1 Introduction

Boxes of cornflakes typically sold in supermarkets advertise their content through a repertoire of concepts expressed by recognizable tags—like “zero-fat,” “crispy and golden,” “the original breakfast,” “high in iron,” “just 104 cal per serving,” “for the whole family,” “with naturally nutritious grains,” “the healthy way to start your day.”Footnote 1 Any given box accompanies these tags with descriptive frames—such as “made from ingredients carefully selected from local farmers to meet the growing needs of our consumers, who appreciate wholeness through natural nutrition”—as well as by a score of technical and commonsense concepts, such as “measuring,” “calories,” “micro-” and “macro- nutrients,” “pleasure,” “breakfast,” “original breakfast,” “healthy for you and your whole family.”

The foodscape is overloaded with concepts like those camping on boxes of cornflakes. While some are frequently written down, others may be reserved to specific conversational contexts—as in the language of a sommelier or a butcher—or may even remain implicit—for example in cooking or eating practices. Jointly taken, these concepts play a crucial role in guiding our dietary behaviors, connecting them to a piece of medical advice, a lifestyle, a culture, or a tradition. More to the point, many of them also exemplify a poignant characteristic of food concepts that we wish to analyze—defectiveness.

In this paper we set out to offer a method of study for defective food concepts. These are, generally speaking, those concepts that fail to suitably represent a food-related domain or that offer representations that run counter to the interests of their users, taken individually or collectively. In employing the expression “defective concept” we line up with recent philosophical scholarship on so-called conceptual engineering,Footnote 2 which makes ample use of it. At the same time, our work is also robustly grounded into different loci of the literature related to food, which have already discussed defective concepts, without giving them such a name. The concepts featured on boxes of cornflakes are a case in point of defectiveness: they typically bootstrap the meaning of the terms they employ, arousing the suspicion of promising more than what they actually deliver.

Defective food concepts demand up to date and targeted processes of rethinking or negotiation, which involve different stakeholders within the food discourse, and which need to account for reasons that are both contextual and principled. Philosophers can play an important role in such processes. In particular, and building upon the work done by Borghini et al. (2021) with respect to local food, we show in the sequel that philosophers can offer means to represent chief disputes regarding food. Our study extends an approach to philosophizing that is not new (see e.g., Carnap, 1950) and that, in recent years, has been increasingly fine-tuned and put to use under the labels of “conceptual ethics,” “conceptual engineering” (Burgess & Plunkett, 2013), “ameliorative analysis” (Haslanger, 2012), and “conceptual negotiation” (Thomasson, 2017). As for food scholars, while they tend not to explicitly utilize “defectiveness” for referring to those concepts which they think should be revised, they offer numerous case studies of concepts that seem flawed and in need of revision. For instance, consider the pivotal work by Adams (1990) on the concept of “meat”: after unveiling its underlying hierarchical, racist, and patriarchal significance, she proposes a revised understanding of it.

We begin (Sect. 2) by sorting out four dimensions that are key to assess the defectiveness of a food concept: (i) the data upon which it rests and the methodology by which those data are gathered; (ii) the ontological categories that it represents; (iii) the social acts that serve to negotiate and establish the concept; (iv) and the objectives and values that the concept is meant to reach. We then (Sect. 3) point out four types of defects that a food concept can have—fragility, polarization, incoherence, and schizophrenia—by examining two specific examples: local food and healthy food. Finally (Sect. 4), we close by suggesting the creation of situated conceptual maps as accessible tools for negotiation.

2 Four dimensions of food concepts

In our analysis, we shall rely on a minimal view of food concepts, which treats them as representational devices for states of affairs involving food in meaningful ways (Burgess & Plunkett, 2013; Burgess et al., 2020).Footnote 3 According to the view, also, any food concept is linked to a wide and varied network of representations. Consider, for instance, the concept “healthy food” and imagine the following four contexts in which it can be put at use: a lab where specific antioxidant properties of fruits are studied and tested; a dietitian chairing a weight loss group support; a blogger describing their morning routine to their readers; and an indigenous granny preparing a traditional meal for the grandchildren. These contexts will link “healthy food” to possibly overlapping, yet different, clusters of specific ingredients, recipes, dietary patterns, culinary traditions, lifestyles, medical conditions, brands, and so on. Therefore, whether “healthy food” manages to serve a valuable or intended role should be assessed in relation to a given context of agency and use. The need for contextualization—we submit—holds true to a greater or lesser extent for all food concepts. For these reasons, it is of utter theoretical importance to devise some tools for suitably capturing the contextual salience of food concepts.

With this in mind, we propose to frame our analysis of food concepts in terms of four dimensions. (1) Data and methodologies, which establish the empirical validity of a food concept. Thus, in a given context of agency, we may primarily rely on empirical data—from microbiological to evolutionary, from nutritional to metabolic, gathered following science-specific methodologies. (2) Ontological categories, through which we impose certain structures onto our experiences, as when we regard a certain food (e.g., a croissant with a cappuccino) as a breakfast item. Such categories are not arbitrarily introduced nor are they part of the structure of reality: they rather emerge from the interplay between reality, culture, cognition, and semantics. (3) Fiat acts, which ground the existence of the concept in specific actors, such as the decision of a committee of experts to regard a certain food as a threat for a certain people. (4) Aims and values, as food is connected to identity, emotions, life plans, heritage, and many other value-laden domains of life.

