Other types of functional resources need coordination as well. Let us think of the interplay between metabolic regimes relying on different carbon sources, such as lactose and glucose. Without the proper regulation (realised for example by the lac-operon subsystem) these regimes would compete for basic catalytic resources in the cell.

  25. 25.

    The idea of improving adaptivity and robustness by increasing the degrees of freedom available to the systems’ dynamics at the expense of distributed stability of the network can be found already in Piaget’s school (Meyer 1967). For a recent discussion of the interplay between organisation and variation in biology see instead Montévil et al. (2016).

  26. 26.

    See Bich and Moreno (2016) for a more detailed discussion of minimal cognition in relation to biological regulation.

  27. 27.

    See Godfrey-Smith (2016) for a critical discussion of this account of minimal cognition focused on sensory-motor activity.

  28. 28.

    See Pattee (1972, 1973), Kauffman (2000), Umerez and Mossio (2013), Moreno and Mossio (2015), Winning and Bechtel (2018).

References

  • Alexandre, G. (2010). Coupling metabolism and chemotaxis-dependent behaviours by energy taxis receptors. Microbiology, 156(8), 2283–2293.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Arnellos, A., & Moreno, A. (2012). How functional organization originated in prebiotic evolution. Ludus Vitalis, XX(37), 1–23.

    Google Scholar 

  • Arnellos, A., Ruiz-Mirazo, K., & Moreno, A. (2014). Organizational requirements for multicellular autonomy: Insights from a comparative case study. Biology and Philosophy, 29(6), 851–884.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Barandiaran, X., & Moreno, A. (2006). On what makes certain dynamical systems cognitive: A minimally cognitive organization program. Adaptive Behavior, 14(2), 171–185.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bechtel, W. (2007). Biological mechanisms: Organized to maintain autonomy. In F. Boogerd, F. Bruggerman, J. H. Hofmeyr, & H. V. Westerhoff (Eds.), Systems biology: Philosophical foundations (pp. 269–302). Amsterdam: Elsevier.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Bechtel, W. (2008). Mental mechanisms: Philosophical perspectives on cognitive neuroscience. New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bechtel, W. (2014). Cognitive biology: Surprising model organisms for cognitive science. In Proceedings of the 36th annual conference of the cognitive science society (pp. 158–163).

    Google Scholar 

  • Bechtel, W. (2017a). Explicating top-down causation using networks and dynamics. Philosophy of Science, 84, 253–274.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bechtel, W. (2017b). Systems biology: Negotiating between holism and reductionism. In S. Green (Ed.), Philosophy of systems biology: Perspectives from scientists and philosophers (pp. 25–36). New York: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Bernard, C. (1865). Introduction à l’étude de la médecine expérimentale. Paris: Balliére.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bich, L. (2016). Systems and organizations: Theoretical tools, conceptual distinctions and epistemological implications. In G. Minati, M. R. Abram, & E. Pessa (Eds.), Towards a Post-Bertalanffy Systemics (pp. 203–209). New York: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Bich, L., & Arnellos, A. (2012). Autopoiesis, autonomy and organizational biology: Critical remarks on “Life After Ashby”. Cybernetics and Human Knowing, 19(4), 75–103.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bich, L., & Damiano, L. (2008). Order in the nothing: Autopoiesis and the organizational characterization of the living. Electronic Journal of Theoretical Physics – Special Issue Physics of Emergence and Organization, 4(16), 343–373.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bich, L., & Damiano, L. (2012a). Life, autonomy and cognition: An organizational approach to the definition of the universal properties of life. Origins of Life and Evolution of Biospheres, 42(5), 389–397.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bich, L., & Damiano, L. (2012b). On the emergence of biology from chemistry: A discontinuist perspective from the point of view of stability and regulation. Origins of Life and Evolution of Biospheres, 42(5), 475–482.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bich, L., & Moreno, A. (2016). The role of regulation in the origin and synthetic modelling of minimal cognition. Biosystems, 148, 12–21.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bich, L., Mossio, M., Ruiz-Mirazo, K., & Moreno, A. (2016). Biological regulation: Controlling the system from within. Biology and Philosophy, 31(2), 237–265.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bitbol, M., & Luisi, P. L. (2004). Autopoiesis with or without cognition: Defining life at its edge. Journal of the Royal Society Interface, 1(1), 99–107.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bourgine, P., & Stewart, J. (2004). Autopoiesis and cognition. Artificial Life, 10(3), 327–345.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chen, C. (2008). Review on robustness in systems biology. Journal of Biomechatronics Engineering, 1(2), 17–28.

