Skip to main content
Log in

De-Ontologizing the Debate on Social Explanations: A Pragmatic Approach Based on Epistemic Interests

  • Research Paper
  • Published:
Human Studies Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

In a recent paper on realism and pragmatism published in this journal, Osmo Kivinen and Tero Piiroinen have been pleading for more methodological work in the philosophy of the social sciences—refining the conceptual tools of social scientists—and less philosophically ontological theories. Following this de-ontologizing approach, we scrutinize the debates on social explanation and contribute to the development of a pragmatic social science methodology. Analyzing four classic debates concerning explanation in the social sciences, we propose to shift the debate away from (a) the ontologizing defenses of forms of social explanation, and (b) a winner-takes-all-approach. Instead, we advocate (c) a pragmatic approach towards social explanation, elaborating a rigorous framework for explanatory pluralism detached from the debates on social ontology.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. For more details on the erotetic model, see, e.g., Garfinkel (1981); Kincaid (1997); Risjord (2000); van Fraassen (1980).

  2. P and P′ are supposed to be mutually exclusive.

  3. Two kinds of fine-grain preference can be distinguished: the small-grain preference and close-grain preference. We will discuss the small-grain preference in this section; in the social sciences, the small-grain preference advises to look for detailed individualistic micro-accounts that replace macro-level accounts. The close-grain preference is a matter of favoring explanations that provide the detailed mediating mechanisms in causal chains across time. Explanations satisfying this preference will not leave any causal gaps in the temporal chain of events. So any explanatory factor that is at a temporal remove from the fact explained should be replaced by a factor closer to the fact. We will deal with the close-grain preference in section A third debate: remote versus proximate causes in structural explanations.

  4. Lacking a better term; possible alternatives might be non-ontologizing strategy (in order to emphasise the distinction with the ontologizing strategy, but it might suggest that no ontological claims at all are made in this strategy, which is, of course, incorrect) or pragmatic strategy (as the core of the strategy is avoiding a kind of eternal truths or a priori ontological stances).

  5. Cf., Kincaid (1997, p. 4): “Both individualists and holists often claim that their position is some kind of conceptual truth—that more or less a priori, perfectly general considerations show the other side inevitably flawed. I will argue that this approach is misguided. The real issues are ultimately empirical ones about how the world works.” And, Kivinen and Piiroinen (2006, p. 324): “Unlike those who believe that philosophical revelations of reality are the proper basis of scientific research practices, we prefer to approach social sciences from just about the opposite direction—from the direction of problem-driven methodology, instead of metaphysical theorizing.”

  6. Cf. Sober (1999, p. 554): “The multiple realizability argument is not needed to show that the thesis of reducibility in practice is false; one can simply inspect present-day science to see this.”

  7. See Vanderbeeken and Weber (2002), Weber and Vanderbeeken (2005) for explanations of individual actions.

  8. For the micro-foundations and micro-mechanisms idea, see as well Little (1991, 1998); this idea is still very popular in the social sciences, e.g., Hedström and Swedberg (1998).

  9. Taylor refers to Jon Elster’s Explaining technical change (1983, pp. 24, 28–29).

  10. We have elaborated the distinction between both forms of explanations here to show how both have their benefits. We do not want to exclude the possibility of explanations that combine both levels. These latter ones could provide the most adequate answer to some explanation-seeking why-question, as well.

  11. According to Elster: “The attraction stems, I believe, from the implicit assumption that all social and psychological phenomena must have a meaning, i.e., that there must be some sense, some perspective in which they are beneficial for someone or something; and that furthermore these beneficial effects are what explain the phenomena in question.” (Elster 1994, p. 403).

  12. This point is developed by Philip Pettit (1996). Virtual selection can be understood as follows: were the trait in question to be in danger of disappearing then a selectional mechanism would be activated that would preserve it against that danger (In general: the selectional mechanism may not operate under actual circumstances but would operate under relevant counterfactual conditions).

  13. For a more extensive discussion (including real examples relating to the political history of South-American countries), see Van Bouwel and Weber (2002).

  14. Other aficionados of the social mechanism approach are, e.g., the contributors to Hedström and Swedberg (1998); Hedström (2005); Elster (1999); Tilly (2001), etc.

References

  • Axelrod, R. (1984). The evolution of cooperation. New York: Basic Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cohen, G. A. (1978). Karl Marx’s theory of history. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dewey, J. (1991). Logic: The theory of inquiry. The later works of John Dewey. In J. A. Boydston (Ed.), Paperback edition. Carbondale and Edwardsville (Vol. 12). IL: Southern Illinois University Press. (Original work published 1938).