These four dimensions are suggested by the different sorts of propositions that govern our understanding of food: propositions that rest on data and empirical observations; propositions that depend upon ontological categories imposed by cognitive and semantic constraints; propositions that rest on speech acts that seem to “make things with words” in a way that is peculiar; and propositions that depend upon value judgments. And yet, we recognize that the issues at stake emerge from a complexity that can hardly be resolved by philosophical analysis alone. As Parasecoli (2019, pp. 12ff) points out, in fact, a comprehensive understanding of food requires “knowledge in fields ranging from economics to politics, from agriculture to technology,” which should involve a variety of different agents, each with its own expertise and values, such as “individuals and communities of consumers and producers, activists, distributors, marketers, retailers, chefs, scientists and nutritionists, designers and engineers, financial institutions, transnational corporations, local and national authorities.”

In the remainder of this section, we offer a characterization of each dimension. Given the premises, we acknowledge that our analysis may not be all-encompassing; but, we believe it serves the much-needed theoretical purpose of introducing a conceptual frame to be employed by the broad community of food scholars and by the actors negotiating the use of key food terms.

2.1 Data and methodologies

Which data should ground a given food concept and which methodology should be employed to gather the data has been a hot and highly controversial topic. Two chief methodological camps can be sorted out here, a quantitative and a qualitative one.

The quantitative approach aims to measure and calculate the basic components of food and their function for sustaining human life on the basis of a given standard, i.e., nutritional needs and the qualities of food which should meet those needs. For instance, the number of calories, the presence of micro- and macro- nutrients, vitamins, and so on (Mudry, 2009; McClements et al., 2011; Scrinis, 2013). According to Carpenter (2003a) this approach traces all the way back to the chemical revolution that occurred at the end of the eighteenth century. It focuses on the relation between the physiology of the human body and some blocks taken as founding units of measure.Footnote 4

The qualitative approach centers on the cultural, moral, social, aesthetical and structural role of food. The data are collected by surveys among eaters (e.g., Spence, 2017), sociological and anthropological analysis (e.g., Counihan & Van Esterik, 2013), self-reflection of the human relations to food (e.g., Pollan, 2008), and structural studies on society (e.g., Biltekoff, 2013).

Both approaches can be cashed out in terms of their being more or less food-specific or consumption-specific—that is, whether their focus is on the eaten or on the eater. For instance, a quantitative approach can focus on, say, the nutrients found in a food item or in the digestive capacity of human beings, while a qualitative approach can focus on the relations between nutrients and ideology (Scrinis, 2013), or on the individual justification of a chosen diet (Pollan, 2008).

The number of data taken into account can vary considerably. In a simple network, each food concept is paired with just one kind of data, e.g., when nutrients are the only determinant of a healthy food. In a reductionist framework, the explanatory role of some data is reduced to the explanatory role of some more basic data, e.g., when nutritional data are reduced to those about the molecular composition of food (Ströhle & Döring, 2010), or when a collection of eating habits is reduced to data about the economic relations that sustain them. In a more complex, multi-layered network, instead, food concepts are explained by different sets of data, e.g., food security (roughly speaking, the possibility of access to nutrient food) roots out on data regarding nutritional intake, economic, social, and environmental conditions.

Data gathering is surrounded by controversies. A chief one concerns their neutrality. As Biltekoff et al. (2014) efficiently sum up, purely quantitative data gathering tends to be presented as neutral with regard to other non-quantitative food externalities, including habits, conventions, beliefs, rituals, and taste. Yet, scholars demonstrated several hidden assumptions that underscore quantitative units of measure. These include: politics of the body and endorsed ideologies (Mudry, 2009); implicit biases of scientific research (Nestle, 2013); the dubious status of the basic components of the concepts that should be collected, e.g., whether nutrients or whole foods are to be measured (Jacobs & Tapsell, 2007); which specific population is taken into account for collecting data (Pogge, 2016).

Conceptual negotiation could be employed to address issues surrounding data gathering, including their neutrality. In this paper, however, we shall focus on higher-levels of conceptual disagreement, which have so far escaped the attention of scholars and that involve negotiations concerning data and methods as a sub-part.

2.2 Ontological categories

Food concepts represent a variety of different ontologies populated by a variety of categories: physical objects (e.g., dishes, meals), artifacts (e.g., recipes,Footnote 5 restaurants), events (e.g., cooking, farming), conditions (e.g., hunger, appetite), processes (e.g., metabolism, foraging), perceptual states (e.g., bitter food, excellent food).Footnote 6 How to comprise in one ontology all these different categories is the first complexity that food concepts should tackle.

A further kind of complexity derives from the different ontological commitments that agents who use the same concept may have. For instance, while to a certain agent the concept of natural food is nothing above a façon de parler, for another it is a concept tracking real properties of entities that carve nature at its joints.Footnote 7

Mapping the heterogeneity of ontologies and ontological commitments could be conceived per se as a work of conceptual negotiation since an inventory of the ontological inventories—following the renowned Quinean metaphor—may be a useful tool for philosophers who want to spell out what are the ontologies of food concepts. However, also here, our priority is to tackle higher-level processes of negotiation, which would embed ontological issues as a sub-part.

For the purposes of the present discussion, we now provide a mapping tool for framing food ontologies based on a two-dimensional framework, visually consisting of two axes, each representing one dichotomy, and four quadrants where the different ontologies can be placed (see Fig. 1).