    Google Scholar 

  • Christensen, W. (2007). The evolutionary origins of volition. In D. Spurrett, H. Kincaid, D. Ross, & L. Stephens (Eds.), Distributed cognition and the will: Individual volition and social context (pp. 255–287). Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Christensen, W. D., & Hooker, C. (2000). An interactivist-constructivist approach to intelligence: Self-directed anticipative learning. Philosophical Psychology, 13, 5–45.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cornish-Bowden, A. (2006). Putting the systems back into systems biology. Perspectives in Biology and Medicine, 49(4), 475–489.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Damiano, L., & Luisi, P. L. (2010). Towards an autopoietic redefinition of life. Origins of Life and Evolution of Biospheres, 40(2), 145–149.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dupré, J., & O’Malley, M. (2005). Fundamental issues in systems biology. Bio Essays, 27, 1270–1276.

    Google Scholar 

  • Eisenbach, M. (Ed.). (2004). Chemotaxis. Singapore: Imperial College Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Eisenbach, M. (2007). A hitchhiker’s guide through advances and conceptual changes in chemotaxis. Journal of Cellular Physiology, 213, 574–580.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ganti, T. (1975). Organization of chemical reactions into dividing and metabolizing units: The chemotons. Bio Systems, 7, 15–21.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ganti, T. (1979). A theory of biochemical supersystems. Baltimore: University Park Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ganti, T. (2003a). The principles of life. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Ganti, T. (2003b). Chemoton theory. New York: Kluwer Academic/Plenum Publisher.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Godfrey-Smith, P. (2016). Individuality, subjectivity, and minimal cognition. Biology and Philosophy, 31, 775–796. https://doi.org/10.1007/s10539-016-9543-1.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Griesemer, J., & Szathmáry, E. (2009). Ganti’s chemoton model and life criteria. In S. Rasmussen, M. Bedau, L. Chen, D. Deamer, D. Krakauer, N. Packard, & P. Stadler (Eds.), Protocells. Bridging nonliving and living matter (pp. 481–513). Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heschl, A. (1990). L = C. A simple equation with astonishing consequences. Journal of Theoretical Biology, 145, 13–40.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hofmeyr, J. H., & Cornish-Bowden, A. (1991). Quantitative assessment of regulation in metabolic systems. European Journal of Biochemistry/FEBS, 200(1), 223–236.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hofmeyr, J. S., & Cornish-Bowden, A. (2000). Regulating the cellular economy of supply and demand. FEBS Letters, 476(1–2), 47–51.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jacob, F., & Monod, J. (1961). Genetic regulatory mechanisms in the synthesis of proteins. Journal of Molecular Biology, 3, 318–356.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kant, I. (1790). Kritik der Urteilskraft.

