Skip to main content

Advertisement

Log in

The Priority of Legitimacy in Times of Political Transition

  • Published:
Human Rights Review Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

This paper interprets the relation between justice and legitimacy found in John Rawls's Political Liberalism and then applies it to the field of transitional justice. The author argues that transitional mechanisms can be better defended in terms of “legitimacy” than in “justice,” because the circumstances of transitional justice admit of reasonable disagreement over “just” public policy. In such circumstances, policy recommendations can always be construed as falling short of justice, thus raising plausible concerns over their normative justification. This paper attempts to answer such concerns by justifying transitional mechanisms as morally appropriate yet less than fully just. The author explains how the concept of legitimacy facilitates such a justification and how such a justification can secure the normative grounds that are ironically threatened by investigations relying on a concept of justice.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. One possible exception is Jose Zalaquett who outlines three “conditions of legitimacy” for any transitional policy. However, his use of the term “legitimacy” means little more than consistent with “contemporary values enshrined in international law and generally accepted legal doctrine” (Zalaquett 1990, p. 628).

  2. Some important articles focusing on this issues include Dreben (2002), Buchanan (2000), Estlund (1996), Wenar (2004), and Weinstock (1994).

  3. Typically, commentators make legitimacy derivative of justice by employing the familiar idea that one must first determine what justice requires before one can articulate the legitimate use of coercive power. One variant of this view denies a close relation between legitimacy and justice in PL because it interprets PL primarily as a treatise on the legitimate use of coercive law rather than justice (Dreben 2002, p. 317; Estlund 1996, p. 68). Another splits legitimacy from justice by attaching legitimacy to citizens’ conceptions of the good rather than a justification of the right (Weithman 2013, p. 5).

  4. Buchanan uses a conceptually loose construction of the “reasonable.” As a result, he draws the provisional conclusion that “the primacy of legitimacy may be compatible with a law of peoples that is much more egalitarian than Rawls supposes” (Buchanan 2000, p. 88 emphasis added).

  5. I use “social unity” rather than “stability” because Rawls later restates the problem as one of social unity rather than stability, noting the latter has an “uninteresting Hobbesian answer” (Rawls 1993, pp. 27n, 391; Rawls 2001a, p. 82n).

  6. In addition to these, Rawls also identifes three conditions for assessing the justification of principles: (1) a specification of certain basic rights, liberties and opportunities (of a kind familiar to a constitutional democratic regime); (2) an assignment of special priority to those rights, liberties, and opportunities, especially with respect to the claims of the general good and of perfectionist values; and (3) measures assuring to all citizens adequate all-purpose means to make effective use of their liberties and opportunities (Rawls 1993, pp. xlviii, 6; Rawls 2001a, p. 14).

  7. While not normally expressed as a “problem,” this expression has been distilled from the secondary literature, including but not limited to the following: Zalaquett (1990), Arthur (2009), Elster (2006), Huntington (1991), Teitel (2000), United Nations Security Council (2004).

  8. This represents Rawls’s fifth “burden of judgment” (Rawls 1993, 55–56).

  9. Neil Kritz estimates that nearly half the population was implicated as having supported the previous regime in some countries of the former Warsaw Pact (Kritz 1995, p. xxii).

  10. This represents Rawls’s third “burden of judgment” (Rawls 1993, pp. 55–56).

  11. The challenge is quite conspicuous in attempts to coordinate Disarmament, Demobilization and Reintegration programs with TJ measures, since the former is primarily concerned with alleviating the most egregious injustices resulting from conflict and has consequentialist aims in mind, while the latter is framed in terms of human rights violations against victims and operates with deontological considerations (Buckley and Tomb 2012).

  12. This represents Rawls’s second ‘burden of judgment’ (Rawls 1993, pp. 55–56).

  13. As Thomas Nagel notes, “the hardest problems of political theory are conflicts within the individual,” that is, between the personal and impersonal standpoints within each person (Nagel 1991, p. 4).

  14. This represents Rawls’s first ‘burden of judgment’ (Rawls 1993, pp. 55–56)

References

  • Aguilar, P. 2001. Justice, Politics and Memory in the Spanish Transition. In: A. B. De Brito, C. G. Enríquez, and P. Aguilar (eds) The Politics of Memory. Transitional Justice in Democratizing Societies, pp. 92–119.

  • Albon, M. 1992. The Project on Justice in Times of Transition. In: Salzburg, Austria: The Charter 77 Foundation-New York. Report of the Project Inaugural Meeting, Salzburg, 7–l0 March I992

  • Amnesty International and Human Rights Watch. 2003. Truth and Justice: Unfinished Business in South Africa. AL3102. South African Historical Archive.

  • Arthur, P. 2009. How ‘Transitions’ Reshaped Human Rights: A Conceptual History of Transitional Justice. Human Rights Quarterly 31 (2): 321–367.