Fig. 1
figure 1

Space of negotiation between different ontologies

The first dimension of the framework represents the families of the domains of discourse where an ontology originates. That is, it shows an opposition between entities, which are posited by different agents in different domains, e.g., the domain of common sense and the domain of science. The dimension clusters, at one pole, all the ontologies whose entities rest on folk and common sense. Generally speaking, those ontologies are not the result of experimental methods but are the outcomes of more or less shared beliefs, based on first-person or collective experience. At the other pole stand ontologies populated by entities liable to experimental treatment or entities that are the outcomes, or the assumptions, of experiments, i.e., the so-called theoretical entities.

The second dimension stands for the approaches taken by the users who are meant to buy into those ontologies, i.e., whether they believe that the existence of the entities is grounded on how the world is or they are constructed by social and linguistic practices. The dimension clusters, at one pole, naturalist and realist approaches to ontology, which endorse the existence of the posited entities regardless of conventions, beliefs, languages, and conceptual schemas. On the other pole, we group constructivist and relativist approaches, which claim that the existence of those ontologies depends on conventions, beliefs, languages, and conceptual schemas.Footnote 8

For instance, a diet based on nutritional intake typically rests on nutritional science. The entities posited (i.e., nutrients) crucially depend on the experimental method, which is also used to link food components with human metabolism. This ontology is artlessly undertaken with a realistic or naturalistic stance and finds its place at quadrant 3. By contrast, consider a classic approach of structuralist anthropologists, that sees food as a socially constructed entity to the extent that anything can turn into food, if a community believes that it is such. This ontology would be placed in quadrant 2, since its domain is delivered by common sense and it is taken as constructed or relative to some situated beliefs.

The two-dimensional framework can be used for clarifying the “distance” among two stakeholders in negotiating a food concept, facilitating the individuation of specific disagreements and focusing the discussion. It can also serve as a tool to fine-tune the ontological nuances of complex concepts, such as geographical indications,Footnote 9 where scientific knowledge and common sense, realist and constructivist approaches, can often be mingled together in the same document or discourse.

2.3 Fiat acts

Data and ontologies are linked to concepts by means of specific acts on the part of specific agents. Following Smith (2001), we call those fiat acts. They can be characterized based on two aspects. The first is the type of agential authority, while the second is the kind of knowledge that guides the act.

Authority. A fiat act can be based on an absolute or relative form of authority. Each of them, in turn, may be performed by an individual or a community.Footnote 10 When absolute, the agent—be it an individual or a community—sets the boundaries of a food concept regardless of other networks of agents. For instance, the fact that a True Neapolitan Pizza should be consumed within 10 min of production as dictated by The Neapolitan Pizza Association is an example of an absolute fiat act exerted by a community of agents.

A relative fiat act, instead, rests on a source of legitimacy which does not depend on the involved agents. An example of an individual relative fiat act is given by an expert who owes their authority to an institution, e.g., a biologist who should decide what microbes can be safely included in a given fermentation process whose general guidelines are established by a sanitary bureau. A community-relative fiat act is when the authority of a group is conferred by external authorities, e.g., whether a wine is a geographical indication is due to a cartel of producers who set up the characteristics that should be met by the wine. However, their authority should in turn be officially recognized by national and supranational agencies, e.g., the European Union.Footnote 11

Knowledge. Fiat acts may require specific knowledge to be performed. When it comes to food, the literature (Borghini et al., 2020b) spotlights three types of knowledge. (i) Scientific and technical knowledge. Fiat acts concerning certain food concepts should involve objective and measurable data, or the ability to master specific technical instruments. This is the case, for instance, of basic food categories such as milk, cheese, or tomato, whose understanding may arguably depend upon the evidence produced by specific scientists; or the concept of safe food, which depends upon the knowledge of technical experts. (ii) Traditional ecological knowledge (TEK). This is a broad category that comprises all the ways of sorting out concepts based on “local” (i.e., contextually specific) clusters of expertise, such as those arising from local agricultural and breeding practices, and traditional beliefs. Certain salmon taxonomies, for instance, require that the assignment of a fish to a taxon be performed by a local salmon expert (Lien, 2015). (iii) Practical knowledge. Fiat acts founding certain foods depend on knowledge established through practices, interests, contextual and non-systematic goals that cannot be rendered in a principled way and that, at the same time, do not constitute forms of TEK. Instances are practices of recipe making, such as baking bread, which may depend upon contextual elements and specific know-how.

The variety of fiat acts that can set the boundaries of a food concept is conducive to a host of disagreements and confusions. Take, for instance, Parmesan cheese. Who has the authority to establish whether a certain piece of cheese is or is not Parmesan? Is such authority granted in virtue of some specific knowledge or in virtue of some other principle? Again, we shall not engage in conceptual negotiation at this level (see Borghini, 2015, 2022; Borghini & Gandolini, 2020), but rather we consider fiat acts as one of the sub-components of a more comprehensive conceptual negotiation about food concepts.

2.4 Aims and values

Food concepts may be upheld for different aims and values and philosophers are naturally in a good position to assess and negotiate them. In practice, it is often impossible to disentangle them. But, from a theoretical standpoint, they can be divided into two broad categories, namely epistemic and social aims or values (Brigandt & Rosario, 2020). Let us see each of them.