    Google Scholar 

  • Elster, J. (1982). Marxism, functionalism and game theory. Theory and Society, 11, 453–482.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Elster, J. (1983). Explaining technical change. A case study in the philosophy of science. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Elster, J. (1984). Ulysses and the Sirens. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Elster, J. (1983/1994). Functional explanation: In social science. In M. Martin & L. McIntyre (Eds.), Readings in the philosophy of social science (pp. 403–414). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

  • Elster, J. (1999). Alchemies of the mind: Rationality and emotions. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Garfinkel, A. (1981). Forms of explanation. Rethinking the questions in social theory. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gorski, P. (2004). The poverty of deductivism: A constructivist realist model of sociological explanation. Sociological Methodology, 34, 1–34.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hedström, P. (2005). Dissecting the social: On the principles of analytical sociology. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hedström, P., & Swedberg, R. (Eds.). (1998). Social mechanisms. An analytical approach to social theory. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kincaid, H. (1997). Individualism and the unity of science. Lanham, MD: Rowman & Littlefield Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kivinen, O., & Piiroinen, T. (2006). Toward pragmatist methodological relationalism: From philosophizing sociology to sociologizing philosophy. Philosophy of the Social Sciences, 36, 303–329.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kivinen, O., & Piiroinen, T. (2007). Sociologizing metaphysics and mind: A pragmatist point of view on the methodology of the social sciences. Human Studies, 30, 97–114.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Little, D. (1991). Varieties of social explanation. Boulder, CO: Westview Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Little, D. (1998). Microfoundations, method, and causation. New Brunswick: Transaction Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pettit, P. (1996). Functional explanation and virtual selection. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 47, 291–302.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Risjord, M. (2000). Woodcutters and witchcraft. Rationality and interpretive change in the social sciences. Albany, NY: State University of New York Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sawyer, R. K. (2003). Nonreductive individualism. Part II–social causation. Philosophy of the Social Sciences, 33, 203–224.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Skocpol, T. (1979). States and social revolutions. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sober, E. (1999). The multiple realizability argument against reductionism. Philosophy of Science, 66, 542–564.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Steel, D. (2005). Mechanisms and functional hypotheses in social science. Philosophy of Science, 72, 941–952.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Taylor, M. (1988). Rationality and revolutionary collective action. In M. Taylor (Ed.), Rationality and revolution (pp. 63–97). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tilly, C. (2001). Mechanisms in political processes. Annual Review of Political Science, 4, 21–41.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Van Bouwel, J. (2004a). Individualism and holism, reduction and pluralism. Philosophy of the Social Sciences, 34, 527–535.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Van Bouwel, J. (2004b). Questioning structurism as a new standard for social scientific explanations. Graduate Journal of Social Science, 1, 204–226.

    Google Scholar 

  • Van Bouwel, J. (2004c). Explanatory pluralism in economics: Against the mainstream? Philosophical Explorations, 7, 299–315.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Van Bouwel, J., & Weber, E. (2002). Remote causes, bad explanations? Journal for the Theory of Social Behavior, 32, 437–449.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Van Bouwel, J., & Weber, E. (2008). A pragmatic defence of non-relativistic explanatory pluralism in history and social science. History and Theory, 47, 168–182.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Vanderbeeken, R., & Weber, E. (2002). Dispositional explanations of behavior. Behavior & Philosophy, 30, 43–59.

    Google Scholar 

  • Van Fraassen, B. C. (1980). The scientific image. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Watkins, J. (1973). Methodological individualism: A reply. In J. O’Neill (Ed.), Modes of individualism and collectivism (pp. 179–184). London: Heinemann.

    Google Scholar 

  • Weber, E., & Van Bouwel, J. (2002). Can we dispense with the structural explanation of social facts? Economics and Philosophy, 18, 259–275.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Weber, E., & Vanderbeeken, R. (2005). The functions of intentional explanations of actions. Behavior & Philosophy, 33, 1–16.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgement

Jeroen Van Bouwel is a Postdoctoral Fellow of the Scientific Research Foundation, Flanders (Belgium). The authors would like to thank the anonymous reviewers for their comments on an earlier version of this paper.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Jeroen Van Bouwel.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Van Bouwel, J., Weber, E. De-Ontologizing the Debate on Social Explanations: A Pragmatic Approach Based on Epistemic Interests. Hum Stud 31, 423–442 (2008). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10746-008-9102-0

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10746-008-9102-0

Keywords

Navigation