    Google Scholar 

  • Asmal, K. 2013. Truth, Justice and Reconciliation. Cape Town, South Africa. International Center for Transitional Justice Archives.

  • Bell, C. 2009. “Transitional Justice, Interdisciplinarity and the State of the ‘Field’ or ‘Non-field’.” International Journal of Transitional Justice 3 (1): 5–27.

    Google Scholar 

  • “Beyond Verdict Text.” 2012. The Egyptian Gazette, June 3.

  • Boraine, Alex. 2001. Truth and Reconciliation in South Africa: The Third Way. In: R. I. Rotberg and D. Thompson (eds) Truth V. Justice: The Morality of Truth Commissions, pp. 141–157. Princeton University Press, Princeton.

  • Buchanan, A. 2000. Justice, Legitimacy, and Human Rights. In: Davion, V. &Wolf, C. (eds) The Idea of a Political Liberalism. Essays on Rawls. Rowman & Littlefield Publishers Inc, Lanham, pp. 73–89.

  • Buckley, M. 2010. “The Structure of Justification in Political Constructivism.” Metaphilosophy 41 (5): 669–689.

  • Buckley, M and Nick Tomb. 2012. “A Just Peacemaking Process: The UN’s Integration of Transitional Justice with DDR.” In Anja Mihr (ed) Transitional Justice: Between Criminal Justice, Atonement and Democracy, ed. Netherlands Institute of Human Rights, Utrecht.

  • Chhang, Y. 2007. The Thief of History—Cambodia and the Special Court. International Journal of Transitional Justice 1 (1) (March 1): 157–172.

  • Clark, Phil. 2010. The Gacaca Courts, Post-Genocide Justice and Reconciliation in Rwanda. Cambridge Studies in Law and Society. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • De Greiff, Pablo, and Alexander Mayer-Rieckh. 2007. Justice as Prevention: Vetting Public Employees in Transitional Societies. SSRC.

  • Dreben, B. 2002. On Rawls and Political Liberalism.” In Samuel Freeman (ed) The Cambridge Companion to Rawls, 316–346. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge.

  • Du Toit, Andre. 2001. The Moral Foundations of the South African TRC: Truth and Acknowledgment and Justice as Recognition. In: R. I. Rotberg and D. Thompson (eds) Truth V. Justice: The Morality of Truth Commissions. Princeton University Press, Princeton, pp. 122–140.

  • Duggan, C. 2010. “Editorial Note.” International Journal of Transitional Justice 4 (3): 315–328.

  • Elster, J. 2004. Moral Dilemmas of Transitional Justice. In: Peter Baumann and Monika Betzler (eds) Practical Contexts: New Philosophical Essays. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, pp. 295–315.

  • Elster, Jon. 2006. Introduction. In: Elster, J (ed) Retribution and Reparation in the Transition to Democracy. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, pp. 1–14.

  • Estlund, D. 1996. The Survival of Egalitarian Justice in John Rawls’s Political Liberalism. Journal of Political Philosophy 4 (1): 68–78.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fox, Jonathan. 2007. The Uncertain Relationship Between Transparency and Accountability. Development in Practice 17 (4–5): 663–671.

  • Freeman, S. 2007. Rawls. Routledge, New York, NY.

  • Gates, Scott, Helga Malmin Binningsbo, and Tove Grete Lie. 2007. Post-Conflict Justice And Sustainable Peace. World Bank Publications, Washington, DC.

  • Gutmann A, Thompson D. 2001. The Moral Foundations of Truth Commissions. In: R. I. Rotberg and D. Thompson (eds) Truth V. Justice: The Morality of Truth Commissions. Princeton University Press, Princeton.

  • Huntington, S. P. 1991. The Third Wave: Democratization in the Late Twentieth Century. Vol. 4. University of Oklahoma Press, Norman.

  • Jensen, Mark. 2009. The Limits of Practical Possibility. Journal of Political Philosophy 17 (2): 168–184.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kiss, Elizabeth. 2001. Moral Ambition Within and Beyond Political Constraints: Reflections on Restorative Justice. In: R. I. Rotberg and D. Thompson (eds) Truth V. Justice: The Morality of Truth Commissions. Princeton University Press, Princeton, pp. 68–98.

  • Korsgaard, C. 2003. Realism and constructivism in twentieth-century moral philosophy. Journal of Philosophical Research 28: 99–122.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kritz, Neil J. 1995. “The Dilemmas of Transitional Justice.” In: Neil Kritz (ed) Transitional Justice: How Emerging Democracies Reckon with Former Regimes, Volume III: Laws, Rulings, and Reports, xix–xxxii. United States Institute of Peace, Washington, DC.

