Skip to main content
Log in

Pragmatic norms in science: making them explicit

  • Published:
Synthese Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

The present work constitutes an attempt to make explicit those pragmatic norms successfully operating in empirical science. I will first comment on the initial presuppositions of the discussion, in particular, on those concerning the instrumental character of scientific practice and the nature of scientific goals. Then I will depict the moderately naturalistic frame in which, from this approach, the pragmatic norms make sense. Third, I will focus on the specificity of the pragmatic norms, making special emphasis on what I regard as a key idea underlying them, namely, the view, vigorously advocated by classical pragmatists like C. S. Peirce and G. Vailati, that the best test for objectivity is the test of action. Finally, I am going to put forward a tentative list of pragmatic norms that can be abstracted from a careful observation and analysis of scientific practice as provided by current philosophers of experimentation (A. Franklin and F. Steinle among others). The norms will be divided into four classes corresponding to four aspects of science in which they rule, that is, self-correction, prediction, explanation and both experimentation and computation. In the following account, the formulation of those pragmatic norms successfully governing science will be understood as a contribution that scientifically-oriented pragmatism can make to the normative naturalistic project in epistemology.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

References

  • Almeder R. (2008) Pragmatism and science. In: Psillos S., Curd M. (eds) The Routledge companion to philosophy of science. Routledge, New York, pp 91–99

    Google Scholar 

  • Bechtel W. (2002) Aligning multiple research techniques in cognitive neuroscience: Why is it important?. Philosophy of Science 69: S48–S58

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Craver C. (2002) Interlevel experiments and multilevel mechanisms in the neuroscience of memory. Philosophy of Science 69: S83–S97

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Evans V. B. (1939) The pragmatism of Giovanni Vailati. International Journal of Ethics 403: 416–424

    Google Scholar 

  • Franklin A. (2005) No easy answers: Science and the pursuit of knowledge. University of Pittsburgh Press, Pittsburgh

    Google Scholar 

  • Gower B. (1997) Isaac Newton: Rules for reasoning scientifically. In: Gower B. (ed.) Scientific method: A historical and philosophical introduction. Routledge, London, pp 63–82

    Google Scholar 

  • Hon G. (2003) An attempt at a philosophy of experiment. In: Galavotti M. C. (ed.) Observation and experiment in the natural and social sciences. Kluwer Academic Publishers, Netherlands, pp 259–284

    Google Scholar 

  • Hookway C. (1999) Doubt: Affective states and the regulation of inquiry. In: Misak C.J. (ed.) Pragmatism. Canadian Journal of Philosophy. University of Calgary Press, Calgary, pp 203–226

    Google Scholar 

  • Hume, D. (1739–1740/1964). A treatise of human nature (Vol. I). London: Dent.

  • Kim J. (1988) What is ‘Naturalized epistemology’?. In: Sosa E., Kim J. (eds) Epistemology: An anthology. Blackwell Publishing, Malden, MA, pp 301–313

    Google Scholar 

  • Kitcher P. (1992) The naturalists return. The Philosophical Review 101(1): 53–114

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Laudan L. (1990) Normative naturalism. Philosophy of Science 57: 44–59

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lipton, P. (1991/2004). Inference to the best explanation. New York: Routledge.

  • Maffie J. (1990) Recent work on naturalized epistemology. American Philosophical Quarterly 27: 281–293

    Google Scholar 

  • Mayo D. G. (1996) Error and the growth of experimental knowledge. The University of Chicago Press, Chicago

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Messick S. (1989) Validity. In: Linn R. L. (ed.) Educational measurement. American Council on Education/Macmillan Publishing Company, New York, pp 13–103

    Google Scholar 

  • Newton, I. (1687/1848). Mathematical principles of natural philosophy. (Trans. by A. Motte, New York: Daniel Adee).

  • Peirce C. S. (1877a/2006) Some consequences of four incapacities. In: Haack S. (ed.) Pragmatism, old & new. Selected writings. Prometheus Books, New York, pp 69–105

    Google Scholar 

  • Peirce C. S. (1877b/2006) The fixation of belief. In: Haack S. (ed.) Pragmatism, old & new. Selected writings. Prometheus Books, New York, pp 107–126

    Google Scholar 

  • Peirce C. S. (1878/2006) How to make our ideas clear. In: Haack S. (ed.) Pragmatism, old & new. Selected writings. Prometheus Books, New York, pp 127–150

    Google Scholar 

  • Peirce, C. S. (1902–1907/2006). Pragmatism and pragmaticism. In S. Haack (Ed.), Pragmatism, old & new. Selected writings (pp. 151–167). New York: Prometheus Books.

  • Quine, W. V. O. (1990/2003). Pursuit of Truth. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

  • Quine, W. V. O & Ullian, J. S. (1970/1978). The web of belief. New York: McGraw-Hill Inc.

  • Rescher N. (1977) Methodological pragmatism. A systems-theoretic approach to the theory of knowledge. New York University Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Steinle F. (1997) Entering new fields: Exploratory uses of experimentation. Philosophy of Science 64(Supplement): s65–s74

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Suppes P. (1985) Explaining the unpredictable. Erkenntnis 22: 187–195

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Suppes P. (1998) Pragmatism in physics. In: Weingartner P., Schurz G., Dorn G. (eds) The role of pragmatics in contemporary philosophy. Hölder-Pichler-Tempsky, Vienna, pp 236–253

    Google Scholar 

  • Vailati G. (1907) The attack on distinctions. The Journal of Philosophy and Scientific Methods 4: 701–709

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Vailati, G., & Calderoni, M. (1909/2010). The origins and the fundamental idea of pragmatism. In C. Arrighi, P. Cantú, M. de Zan, & P. Suppes (Eds.), Logic and pragmatism: Selected essays by Giovanni Vailati (Chap. 18). Stanford: CSLI Publications.

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to María Caamaño Alegre.

Additional information

The resemblance between this title and that of Robert Brandom’s influential work, Making It Explicit (1994), is not casual. There he urged philosophers to make explicit those norms governing the use of words like ‘truth’ or ‘reality’ in actual linguistic practice, as the only way to provide an adequate characterization of the corresponding notions. The same need of explicitness is here vindicated with respect to norms guiding or aiming to guide scientific research, since no plausible understanding of such research seems possible if we ignore them.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Caamaño Alegre, M. Pragmatic norms in science: making them explicit. Synthese 190, 3227–3246 (2013). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-012-0150-7

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-012-0150-7

Keywords

Navigation