Skip to main content

Advertisement

Log in

Foreknowledge, accidental necessity, and uncausability

  • Article
  • Published:
International Journal for Philosophy of Religion Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Foreknowledge arguments attempt to show that infallible and exhaustive foreknowledge is incompatible with creaturely freedom. One particularly powerful foreknowledge argument employs the concept of accidental necessity. But an opponent of this argument might challenge it precisely because it employs the concept of accidental necessity. Indeed, Merricks (Philos Rev 118:29–57, 2009, Philos Rev 120:567–586, 2011a) and Zagzebski (Faith Philos 19(4):503–519, 2002, Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, 2011) have each written favorably of such a response. In this paper, I aim to show that responding to the accidental necessity version of the foreknowledge argument by disputing the concept of accidental necessity, including doing so in the ways these authors do, does not constitute a successful response to the foreknowledge argument. This is because there is an only slightly modified but still well-motivated version of the foreknowledge argument which employs the notion of uncausability rather than accidental necessity; and this argument is not threatened by objections to the concept of accidental necessity, including those objections offered by Zagzebski and Merricks. As recent literature on the foreknowledge argument has emphasized, when a response to a foreknowledge argument fails to threaten an only slightly modified but still well-motivated version of that argument, the response in question is not successful. So the responses to the accidental necessity version of the foreknowledge argument I have mentioned are not successful. Moreover, those working on foreknowledge arguments more generally should take seriously the uncausability version of the foreknowledge argument articulated here, as it may well be that still more responses to the foreknowledge argument will not threaten it, either.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Zagzebski (1996) calls this version “the strongest version of the foreknowledge dilemma.” An alternative version, which appeals to the notion of power over the past, derives from Nelson Pike (1965).

  2. Advocates of the Geachian view explored in (Todd 2011) may reject this way of supporting (1). For a criticism of Todd’s support for Geachianism, see (Byerly 2012a).

  3. I say this is the rough idea because there are some who would endorse (2) but who would reject understanding infallibility as implying that for any proposition p, if God believes p at t then p. Those who would do so would be those who think that non-time-indexed claims can change their truth-values, but time-indexed claims cannot.

  4. See (Zagzebski 1996).

  5. In my own view, some of the most interesting responses to foreknowledge arguments are ones which might be charitably interpreted as rejecting the assumption here that God’s belief occurs in the past, not because they hold to timelessness but because they hold that divine beliefs (or other mental states) occur only cross-temporally. See, e.g., (Zemach and Widerker 1987).

  6. For an overview of the principle of alternate possibilities, see (Widerker and McKenna 2006).

  7. For a recent defense, see (Rota 2010).

  8. E.g., (Van Inwagen 2008).

  9. See (Alston 1986).

  10. (Zagzebski 2011) presses this line.

  11. E.g., see (Adams 1967).

  12. In this section, I follow closely Zagzebski’s presentation in her (2011), which has no page numbers.

  13. For a review of such principles, see (O’Connor 2000).

  14. For a reflection on two-way power and causation in this vein, see (Lowe 2013).

  15. See, e.g., (McCann 2012) and (Goetz 2000).

  16. For simplicity’s sake here, I overlook a slightly different argument Merricks offers for the same conclusion on p.54 which makes a similar mistake as that made by the argument discussed in the main text. The alternative argument depends on the claim that God’s belief at \(\hbox {t}_{0}\) that Jones will sit at t depends on the truth at \(\hbox {t}_{0}\) of the proposition \(<\)Jones will sit at t\(>\). This claim is no more adequately defended than is the claim discussed in the main text that God’s belief at \(\hbox {t}_{0}\) that Jones will sit at t depends on Jones’s sitting at t.

  17. A similar problem seems to be at work in (McCall 2011) and (Westphal 2011)

  18. See especially (Byerly 2012b).

  19. For my part, I think Fischer and Tognazzini overlook another charitable reinterpretation of Merricks’s argument according to which it is not rhetorically infelicitous. Rather than thinking of Merricks as responding to an argument for fatalism, see Merricks as responding to an argument for the incompatibility of foreknowledge and freedom. If we think of Merricks’s work in this context, then his helping himself to the claim that Jones has a choice about his sitting is not ipso facto rhetorically problematic.

  20. See, e.g., (Plantinga 1986).

  21. As, e.g., in (Flint 1998).

  22. See, e.g., (Warfield 2010), (Byerly 2011) and (Jäger 2012)

  23. Again, see (Widerker and McKenna 2006).

  24. E.g., (Stump 2001), (Zagzebski 1996, 2000), and (Hunt 1999, 2000).

  25. For helpful discussion of roughly this point which does not apply it to the foreknowledge debate, see (Timpe 2006).

References

  • Adams, M. M. (1967). Is the existence of god a hard fact? The Philosophical Review, 76(4), 492–503.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Alston, W. P. (1986). Does god have beliefs? Religious Studies, 22(3–4), 287–306.

    Google Scholar 

  • Byerly, T. R. (2011). Ockhamism vs molinism, round two: A reply to warfield. Religious Studies, 47(4), 503–511.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Byerly, T. R. (2012a). “Explaining away the prevention argument for geachianism”. Ars Disputandi 12.

  • Byrely, T. R. (2012b). Infallible divine foreknowledge cannot uniquely threaten human freedom, but its mechanics might. European Journal for Philosophy of Religion, 4, 2.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fischer, J. & Tognazzini, N. (2012). Omniscience, freedom, and dependence. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research. doi:10.1111/j.1933-1592.2012.00606.x.

  • Flint, T. (1998). Divine providence: The molinist account. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Goetz, S. (2000). Naturalism and libertarian agency. In W. L. Craig & J. P. Moreland (Eds.), Naturalism: A critical analysis. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hunt, D. (1999). On augustine’s way out. Faith and Philosophy, 16(1), 3–26.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hunt, D. (2000). Moral responsibility and unavoidable action. Philosophical Studies, 97(2), 195–227.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jäger, C. (2012). Molina on foreknowledge and transfer of necessities. In C. Tapp & E. Runggaldier (Eds.), God, eternity, and time. Burlington, VT: Ashgate.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lowe, E. J. (2013). The will as a rational free power. In J. Greco & R. Groff (Eds.), Powers and capacities in philosophy: The new aristotelianism. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • McCall, S. (2011). The supervenience of truth: Freewill and omniscience. Analysis, 71, 501–516.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McCann, H. (2012). Making decisions. Philosophical Issues, 22, 246–263.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Merricks, T. (2009). Truth and freedom. The Philosophical Review, 118, 29–57.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Merricks, T. (2011a). Foreknowledge and freedom. The Philosophical Review, 120, 567–586.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Merricks, T. (2011b). Truth and molinism. In Ken Perszyk (Ed.), Molinism: The contemporary debate. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  • O’Connor, T. (2000). Persons and causes: The metaphysics of free will. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • O’Connor, T., & Jacobs, J. (2013). Agent causation in a neo-aristotelian metaphysics. In S. C. Gibb, E. J. Lowe, & R. D. Ingthorsson (Eds.), Mental causation and ontology. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pike, N. (1965). Divine omniscience and voluntary action. The Philosophical Review, 86, 209–216.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Plantinga, A. (1986). On ockham’s way out. Faith and Philosophy, 3(3), 235–269.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rota, M. (2010). The eternity solution to the problem of human freedom and divine foreknowledge. European Journal of Philosophy of Religion, 2(1), 165–186.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stump, E. (2001). Augustine and free will. In E. Stump & N. Kretzman (Eds.), The Cambridge Companion to Augustine. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Timpe, K. (2006). A critique of frankfurt-libertarianism. Philosophia, 34, 189–202.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Todd, P. (2011). Geachianism. In J. L. Kvanvig (Ed.), Oxford studies in philosophy of religion (Vol. 3). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Van Inwagen, P. (2008). What does an omniscient being know about the future. In J. L. Kvanvig (Ed.), Oxford studies in philosophy of religion (Vol. 1). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Warfield, T. (2010). Ockhamism and molinism: Foreknowledge and prophecy. In J. L. Kvanvig (Ed.), Oxford studies in philosophy of religion (Vol. 2). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Westphal, J. (2011). The compatibility of divine foreknowledge and freewill. Analysis, 71, 246–252.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Widerker, D., & McKenna, M. (Eds.). (2006). Moral responsibility and alternative possibilities: Essays on the importance of alternative possibilities. Burlington, VT: Ashgate.

  • Zagzebski, L. (1996). The dilemma of freedom and foreknowledge. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Zagzebski, L. (2000). Does libertarian freedom require alternative possibilities? Philosophical Perspectives, 14, 231–248.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zagzebski, L. (2002). Omniscience and the arrow of time. Faith and Philosophy, 19(4), 503–519.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Zagzebski, L. (2011). “Foreknowledge and free will”. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy. http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/free-will-foreknowledge/.

  • Zagzebski, L. (2012). Eternity and fatalism. In C. Tapp & E. Runggaldier (Eds.), God, eternity, and time. Burlington, VT: Ashgate.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zemach, E., & Widerker, D. (1987). Facts, freedom, and foreknowledge. Religious Studies, 23, 19–28.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to T. Ryan Byerly.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Byerly, T.R. Foreknowledge, accidental necessity, and uncausability. Int J Philos Relig 75, 137–154 (2014). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11153-013-9436-z

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11153-013-9436-z

Keywords

Navigation