  • Mandle, J. 1999. The Reasonable in Justice as Fairness. Canadian Journal of Philosophy 29 (1): 75–107.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mill, John Stuart. 1965. The Collected Works of John Stuart Mill, Volume II—the Principles of Political Economy with some of their Applications to Social philosophy (Books I–II) [1848]. In: J.M. Robson (ed). Vol. 2. 33 vols. University of Toronto Press, Toronto.

  • Miller, David. 2008. Political Philosophy for Earthlings. In: David Leopold and Marc Stears (eds) Political theory: methods and approaches. Oxford University Press, New York.

  • Mydans, Seth. 2009. Trials in Cambodia Expose the Cogs in a Killing Machine. The New York Times, March 7.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nagel, Thomas. 1991. Equality and Partiality. Oxford University Press, New York.

  • Olsen, Tricia D., Leigh A. Payne, and Andrew G. Reiter. 2010. Transitional Justice in Balance: Comparing Processes, Weighing Efficacy. United States Institute of Peace Press, Washington, DC.

    Google Scholar 

  • Orentlicher, D. F. 2007. ‘Settling Accounts’ Revisited: Reconciling Global Norms with Local Agency. International Journal of Transitional Justice 1 (1): 10–22.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Parfit, D. 1984. Reasons and Persons. Oxford University Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Payne, L. A., T. D. Olsen, and A. G. Reiter. 2008. Does Transitional Justice Work? In International Studies Association Convention, San Francisco, March, 26–29.

  • Posner, E. A., and A. Vermeule. 2004. Transitional Justice as Ordinary Justice. Harvard Law Review, pp. 761–825.

  • Rawls, J. 1993. Political Liberalism. Columbia University Press, New York.

  • Rawls, J. 1999a. A Theory of Justice, Revised Edition. Harvard University Press, Cambridge.

  • Rawls, J. 1999b. Collected Papers. Harvard University Press, Cambridge.

  • Rawls, J. 2001a. The Law of Peoples. Harvard University Press, Cambridge.

  • Rawls, J. 2001b. Justice As Fairness: A Restatement. In: Erin Kelly (ed). Harvard University Press, Cambridge.

  • Rorty, R. 1990. “The Priority of Democracy to Philosophy.” In Objectivity, Relativism and Truth, 1:175–196. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge.

  • Scanlon, T. M. 2003. Rawls on Justification. In: Freeman, S (ed) The Cambridge Companion to Rawls, pp. 139–167.

  • Sprecht, Irma. 2006. “Red Shoes: Experiences of Girl-combatants in Liberia,”. International Labor Organization.

  • Street, S. 2010. What Is Constructivism in Ethics and Metaethics? Philosophy Compass 5 (5): 363–384.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Teitel, Ruti G. 2000. Transitional Justice. Oxford University Press, New York

  • Thoms, O. N. T., J. Ron, and R. Paris. 2008. “The Effects of Transitional Justice Mechanisms.” Center for International Policy Studies, CIPS Working Paper. Available from Http://www.Humansecuritygateway.com/documents/CIPS_Transitional_Justice_April2008.Pdf [October26,2010].

  • Tucker, Aviezer. 2006. Rough Justice: Rectification in Post-authoritarian and Post-totalitarian Regimes. In: J. Elster (ed) Retribution and Reparation in the Transition to Democracy, 276–298. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge.

  • Tutu, D. 2002. Forward: Truth and Reconciliation Commission of South Africa Report. South African Government. http://www.info.gov.za/otherdocs/2003/trc/.

  • United Nations Security Council. 2004. Report of the Secretary-General on the Rule of Law and Transitional Justice in Conflict and Post-Conflict Societies. UN Doc. S/2004/616

  • Weinstein, H M. 2011. “Editorial Note: The Myth of Closure, the Illusion of Reconciliation: Final Thoughts on Five Years as Co-Editor-in-Chief.” International Journal of Transitional Justice 5 (1) (March 1): 1–10.

  • Weinstock, D. M. 1994. The Justification of Political Liberalism. Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 75 (3–4): 165–185.

    Google Scholar 

  • Weithman, P. 2013. Legitimacy and the Project of Political Liberalism. http://philosophy.nd.edu/assets/74988/legitimacyandtheprojectofrawlsspoliticalliberalism.pdf.

  • Wenar, L. 2004. The Unity of Rawls’s Work. The Journal of Moral Philosophy 1 (3): 265–275.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Zalaquett, J. 1990. Confronting Human Rights Violations Committed by Former Governments: Applicable Principles and Political Constraints. Hamline L. Rev. 13: 623.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Michael Buckley.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Buckley, M. The Priority of Legitimacy in Times of Political Transition. Hum Rights Rev 14, 327–345 (2013). https://doi.org/10.1007/s12142-013-0276-0

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s12142-013-0276-0

Keywords

Navigation