    Google Scholar 

  • Karpen, J. W. (2004). Ion channel structure and the promise of bacteria. The Journal of General Physiology, 124(3), 199–201.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kauffman, S. A. (1986). Autocatalytic sets of proteins. Journal of Theoretical Biology, 119(1), 1–24.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kauffman, S. A. (2000). Investigations. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kirschner, M. W., & Gerhart, J. C. (2005). The plausibility of life: Resolving Darwin’s dilemma. New Haven: Yale University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kitano, H. (2004). Biological robustness. Nature Reviews. Genetics, 5(11), 826–837.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kitano, H. (2007). Towards a theory of biological robustness. Molecular Systems Biology, 3(137), 1–7.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kulasekara, H. D., & Miller, S. I. (2007). Threonine phosphorylation times bacterial secretion. Nature Cell Biology, 9(7), 734–736.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lamelas, A., Gosalbes, M. J., Manzano-Marín, A., Peretó, J., Moya, A., & Latorre, A. (2011). Serratia symbiotica from the aphid Cinara cedri: A missing link from facultative to obligate insect endosymbiont. PLoS Genetics, 7(11), e1002357.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Letelier, J.-C., Soto-Andrade, J., Guíñez Abarzúa, F., Cornish-Bowden, A., & Luz Cárdenas, M. (2006). Organizational invariance and metabolic closure: Analysis in terms of (M,R) systems. Journal of Theoretical Biology, 238(4), 949–961.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Luisi, P. L. (2006). The emergence of life. From chemical origins to synthetic biology. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Mansy, S. S., Schrum, J. P., Krishnamurthy, M., Tobé, S., Treco, D. a., & Szostak, J. W. (2008). Template-directed synthesis of a genetic polymer in a model protocell. Nature, 454(7200), 122–125.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Maturana, H., & Varela, F. J. (1980). Autopoiesis and cognition. The realization of the living. Dordrecht: Reidel Publishing.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Meyer, F. (1967). Situation épistémologique de la biologie. In J. Piaget (Ed.), Logique et connaissance scientifique. Encyclopédie de la Pléyade (pp. 781–821). Paris: Gallimard.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mitchell, S. (2009). Unsimple truths: Science, complexity, and policy. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Montévil, M., & Mossio, M. (2015). Biological organisation as closure of constraints. Journal of Theoretical Biology, 372, 179–191.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Montévil, M., Mossio, M., Pocheville, A., & Longo, G. (2016). Theoretical principles for biology: Variation. Progress in Biophysics and Molecular Biology, 122, 36–50. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.pbiomolbio.2016.08.005.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Moreno, A. (2016). Some conceptual issues in the transition from chemistry to biology. History and Philosophy of the Life Sciences, 38(4), 1–16.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Moreno, A., & Mossio, M. (2015). Biological autonomy: A philosophical and theoretical enquiry. Dordrecht: Springer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Moreno, A., & Ruiz-Mirazo, K. (2009). The problem of the emergence of functional diversity in prebiotic evolution. Biology and Philosophy, 24(5), 585–605.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Moreno, A., Umerez, J., & Ibanez, J. (1997). Cognition and life. The autonomy of cognition. Brain & Cognition, 34(1), 107–129.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Moreno, A., Ruiz-Mirazo, K., & Barandiaran, X. (2011). The impact of the paradigm of complexity on the foundational framework of biology and cognitive science. In C. Hooker (Ed.), Philosophy of complex systems (pp. 311–333). Amsterdam: North Holland.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Mossio, M., & Bich, L. (2017). What makes biological organisation teleological? Synthese, 194(4), 1089–1114.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mossio, M., & Moreno, A. (2010). Organisational closure in biological organisms. History and Philosophy of the Life Sciences, 32, 269–288.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mossio, M., Saborido, C., & Moreno, A. (2009). An organizational account of biological functions. The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 60(4), 813–841.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mossio, M., Bich, L., & Moreno, A. (2013). Emergence, closure and inter-level causation in biological systems. Erkenntnis, 78(2), 153–178.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mossio, M., Montévil, M., & Longo, G. (2016). Theoretical principles for biology: Organization. Progress in Biophysics and Molecular Biology., 122, 24–35. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.pbiomolbio.2016.07.005.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nghe, P., Hordijk, W., Kauffman, S. A., Walker, S. I., Schmidt, F. J., Kemble, H., et al. (2015). Prebiotic network evolution: Six key parameters. Molecular Bio Systems., 11, 3206–3217. https://doi.org/10.1039/C5MB00593K.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nicolis, G., & Prigogine, I. (1977). Self-organization in nonequilibrium systems: From dissipative structures to order through fluctuations. New York: Wiley.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pascal, R., & Pross, A. (2016). The logic of life. Origins of Life and Evolution of Biospheres, 46(4), 507–513.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pattee, H. H. (1972). The nature of hierarchical controls in living matter. In R. Rosen (Ed.), Foundations of mathematical biology. Volume I, S ubcellular Systems (pp. 1–22). New York: Academic Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pattee, H. H. (Ed.) (1973). Hierarchy theory. New York: Braziller.

    Google Scholar 

  • Piaget, J. (1967). Biologie et Connaissance. Paris: Gallimard.