The epistemic aims and values of a food concept relate to its degree of accuracy and contextual relevance. These aims can be either terminal, i.e., the concept should produce accurate and contextually relevant beliefs about a food domain, or instrumental, i.e., the concept should produce accurate and contextually relevant beliefs about other concepts (or they could be employed as instruments for producing such beliefs). For instance, one of the epistemic aims of a certain interpretation of local food is to certify that the foods that satisfy the application conditions of the concept have been produced in a certain region (e.g., Adams, 2018). The concept of food miles, i.e., the distance between the production and the consumption places of a given food measured in miles, is instrumental to the concept of local food since it provides the metrics for certifying whether a food is local or not.

The social aims and values of a food concept relate to its role in bringing about desirable social conditions (Haslanger, 2012), which may be explicitly (i.e., directly) included within the concept, or only implicitly (i.e., indirectly). For instance, preventing famine is a direct aim of food security (FAO, 2006), while it is an indirect effect of food sovereignty that enabling local farmers to govern food chains could also allow them a free, stable, and continuous access to food.

Arguably, a good concept can reach its aims or express and embody a value. If it fails, two strategies can be deployed—resetting the concept or doing away with it. For instance, the concept of nutritious food has been reset several times throughout the history of nutritional science to better reach its aim, namely being adequate for human dietary intake (e.g., Scrinis, 2013 offers a significant overview, from the quantification of the components of a food to the study of its specific functions with respect to a specific human need).

However, some concepts may not be suitable to be reset, for instance because they are representationally inadequate or because they have become practically useless or even harmful. An instance of the first case may be the UNESCO concept of the Mediterranean Diet, which, according to several scholars, fails to represent the variety as well as the social structures and historical patterns of the many diets widespread in the Mediterranean regions (Simopoulos, 2001; Simopoulos et al., 2000). An instance of the second case is the famous 1992 USDA’s food pyramid (and its successors), which flunks its target of instituting a balanced and scientifically sound diet for the population at large, therefore failing to adequately counter health issues related to food consumption (see Nestle, 2013, pp. 51–67; Mudry, 2009, pp. 77–136).

Lastly, a food concept may also hold wrong aims or bad values, both on epistemic and social grounds. For instance, Scrinis (2013) claims that the concept of functional food, which reduces food to its capacity of improving human bodies, cannot give us a comprehensive and genuine knowledge of food. At the same time, functional food promotes the wrong aim of making the body more suitable for commodification as long as it reduces nutrition to the goal of improving bodily functions for increasing the profit of private companies. Thus, he contends, the concept should be dismissed.

3 Defective food concepts

The four dimensions of food concepts outlined in the previous section provide one of the two main sides of our analysis. We shall now turn to the other side, namely the avenues that render a concept defective. As we already noted above, the literature suggests that a concept may be defective either by failing to represent its intended content or by fostering undesirable social consequences. Below we spell out these two avenues in some details. Our analysis will be specific to the food domain, though what we outline may hold for a wider range of inquiries that avail themselves of defective concepts.

Failures in representation obtain when a food concept fails to suitably represent an intended food domain by excluding or misrepresenting some or all of its dimensions, namely the intended data and methodologies, the ontological categories, the fiat acts, and the aims and values. For instance, the concept of “novoandino cuisine,” as forged by Peruvian starred chefs, is charged with misrepresenting meals and dietary patterns of Peruvian rural communities who are deprived of a fair representation of their cultural heritage (see García, 2013, 2021). This failure may be explained by pointing out that (the data and methodology, ontological categories, fiat acts, and aims and values of) “novoandino cuisine” represent a counterfeit version of Peruvian gastronomic culture designed to earn a profit for the few starred chefs in Lima. Another notable example is offered by fair-trades labels, which have been criticized for smuggling unethical products under the “fair-trade food” tag (see Sylla, 2014, pp. 34–58). In this case, the failure can be explained by stressing the shallowness of certain certifications (that take into account only one phase of the complex processes of production and distribution), the polarization of different fair-trade labels, and the incapacity of many of those labels of reflecting fair aims.

Failures in the social consequences obtain when the food concept has undesirable consequences for some or all of its stakeholders. For instance, as Adams (1990) argued, the patriarchal understanding of “meat,” by placing meat as the main dish, mirrors and reinforces unjust and abusive hierarchical relationships as well as the social exclusion of women and non-Western people. In this case, the concept “meat” fails to integrate stakeholders’ goals: it aims at covering all the ways of eating, while its first three conceptual dimensions are filled up by objects, patterns, and relations privileging meat consumption.Footnote 12

The two avenues for failure are interwoven, as undesired social consequences are often traced back to the fact that a concept fails to fairly represent a domain. Even when there is no overlap, defects may be distinct and yet comparable in some respects. It may in fact be feasible to compare conceptual failures in the number of defective dimensions (we have, thus, mono-, bi-, tri-, and four-dimensionally defective food concepts). For instance, if the aim of a diet is to prevent animal suffering, then a diet with a lower presence of food of animal origin is less defective than a diet including a higher level of animal food. At the same time, comparative assessments of defectiveness risk incurring significant margins of error and we shall not back up their generic usage here. This is because it is often difficult to find an evaluative standard agreed upon by different stakeholders and shared across different contexts. For instance, while it may be crucial for legal and economic purposes to pin down whether a plant-based hamburger is meat, for the sake of ordinary conversation the question may not arise at all or come off as brainy and futile.

These two major avenues of defectiveness for food concepts, by themselves, are unable to explain where the defectiveness of a given food concept may lie, in a way that suggests how the concept may be amended, negotiated, and hopefully improved. A more promising strategy we wish to pursue here is to put together the two avenues with the analysis of the four dimensions we proposed in the previous section. By means of this strategy we can pinpoint why a given concept is defective, that is, which (aspects of the) dimensions of the concept make it defective.

Now, the dimensions of a concept can be linked in multifarious ways to the avenues of defectiveness. To provide some order to our analysis, we introduce four types of defects that may affect a food concept. These defects—we contend—cover the most common sources of conceptual failures when it comes to food, though of course they do not pretend to exhaust all the possible conceptual failures that have and will emerge in food cultures. We first briefly characterize the defects, to then exemplify them. As it goes, they typically emerge when different stakeholders buy into different and conflated versions of the same concept, without negotiating a common content and structure.

  1. (a)

    Fragility, that occurs when a concept does not deliver definite or informative contents with respect to the four dimensions. A fragile concept may fail to include sufficient information for representing what it is supposed to refer to, or feasible indications for the aims it strives for.

  2. (b)

    Polarization, that occurs when the concept can stand a plurality of mutually inconsistent interpretations leading up to some clashes (e.g., over ethical, political, or cultural values).

  3. (c)

    Incoherence, that occurs when there is a mismatch between the first three dimensions of the concept and its aims.

  4. (d)

    Schizophrenia, that occurs when there is a combined endorsement of dimensions pertaining to different instantiations of a concept. A schizophrenic concept represents disparate non-mutually related states of affairs, resulting in being practically useless since it is unclear what are its contents and aims.

We shall now illustrate how the four defects actually affect food concepts. To do so, we chose two widely used examples—local food and healthy food. Before moving on to that task, however, one more issue shall be addressed, albeit briefly: whether the degree of defectiveness of a food concept is owed to its internal constitution or to external conditions.

It is tempting to think that some concepts are defective due to some internal conditions. Plausible candidates may be those concepts having a partisan origin and promoting unjust or unsound principles, like the already mentioned concepts of “Mediterranean Diet,” “food pyramid,” and “functional food,” which have been charged with internal flaws. Also, a concept may be misappropriated by an agent or a group of agents for achieving consequences that are undesirable to another agent or group. A case in point is “extra virgin olive oil,” which—at least according to Mueller (2011)—has been used for selling adulterated oil and hence defrauding consumers.Footnote 13

At the same time, some food concepts may become defective after serving desirable purposes because of changing external conditions. This is for instance the case of concepts that are no longer able to represent a food because the food itself changes, like the shift in underlying conditions that fixed the meaning of key food items such as “bread” and “yogurt” occurred in the US market in the 1970s (Pollan, 2008, pp. 148–154), or like the foods that had been contaminated with nuclear waste during the Chernobyl disaster, after which food concepts such as “fresh milk,” “local berries,” and “wild weeds” abruptly changed, from referring to safe and nutritious food to hazardous ones. Shifting social conditions may render a concept defective, too. A case in point is “wild food” when applied to non-Western foods, which can hardly explain different production and consumption patterns and, hence, turns into a fragile or schizophrenic concept (Borghini et al., 2020b).

The possibility that some food concepts are only externally—and not internally—defective suggests that not all food concepts are constitutively defective. For instance, the literature suggests that “organic,” as originally conceived, was highly functional to its scopes, i.e., providing foods totally free of synthetic additives and pesticides (see Fromartz, 2006). Other examples are provided by scientific concepts that are not defective in an original context of application, e.g., the concept of ketogenic diet when applied in controlled conditions for healthy losing weight to severely obese patients.

3.1 Local food

“Local food” is at once a model for sustainable dieting, a tool for socially valuable interaction, and a precious label in the market (Borghini, 2014; Gray, 2014; Yeung, 2014). It is often maintained that foods locally produced fit many ethical claims about alternative food production, the preservation of cultural heritage, social cohesion, sustainability, and so on (see McWilliams, 2010 for a critical overview). Yet, defining when a food is local is not as easy as it may seem. Building upon the study of local food begun in Borghini et al. (2021), we sort out three takes on the concept, which differ widely across the four conceptual dimensions. In the sequel, we provide a characterization of each take on the concept and sum up our analysis in Table 1. Then, we use the table to illustrate the four types of defects that a food concept can be charged with.

Table 1 Three chief takes on local food illustrated through their four conceptual dimensions

LF1. This is a distance-driven take on local food, according to which a food is local when it is consumed at less than some fixed distance to the production place. In this case, the data are the miles traveled by the food from the production place to the consumption one(s); the ontology is constituted by foods that have traveled less than the fixed distance; the fiat act is accomplished by an institution that fixes the number of miles and certifies how many miles a food has actually traveled; the aims and values typically involve the reduction of pollution due to food transportation, the improvement of local economies, or providing local consumers with fresh and safe food (e.g., Werkheiser & Noll, 2014).

LF2. This is a terroir-driven take, according to which a food is local when it owes its specific qualities to its place of production (i.e., climate, sun exposure, soil, rainfall) and to the traditional techniques rooted in that place, e.g., the Italian cheese Bitto owes its flavor to the environment where the cows that produce the milk grow and the curdling techniques adopted by local farmers.Footnote 14 In this case, the data are provided by the qualities featured by the food and the qualities of the place, in a sense as broad as including local practices; its ontology is fixed by a twofold framework, which includes the historical relations of the food to its production place and the causal link between the place’s properties and the food qualities; the fiat act is granted by an institution, e.g., a consortium, which establishes and certifies the link between the qualities of the food and the qualities of the placeFootnote 15; the main aim of the concept is to ground the intellectual property of the food to the producers located in that place (e.g., Giovannucci et al., 2009).

LF3. This is a socially driven take, according to which a food is local when the social distance between the different stakeholders is as short as possible in order to promote a joint protest against developmentalist forms of production. The data are the qualitative relations between consumers and producers; the ontology is populated by food items produced through just labor conditions, such as fair wages and trustworthiness; the fiat acts are the agreements stipulated between those agents, which jointly decide whether a food respects the criteria for being local, i.e., whether it has been produced in a fair way; the aim is preserving human relations between agents involved in food production and consumption (see Ho, 2020).

Table 1 below sums up these three takes on local food via specific examples, showcasing the variability of the concept across its four dimensions. Each row stands for one of the four conceptual dimensions, while each column represents a different instantiation of the concept of local food. We selected as an instance of LF1 the general guidelines about local food provided by the US Department of Agriculture; LF2 instantiates the Protected Designation of Origin specification of the Bitto cheese, i.e., Consorzio Tutela Bitto Casera della Valtellina; as an instance of LF3 we picked the concept of cosmopolitan locavorism recently developed by some Hong Kong young farmers and activists (Ho, 2020).

The table organizes the different instantiations of local food by teasing out their dimensions. It serves also to highlight the four defects that can affect a food concept—fragility, polarization, incoherence, and schizophrenia. We now provide a few examples for each kind of defect.Footnote 16

Fragility. Let us consider the data of LF1 and the methodologies adopted to gather them. The instantiation of the concept aims to increase the values of local economies, as established by the US Department of Agriculture, which also states that a food can boast of the title “local food” if it travels for no more than 400 miles. However, this distance is controversial: why the interests of local farmers can spread up to 400 miles? Isn’t there the possibility that different local interests conflict? In fact, according to some who still endorse this view, the number of miles should be considerably shorter, i.e., 100 miles (Smith & MacKinnon, 2007). As it would be easily imaginable, the distance cannot be fixed once for all since there is no objective or shared criterion of the measurement. This instantiation thus proves to be fragile inasmuch as it cannot provide a fixed method to establish how many miles a food can travel while remaining local. LF3 might be fragile too, as long as its data crucially depend on the feelings of involved agents, such as social cohesion, which are surely difficult to measure.

Polarization. Although the different takes of the concept may apply to different contexts, they are frequently employed in the same one. In this case, takes may conflict with each other ending with the polarization of the positions. For instance, consider when an international organization, e.g., the European Union, decides what should count as local food: should it endorse LF1 or LF2? If it endorses LF1, then many geographical indications nowadays considered as local food would be ruled out, e.g., Cioccolato di Modica, a renowned chocolate from Sicily, whose cacao seeds come from Mexico, would no longer be considered a local food.18 While, if the European Union would endorse LF2, then a European producer, say, of bananas, could not claim that the bananas it produces are local. In fact, bananas do not hold any special link to Europe and thus they match neither the data, nor the ontology of LF2. As long as these two instantiations cannot be integrated, they turn out to be polarized within the same context, i.e., the legislative camp of the European Union.

Incoherence. The instantiations of the concept may often fail to reach their aims or express a value due to an incoherence between the contents of its dimensions. For instance, LF2 could fail to preserve local intellectual properties, if the place where a certain food is produced is owned by non-local companies that however fulfill all the other dimensions. Indeed, the dimensions of LF2 fail to specify who should own the specific place where the food is produced. In that case, the intellectual property of that food is not held by local producers. Thus, the aim of the concept is not accomplished, even if all the other dimensions are respectively satisfied.

Schizophrenia. Some actors, more or less consciously, may endorse the contents of dimensions pertaining to different instantiations of the same concepts, ending up mixing them in a concept that is not well-integrated. In fact, very often, it is not clear at all who can and should set up a concept and what is the normative standard they should abide by. Consumers’ associations and cartels of producers provide different conflating notions of local food feeding a schizophrenic understanding of it. In fact, the absence of a common negotiation and a shared evaluative standard may result in allowing the most diverse versions of a food concept. For instance, a survey by Durham et al. (2009) shows that many American consumers endorse LF1. However, they replace the food miles, i.e., the data of LF1, with the State where the food was produced. Thus, a food produced in Texas is local when it is consumed in Texas, regardless of whether the distance between the production and the consumption places exceeds 400 miles. It is clear that local food could no longer be based on an ontology that rests on miles, but might instead switch to, say, the ontology of LF2. Local consumers can indeed justify their belief that the food produced in their State is comparatively better than the ones produced away due to a special link with its place. This new take of local food is composed of a new datum and the ontology of LF2. The fiat act can in turn be charged by the involved agents, who should recognize where the food comes from. It somehow matches the fiat act of LF3. Its aims, finally, may remain the ones of LF1.

The resulting take appears to be schizophrenic for a number of reasons: its data and its ontology mismatch: the State where a food comes from, which is the new datum of the take, does not suffice as a basis of an LF2 ontology since it does not spell out the relations between the qualities of a food and the qualities of the place; the fiat act so redefined may, in turn, fail to provide a basis for the ontology of the take. The agents involved, who basically are the consumers, could not have the right expertise to justify the relation between a food and a place. Finally, the aims of LF1 are disconnected from the other dimensions. The same State may be populated by different competing local economies, so the new datum can hinder that aim; the link between food and place, as required by ontology, can undermine the aim of LF1 since a local farmer may also decide to produce more convenient food that is nonetheless not historically rooted in that place of production. Therefore, due to the lack of internal integration, this take on local food fails to accomplish its intended aim.

3.2 Healthy food

Healthy food can be framed either in terms of the absence of harm, i.e., the idea that food must not be poisonous, or in terms of benefits, i.e., food should enhance health (Murphy, 2020). As many scholars suggest (e.g., Siipi, 2013), it is disputed whether healthy food is a concept that should consider a single food item as capable of being healthy for us, or it should consider the healthiness of a whole diet, or of ways of consumption. It turns out that what healthy food means is unclear. We propose four different instantiations of the concept of healthy food to be broken down in the comparative table.

HF1. The first is nutritionism (Scrinis, 2008, 2013), which claims that healthy food has a specific configuration of nutrients. It identifies a reductionist paradigm characterized by a microscopic focus on food composition: food-body-health interaction is understood and framed in biochemical terms. Nutritionism is the dominant ideology within nutrition science, and implies a reductive approach to health as well: as Scrinis puts it, health is reduced to a set of diet-related and quantifiable bio-markers, indicators, and functions. A typical expression of such reductionism is the association of a bodily process to particular food components and the assumption that health can be assessed through that specific association (e.g., glycemic index, body mass index). Data comes from the biochemistry of food and the frameworks of biomarkers; its ontology is populated by nutrients and their relations with human bodies; the fiat acts are performed by nutrition scientists, corporations, and individuals, when they endorse the nutritionist gaze (Scrinis, 2008); the aim is twofold: reaching health via nutritionally balanced diet; aligning individual food choices to the structures of the dominant agrifood system by shaping bodily functions ways that are manageable for science and institution, profitable for the food industry (Biltekoff et al., 2014; Hayes-Conroy et al., 2014; Scrinis, 2008).

HF2. The second instantiation invokes the idea that food is healthy when it is natural. This association has been well investigated by Siipi (2013), who concludes that there are multiple meanings of naturalness connected to the healthiness of food, e.g., “natural” as “familiar,” “natural” as “authentic,” “natural” as “what satisfies needs,” “natural” as “lacking human influence” (Siipi, 2008). The equation between healthy food and natural food never comes with an explicit reference to the kind of un/naturalness involved, making this conception of healthy food particularly problematic at its internal level. Both data and ontology are indeed dependent on the kind of naturalness taken into consideration: for “natural” as “customary,” for instance, cultural norms would be the data, and the food ontology will be ethnocentric (e.g., insects would not count as healthy food for individuals of a certain culture, because they are considered unnatural/not familiar).

HF3. The third instantiation centers around the principles of ecological nutrition, according to which the healthiness of a food depends upon the entire socio-ecological life of the item, from production to digestion. Data comes from the ecological system, food system, and human body (Klein, 2013; Guthman et al., 2014). The approach is intrinsically interdisciplinary: methodology from ecology, biomedicine, and agricultural sciences are applied to produce a systemic and integrated knowledge of food. The ontology is relational: different ontological layers are taken together, from the fine-grained entities to bigger biocultural networks. Fiat acts come from scientists, activists (take for instance the HFHC movement)Footnote 17 and institutions, but also from customers looking for more and complex information on the life-cycle of food they are purchasing. The aim of this approach is to consider food healthiness in the light of an ecological perspective, in which human bodies are systems connected to the broad environment: the health-related costs and benefits of food should be then assessed through this wider ecological network.

HF4. The fourth instantiation is the nutritional epigenetic approach: the idea that what is healthy is defined by our genetic response to dietary inputs. Like HF3, this approach endorses an increasingly relational biology (Landecker, 2011), more focused on network relations than on internal function and structures of single living entities (Powell & Dupré, 2009). Both HF3 and HF4 are sensitive to an ontological shift in understanding biological organization; in the definition of the environment (human body and food can be framed as environments at the same time) and metabolism, as a zone of regulation rather than energy conversion (Dupré & O’Malley, 2009; Landecker, 2013a, b). The data are the effects of nutrition on patterns of gene expression/regulation, gathered for instance through experiments on mice microbiota; fiat acts are performed mainly by researchers in areas like gene ecology, medical microbiology, epigenetics, system biology, gut-microbiome sciences and so on. This instantiation of healthy food goes in the direction of a stronger interplay of the nutritional and therapeutic functions of food, to the point that dietary inputs can be conceived as preventive and care tools.

By means of Table 2, we can illustrate the four conceptual defects that may affect a food concept.

