Skip to main content
Log in

Measurement, Explanation, and Biology: Lessons From a Long Century

  • Published:
Biological Theory Aims and scope Submit manuscript

    We’re sorry, something doesn't seem to be working properly.

    Please try refreshing the page. If that doesn't work, please contact support so we can address the problem.

Abstract

It is far from obvious that outside of highly specialized domains such as commercial agriculture, the methodology of biometrics—quantitative comparisons over groups of organisms—should be of any use in today’s bioinformatically informed biological sciences. The methods in our biometric textbooks, such as regressions and principal components analysis, make assumptions of homogeneity that are incompatible with current understandings of the origins of developmental or evolutionary data in historically contingent processes, processes that might have come out otherwise; the appropriate statistical methods are those suited to random walks, not normal distributions. A valid methodology would further require that especially close attention be paid to the difference between aspects of processes that are plastic, those that encode their own histories or biographies, and the very small fraction of quantifications that can usefully and realistically be modeled as varying by colored noise around a central tendency that itself has some quantitative meaning. This point of view—that only a vanishingly small fraction of the quantitative information borne by any living organism is worth quantifying—is illustrated by some data on a human birth defect, namely, fetal alcohol syndrome. In a suggestive metaphor, the biometrician is like the pilgrim in Friedrich’s painting Der Wanderer über dem Nebelmeer, uncertain as to whether to measure the mountains or the clouds. The mountains stand for contingent history, the clouds for the subset of the data most closely matching controlled experiments suitable for quantitative biometric summary. Biometrics applies to the clouds, not the mountains. The success of statistical methods comes at the expense of all the theories that we simultaneously hold to be true about the biological materials to which they both pertain. Biometrics is thus complementary to all of the emerging reductionist sciences of biological structure.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

References

  • Anson BJ (1963) An Atlas of Human Anatomy. 2nd ed. Philadelphia: W. B. Saunders.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bookstein FL (1978) The Measurement of Biological Shape and Shape Change. Lecture Notes in Biomathematics, Vol. 24. Berlin: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bookstein FL (1987) Random walk and the existence of evolutionary rates. Paleobiology 13: 446–464.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bookstein FL (1989) “Size and shape”: A comment on semantics. Systematic Zoology 38: 173–180.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bookstein FL (2006) My unexpected journey in applied biomathematics. Biological Theory 1: 67–77.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bookstein FL, Sampson PD, Connor PD, Streissguth AP (2002) The midline corpus callosum is a neuroanatomical focus of fetal alcohol damage. The Anatomical Record—The New Anatomist 269: 162–174.

    Google Scholar 

  • Elsasser WM (1975) The Chief Abstractions of Biology. Amsterdam: North-Holland.

    Google Scholar 

  • Feller W (1957) An Introduction to Probability Theory and Its Applications, Vol. 1. 2nd ed. New York: Wiley.

    Google Scholar 

  • Freedman DA (1991) Statistical models and shoe leather. Sociological Methodology 21: 291–313.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gaddis JL (2002) The Landscape of History: How Historians Map the Past. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gerard RW, ed (1958) Concepts of Biology. Publication 560. Washington, DC: National Research Council.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gunz P, Bookstein FL, Mitteroecker P, Stadlmeyr A, Seidler H, Weber GW (2009) Early modern human diversity suggests subdivided population structure and a complex out-of-Africa scenario. Proc Natl Acad Sci USA 106: 6094–6098.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Intergovernmental Panel on Climate Change (2007) Climate Change 2007: The Physical Science Basis. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Kuhn TS (1961) The function of measurement in modern physical science. Isis 52: 161–193.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mitteroecker PM, Bookstein FL (2008) The evolutionary role of modularity and integration in the hominoid cranium. Evolution 62: 943–958.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mitteroecker PM, Bookstein FL (2009) An ordination of the space of covariance matrices, with an application to craniofacial growth in rats and humans. Evolution 63: 727–737.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mitteroecker PM, Hutteger SM (2009) The concept of morphospaces in evolutionary and developmental biology: Mathematics and metaphors. Biological Theory 4: 54–67.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Neurath O, Carnap R, Morris C, eds (1970) Foundations of the Unity of Science: Toward an International Encyclopedia of Unified Science, Vol. 2, nos. 1–9. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Perrin J (1913) Les atomes. Paris: Librairie Félix Alcan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Platt JR (1964) Strong inference. Science 146: 347–353.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Russell B (1967) The Autobiography of Bertrand Russell. 3 Vols. London: George Allen and Unwin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Snow J (1855) On the Mode of Communication of Cholera. 2nd ed. London: John Churchill.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stigler SM (1986) The History of Statistics: The Measurement of Uncertainty to 1900. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stratton K, Howe C, Battaglia F, eds (1996) Fetal Alcohol Syndrome: Diagnosis, Epidemiology, Prevention, and Treatment. Washington, DC: National Academy Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Watson J, Crick FHC (1953) A structure for deoxyribose nucleic acid. Nature 71: 737–738.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Weber GW, Bookstein FL (in press) Virtual Anthropology: A Guide to a New Interdisciplinary Field. Vienna: Springer.

  • Weber GW, Gunz P, Mitteroecker P, Stadlmayr A, Bookstein FL, Seidler H (2006) External geometry of Mladec neurocrania compared with anatomically modern humans and Neandertals. In: Early Modern Humans at the Moravian Gate: The Mladec Caves and Their Remains (Teschler-Nicola M, ed.), 453–471. New York: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Weiss PA (1958) Comment. In: Concepts of Biology (Gerard RW, ed.), 140. Washington, DC: National Research Council.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wigner EP (1960) The unreasonable effectiveness of mathematics in the natural sciences. Communications on Pure and Applied Mathematics 13: 1–14.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Williams RJ (1956) Biochemical Individuality: The Basis for the Genetotrophic Concept. New York: Wiley.

    Google Scholar 

  • Woolf H (1961) Quantification: A History of the Meaning of Measurement in the Natural and Social Sciences. Indianapolis: Bobbs-Merrill.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wright S (1968) Evolution and the Genetics of Populations. Vol. 1. Genetic and Biometric Foundations. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Fred L. Bookstein.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Bookstein, F.L. Measurement, Explanation, and Biology: Lessons From a Long Century. Biol Theory 4, 6–20 (2009). https://doi.org/10.1162/biot.2009.4.1.6

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1162/biot.2009.4.1.6

Keywords

Navigation