    Google Scholar 

  • Piedrafita, G., Montero, F., Morán, F., Cárdenas, M. L., & Cornish-Bowden, A. (2010). A simple self-maintaining metabolic system: Robustness, autocatalysis, bistability. PLoS Computational Biology, 6(8), e1000872.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rosen, R. (1967). Optimality principles in biology. London: Butterworths.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Rosen, R. (1970). Dynamical system theory in biology. Stability theory and its applications. New York: Wiley.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rosen, R. (1972). Some relational cell models: The metabolism-repair systems. In R. Rosen (Ed.), Foundations of mathematical biology. Volume II, Cellular Systems (pp. 217–253). New York: Academic Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Rosen, R. (1978). Fundamentals of measurement and representation of natural systems. NewYork: North Holland.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rosen, R. (1985). Anticipatory systems. Oxford: Pergamon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rosen, R. (1991). Life itself. A comprehensive inquiry into the nature, origin, and fabrication of life. New York: Columbia University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ruiz-Mirazo, K., & Moreno, A. (2004). Basic autonomy as a fundamental step in the synthesis of life. Artificial ife, 10(3), 235–259.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ruiz-Mirazo, K., Peretò, J., & Moreno, A. (2004). A universal definition of life: Autonomy and open-ended evolution. Origins of Life and Evolution of the Biosphere, 34(3), 323–346.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schafer, J. R. A., Fell, D. A., Rothman, D. L., & Shulman, R. G. (2005). Phosphorylation of allosteric enzymes can serve homeostasis rather than control flux: The example of glycogen synthase. In R. G. Shulman & D. L. Rothman (Eds.), Metabolomics by in vivo NMR (pp. 59–71). Chichester: Wiley.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Semenov, S. N., Kraft, L. J., Ainla, A., Zhao, M., Baghbanzadeh, M., Campbell, V. E., et al. (2016). Autocatalytic, bistable, oscillatory networks of biologically relevant organic reactions. Nature, 537(7622), 656–660.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shirt-Ediss, B. (2016). Modelling early transitions towards autonomous protocells. Ph.D. Dissertation. University of the Basque Country.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stelling, J., Sauer, U., Szallasi, Z., Doyle, F. J., & Doyle, J. (2004). Robustness of cellular functions. Cell, 118(6), 675–685.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stock, J. B., Ninfa, A. A., & Stock, A. M. (1989). Protein phosphorylation and regulation of adaptive responses in bacteria. Microbiological Reviews, 53(4), 450–490.

    Google Scholar 

  • Umerez, J., & Mossio, M. (2013). Constraint. In W. Dubitzky, O. Wolkenhauer, K.-H. Cho, & H. Yokota (Eds.), Encyclopedia of systems biology (pp. 490–493). New York: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • van Duijn, M., Keijzer, F., & Franken, D. (2006). Principles of minimal cognition: Casting cognition as sensorimotor coordination. Adaptive Behavior, 14(2), 157–170.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Van Segbroeck, S., Nowé, A., & Lenaerts, T. (2009). Stochastic simulation of the chemoton. Artificial Life, 15, 213–226.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Varela, F. J. (1979). Principles of biological autonomy. New York: North Holland.

    Google Scholar 

  • Varela, F. J., Maturana, H. R., & Uribe, R. (1974). Autopoiesis: The organization of living systems, its characterization and a model. Bio Systems, 5(4), 187–196.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Varela, F. J., Thomson, E., & Rosch, E. (1991). The embodied mind. Cognitive science and human experience. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Veloso, F. (2017). On the developmental self-regulatory dynamics and evolution of individuated multicellular organisms. Journal of Theoretical Biology, 417, 84–99.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wiley, H. R. (2013). Animal communication and noise. In H. Brum (Ed.), Animal communication and noise (pp. 7–30). Berlin/Heidelberg: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Winning, J., & Bechtel, B. (2018). Rethinking causality in biological and neural mechanisms: Constraints and control. Minds and Machines, 28, 287–310. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11023-018-9458-5.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

This project has received funding from: the European Research Council (ERC) under the European Union’s Horizon 2020 research and innovation programme – grant agreement n° 637647 – IDEM; from the Ministerio de Economia, Industria y Competitividad (MINECO), Spain (‘Ramon y Cajal’ Programme RYC-2016-19798 and research project FFI2014-52173-P); and from the Basque Government (Project: IT 590-13).

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Leonardo Bich .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2018 Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Bich, L. (2018). Robustness and Autonomy in Biological Systems: How Regulatory Mechanisms Enable Functional Integration, Complexity and Minimal Cognition Through the Action of Second-Order Control Constraints. In: Bertolaso, M., Caianiello, S., Serrelli, E. (eds) Biological Robustness. History, Philosophy and Theory of the Life Sciences, vol 23. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-01198-7_6

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics