Skip to main content
Log in

Scientific representation and dissimilarity

  • Unrealistic Models
  • Published:
Synthese Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

In this essay, I examine the role of dissimilarity in scientific representation. After briefly reviewing some of the philosophical literature which places a strong emphasis on the role of similarity, I turn to examine some work from Carroll and Borges which demonstrates that perfect similarity is not valuable in the representational use of maps. Expanding on this insight, I go on to argue that this shows that dissimilarity is an important part of the representational use of maps—a point I then extend to the case of scientific representation. Relying on some work from Latour, I argue that dissimilarity plays an essential role in representational practice, by providing novel forms of manipulation and use which affords the achievement of various epistemic and nonepistemic aims. After showing how this point connects to some other literature on scientific representation, I discuss some examples of the value of dissimilarity in the use of representational vehicles. Overall, I argue that to understand scientific representation, we will need to consider more than just similarity. We will need to explore dissimilarities as well.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. For an overview of the literature on scientific representation, see Boesch (2015), Suárez (2015b) and Frigg and Nguyen (2016a).

  2. Though I will not discuss it here, Umberto Eco discusses the same theme in greater detail, “On the Impossibility of Drawing a Map of the Empire on Scale 1 to 1” (Eco 1995, pp. 95–106).

  3. Translation mine.

  4. It is telling, I think, that Borges titled this story “Del rigor en la ciencia” (“On Rigor in Science”), indicating perhaps that his aim was not cartographers but rather a statement about how we should understand the value of exactitude in science.

  5. Most commonly, a map will be smaller in scale than its target, but this need not be the case. For example, a map of an ant hill in a children’s book about anthropomorphized ants would be valuable in virtue the fact that it is larger than its target. Similarly, a map which recreates a famous building or room may not involve any change in scale (though it still allows for a new perspective, since it allows someone to explore the building or room in a different context).

  6. The importance of the use of maps matches well with much of what Wittgenstein says about maps in various locations. For an analysis, see Wagner (2011).

  7. A similar point about the value of distortion is made by van Fraassen (2008, p. 14).

References

  • Ambrosio, C. (2014). Iconic representations and representative practices. International Studies in the Philosophy of Science, 28(3), 255–275. https://doi.org/10.1080/02698595.2014.959831.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bartels, A. (2006). Defending the structural concept of representation. Theoria, 21(1), 7–19.

    Google Scholar 

  • Batterman, R. W., & Rice, C. C. (2014). Minimal model explanations. Philosophy of Science, 81(3), 349–376.

    Google Scholar 

  • Boesch, B. (2015). Scientific representation. In Internet encyclopedia of philosophy. http://www.iep.utm.edu/sci-repr/.

  • Boesch, B. (2017). There is a special problem of scientific representation. Philosophy of Science, 84(5), 970–981. https://doi.org/10.1086/693989.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Boesch, B. (2019). The means-end account of scientific, representational actions. Synthese, 196(6), 2305–2322. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-017-1537-2.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Borges, J. L. (1960). Del Rigor En La Ciencia. In El Hacedor. Buenos Aires: Emecé Editores, S. A.

  • Bueno, O. (1997). Empirical adequacy: A partial structures approach. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A, 28(4), 585–610.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bueno, O., & French, S. (2011). How theories represent. The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 62(4), 857–894.

    Google Scholar 

  • Carroll, L. (1994). The complete works of Lewis Carroll. New York: Barnes and Noble Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chakravartty, A. (2010). Informational versus functional theories of scientific representation. Synthese, 172(2), 197–213.

    Google Scholar 

  • Contessa, G. (2007). Scientific representation, interpretation, and surrogative reasoning. Philosophy of Science, 74(1), 48–68.

    Google Scholar 

  • Contessa, G. (2011). Scientific models and representation. In S. French & J. Saatsi (Eds.), The continuum companion to philosophy of science (pp. 120–137). New York: Bloomsbury.

    Google Scholar 

  • Costa, D., Newton, C. A., & French, S. (2003). Science and partial truth: A unitary approach to models and scientific reasoning. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Decock, L., & Douven, I. (2011). Similarity after Goodman. Review of Philosophy and Psychology, 2(1), 61–75. https://doi.org/10.1007/s13164-010-0035-y.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Eco, U. (1995). How to travel with a Salmon & other essays. Boston: HMH.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fang, W. (2017). Holistic modeling: An objection to Weisberg’s weighted feature-matching account. Synthese, 194(5), 1743–1764. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-016-1018-z.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Foster, J. E. (1971). History and description of the Mississippi basin model. U.S. Army Corp of Engineers Waterways Experiment Station.

  • Van Fraassen, B. (1980). The scientific image. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • French, S. (2003). A model-theoretic account of representation (or, I don’t know much about art…but i know it involves isomorphism). Philosophy of Science, 70(5), 1472–1483. https://doi.org/10.1086/377423.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • French, S., & Ladyman, J. (1999). Reinflating the semantic approach. International Studies in the Philosophy of Science, 13(2), 103–121.

    Google Scholar 

  • Frigg, R. (2006). Scientific representation and the semantic view of theories. Theoria, 21(1), 49–65.

    Google Scholar 

  • Frigg, R. (2010). Models and fiction. Synthese, 172(2), 251–268.

    Google Scholar 

  • Frigg, R., & Nguyen, J. (2016a). Scientific representation. In E. N. Zalta (Eds.), The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy. https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2016/entries/scientific-representation/.

  • Frigg, R., & Nguyen, J. (2016b). The fiction view of models reloaded. The Monist, 99(3), 225–242.

    Google Scholar 

  • Frisch, M. (2015). Users, structures, and representation. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 66(2), 285–306. https://doi.org/10.1093/bjps/axt032.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gärdenfors, P. (2000). Conceptual spaces: The geometry of thought. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gelfert, A. (2011). Mathematical formalisms in scientific practice: From denotation to model-based representation. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A, 42(2), 272–286.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gelfert, A. (2016). How to do science with models. New York: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Giere, R. N. (1988). Explaining science: A cognitive approach. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Giere, R. N. (2004). How models are used to represent reality. Philosophy of Science, 71(5), 742–752.

    Google Scholar 

  • Giere, R. N. (2010). An agent-based conception of models and scientific representation. Synthese, 172(2), 269–281.

    Google Scholar 

  • Godfrey-Smith, P. (2009a). Abstractions, idealizations, and evolutionary biology. In A. Barberousse, M. Morange, & T. Pradeu (Eds.), Mapping the future of biology (pp. 47–56). Berlin: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Godfrey-Smith, P. (2009b). Models and fictions in science. Philosophical Studies: An International Journal for Philosophy in the Analytic Tradition, 143(1), 101–116.

    Google Scholar 

  • Goodman, N. (1976). Languages of art: An approach to a theory of symbols (2d ed.). Indianapolis: Hackett.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hardy, G. H. (1908). Mendelian proportions in a mixed population. Science, 28(706), 49–50.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hughes, R. I. G. (1997). Models and representation. Philosophy of Science, 64, S325–S336.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jebeile, J., & Kennedy, A. G. (2015). Explaining with models: The role of idealizations. International Studies in the Philosophy of Science, 29(4), 383–392.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jones, M. R. (2005). Idealization and abstraction: A framework. In N. Cartwright & M. R. Jones (Eds.), Idealization XII: Correcting the model idealization and abstraction in the sciences (pp. 173–217). Leiden: Brill.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jones, M. R., & Cartwright, N. (2005). Idealization XII: Correcting the model: Idealization and abstraction in the sciences. Amsterdam: Rodopi.

    Google Scholar 

  • Knuuttila, T. (2011). Modelling and representing: An artefactual approach to model-based representation. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A, 42(2), 262–271. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.shpsa.2010.11.034.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Knuuttila, T., & Loettgers, A. (2012). The productive tension: Mechanisms vs. templates in modeling the phenomena. In P. Humphreys & C. Imbert (Eds.), Models, simulations, and representations (pp. 2–24).

  • Knuuttila, T., & Loettgers, A. (2017). Modelling as indirect representation? The Lotka–Volterra model revisited. The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 68(4), 1007–1036.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kralemann, B., & Lattmann, C. (2013). Models as icons: Modeling models in the semiotic framework of Peirce’s theory of signs. Synthese, 190(16), 3397–3420.

    Google Scholar 

  • Latour, B. (1999). Pandora’s hope: Essays on the reality of science studies. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Latour, B. (2014). The more manipulations, the better. In C. Coopmans, J. Vertesi, M. E. Lynch, & S. Woolgar (Eds.), Representation in scientific practice revisited. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Levy, A. (2012). Models, fictions, and realism: Two packages. Philosophy of Science, 79(5), 738–748. https://doi.org/10.1086/667992.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Levy, A., & Bechtel, W. (2013). Abstraction and the organization of mechanisms. Philosophy of Science, 80(2), 241–261.

    Google Scholar 

  • Love, A. C., & Nathan, M. J. (2015). The idealization of causation in mechanistic explanation. Philosophy of Science, 82(5), 761–774.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mäki, U. (2011). Models and the locus of their truth. Synthese, 180(1), 47–63.

    Google Scholar 

  • Parker, W. (2015). Getting (even more) serious about similarity. Biology and Philosophy, 30(2), 267–276. https://doi.org/10.1007/s10539-013-9406-y.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pero, F., & Suárez, M. (2016). Varieties of misrepresentation and homomorphism. European Journal for Philosophy of Science, 6(1), 71–90. https://doi.org/10.1007/s13194-015-0125-x.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pincock, C. (2005). Overextending partial structures: Idealization and abstraction. Philosophy of Science, 72(5), 1248–1259.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pincock, C. (2007). Mathematical idealization. Philosophy of Science, 74(5), 957–967.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rueger, A. (2014). Idealized and perspectival representations: Some reasons for making a distinction. Synthese, 191(8), 1831–1845.

    Google Scholar 

  • Salis, F. (2019). The new fiction view of models. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science. https://doi.org/10.1093/bjps/axz015.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stern, C. (1943). The Hardy-Weinberg law. Science, 97(2510), 137–138. https://doi.org/10.1126/science.97.2510.137.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Suárez, M. (2003). Scientific representation: Against similarity and isomorphism. International Studies in the Philosophy of Science, 17(3), 225–244. https://doi.org/10.1080/0269859032000169442.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Suárez, M. (2004). An inferential conception of scientific representation. Philosophy of Science, 71(5), 767–779. https://doi.org/10.1086/421415.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Suárez, M. (Ed.). (2008). Fictions in science: Philosophical essays on modeling and idealization. New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Suárez, M. (2010). Scientific representation. Philosophy Compass, 5(1), 91–101.

    Google Scholar 

  • Suárez, M. (2015a). Deflationary representation, inference, and practice. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A, 49, 36–47. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.shpsa.2014.11.001.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Suárez, M. (2015b). Representation in science. In P. Humphreys (Ed.), Oxford handbook in philosophy of science (pp. 440–460). New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Toon, A. (2010). The ontology of theoretical modelling: Models as make-believe. Synthese, 172(2), 301–315.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tversky, A. (1977). Features of similarity. Psychological Review, 84(4), 327.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tversky, A., & Gati, I. (1978). Studies of similarity. In E. Rosch & B. Loyd (Eds.), Cognition and categorization. New Jersey: Erlbaum.

    Google Scholar 

  • Van Fraassen, B. C. (2008). Scientific representation: Paradoxes of perspective. New York: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Vorms, M. (2011). Representing with imaginary models: Formats matter. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A, Model-Based Representation in Scientific Practice, 42(2), 287–295. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.shpsa.2010.11.036.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wagner, D. (2011). Glimpses of unsurveyable maps. In R. Heinrich, E. Nemeth, W. Pichler, & D. Wagner (Eds.), Image and imaging in philosophy, science and the arts (Vol. 2, pp. 365–376). Berlin: De Gruyter.

    Google Scholar 

  • Weinberg, W. (1908). Uber Den Nachweis Der Vererbung Biem Menschen. Jahreshefte Des Vereins Für Vaterländische Naturkunde in Württemberg, 64, 368–382.

    Google Scholar 

  • Weisberg, M. (2007). Three kinds of idealization. The Journal of Philosophy, 104(12), 639–659.

    Google Scholar 

  • Weisberg, M. (2012). Getting serious about similarity. Philosophy of Science, 79(5), 785–794.

    Google Scholar 

  • Weisberg, M. (2013). Simulation and similarity: Using models to understand the world. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Brandon Boesch.

Ethics declarations

Conflict of interest

The author declares he has no conflicts of interest.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Boesch, B. Scientific representation and dissimilarity. Synthese 198, 5495–5513 (2021). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-019-02417-0

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-019-02417-0

Keywords

Navigation