Table 2 Four takes on healthy food declined through the four conceptual dimensions

Fragility. Among the four instantiations of the concepts of healthy food, HF2 appears as the most fragile. As mentioned above, the diversity of meanings that could be attributed to “naturalness” affects the concept of healthy food through all the dimensions—to the point that a comparative table for the family of HF2 could be easily imagined. A potential element of fragility can be found in HF4, in the data and methodologies dimension: many different disciplines converge under the label of nutritional ecology, with their own methods, taxa, and concepts. Such interdisciplinarity is a resource only when a methodological integrated framework is at play (Raubenheimer et al., 2009). Furthermore, each of the four instantiations tends to underestimate the role that unhealthy eating plays in relevant social occurrences, both formal and informal. Unhealthy foods may in fact enable experiences that provide highly desirable values, such as family or community identity, crucial for human psychological health (e.g., celebrations with specific cakes, see Barnhill et al., 2014). In this respect, each of the four instantiations could be marked with fragility since they do not include in their ontology specific food entities relevant for human well-being and they do not consider the aim of health in its multifactorial composition.Footnote 18

Polarization. Both HF1 and HF4 focus on the fine-grained layers of molecular interaction. The idea that diet affects physiology is at the very core of both positions but in substantially different ways. HF1 promotes the calculus of input–output, in which the body is the machine where transformation happens, and food is the measured input associated with projections on our body image and health—eat fewer calories to lose weight, take more vitamins to contrast aging. HF4 is not about knowing food components to create the right equation within the body-machine, but rather about how food affects our phenotype through mechanisms of attachment and removal of chemical marks to our DNA. In other words, it is about how food rules and shapes the metabolic equation (Landecker, 2011, 2013b). Two polarized concepts of metabolism and the human body are entailed in HF1 and HF4: clinical research targeting nutrition-related disease, for instance, would likely encounter some obstacles if both concepts are at play simultaneously within the research teams. As shown in Sect. 1.1, another kind of polarization occurs between HF1 and, for instance, HF3.

Incoherence. HF1 aims were divided into two: (a1) is the overt aim; (a2) refers to the broader function of nutritionism, that is, adapting our knowledge and practices about food and the body to the requirements of the agrifood industry (Scrinis, 2008). Nutritionism, thanks to its reductionist account of food, frames human physiology in manageable terms, facilitating its alignment with the dominant ways in which food is produced, processed, retailed, marketed, and consumed nowadays. The effectiveness of nutritionism for health has been largely disputed, both by food scholars and food scientists, mainly due to the oversimplification of eating and diets; the standardization of individual traits; the promotion of ultra-processed food through their supposed health and functional benefits (Pollan, 2008). Accordingly, we would consider HF1 coherent with a2, but incoherent with a1.

Schizophrenia. Supermarket shelves, with packaged and labeled food on display, overflow with examples of schizophrenic healthy food concepts. The plethora of tags and descriptions are, indeed, examples of how we tend to encounter the concept of healthy food: dimensions pertaining to different instantiations of the concept are combined, and endorsed simultaneously by a product. Take for instance a granola bar marketed as “healthy.” Imagine that “100% natural grains” is written down at the center of the green-washed packaging (HF2); at the same time a tag, slightly shifted on the left, stresses the bar’s biochemical features, e.g., “low sodium” (HF1); “no genetically engineered ingredients” shows up on the package as well, entailing a reference to the ecological history of the product (HF3). The bar endorses at least three different concepts of healthy food and the aim is not clear: what kind of health is fostered here? The tags may refer to different kinds of food values (e.g., naturalness as good per se) as well as they may jointly underlie a comprehensive notion of healthy food which includes all the aforementioned takes.Footnote 19 However, it may also be possible that the tags refer to different mutually inconsistent takes’ aims: having low sodium may be inconsistent with, say, the aim of being made by 100% natural grains. In fact, natural grain can be modified at a later stage for matching the low-sodium goal. This, in turn, is in stark contrast with HF3, while may be consistent with HF4.

Following Scrinis (2008), we could argue that creating conceptual confusion towards the healthiness of food is a commonly adopted marketing strategy, to which then, the same food industry responds by offering a simplified (HF2) and reductionist account of food (HF1) to anxious consumers. It seems therefore that some instantiations of healthy food show greater adaptability to, or even benefit from, situations of conceptual confusion.

4 Open problems

Our goal in this paper was to propose an analysis of the structure of food concepts and of their defects. We highlighted four dimensions for these concepts and used them to expose four types of defects. Providing methods to address these defects is an open problem that requires far more space than what we have here and that we reserve for the future. Still, what we have done so far clearly indicates plausible developments of our view.

First of all, our analysis brings to light three key areas of conceptual negotiation for food concepts. The highest level of negotiation takes place between different instantiations of a given concept, e.g., different takes on local food. At an intermediate level, we negotiate between different dimensions of a single instantiation, e.g., about which fiat acts should ground a distance-driven take on local food. At the lowest level, the negotiation concerns one specific dimension, and we pointed out several examples of this sort of negotiation along the paper. The two case studies we discussed—local food and healthy food—well illustrate the three areas of conceptual negotiation.

Secondly, as the case studies we survey demonstrate, our approach can be put to use in providing a conceptual map of a given food concept, which would be divided according to the three levels and would highlight critical spaces of negotiation.

The work ahead of us, then, is to further clarify the three levels of negotiation and how they can be employed to develop conceptual maps for negotiating food concepts. Conceptual maps seem a promising tool for addressing the challenge of integrating the vast and varied knowledge about food that scholars and practitioners have impressively recorded in recent years. In this sense, our study stands as an example of how philosophers can serve the much-needed role of bridging across different camps of knowledge, also when it comes to food and eating.Footnote 20