Skip to main content
Log in

Naturalizing Theorizing: Beyond a Theory of Biological Theories

  • Thematic Issue Article: The Meaning of “Theory” in Biology
  • Published:
Biological Theory Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Although “theory” has been the prevalent unit of analysis in the meta-study of science throughout most of the twentieth century, the concept remains elusive. I further explore the leitmotiv of several authors in this issue: that we should deal with theorizing (rather than theory) in biology as a cognitive activity that is to be investigated naturalistically. I first contrast how philosophers and biologists have tended to think about theory in the last century or so, and consider recent calls to upgrade the role of theory in the life sciences against the background of the recent “data deluge” in molecular biology, systems biology, etc. I then review thinking about theory in biology in relation to physical theory as a positive or negative exemplar. I conclude by discussing various aspects of a positive program for “naturalizing theorizing.”

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Fig. 1

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Inspired by Schopenhauer and Nietzsche, the Lebensphilosophie of Wilhelm Dilthey, Henri Bergson, Ludwig Klages, and others was a reaction against the theoretical focus of neo-Kantianism, anti-religious naturalism, and the rise of positivism. It is superbly embodied by Ulrich, the protagonist in Musil’s The Man Without Qualities (19531954) who pursues a “hovering life” between science and mysticism.

  2. The traditional goal of philosophy was practical: to orient one toward a life of έύδαιμονία (flourishing). Plato and Aristotle would have been perplexed by our plea for a pragmatic or pragmatist turn in thinking about theory.

  3. As “the big picture of science” dealing with the fundamental laws of the universe, physics is characterized even today as the study of “the mind of God” (http://www.physicsforums.com/showthread.php?t=134150); see Fig. 1.

  4. Contrast Fuller’s (2009) critique of the under-laborer “syndrome” with Griesemer’s (2011) advocacy of “philosophy for science.”

  5. By no means does it follow from this that science has become “metaphysically neutral,” as many anti-creationism crusaders would have it. Metaphysical assumptions such as the principles of the uniformity of nature and causality continue to guide the theoretical and empirical study of nature heuristically, and are increasingly supported by scientific evidence (Wartofsky 1967; Fry 2012).

  6. This label, apparently coined by Hilary Putnam in 1960, sounds rather dated today, but has become so entrenched that we continue to use it.

  7. “Tunnel vision” is often associated with Kuhnian “normal science” as routine (Nelson and Winter 1982; Nickles 2003b).

  8. The literature abounds with references to the “nature” of theories, etc. “Nature” (in the sense used here) is a synonym of “essence.” What can this mean in a naturalistic perspective? “In keeping with evolutionary ideas, … nothing outside the realm of abstract constructions, such as a geometrical circle, has anything like an essence to be captured in an explicit definition” (Giere 2006b, p. 53). Yet most analytic philosophy continues to debate the proper account of concepts in terms of necessary and sufficient conditions, as if these concepts had essences. In sequences of exchanges, philosophers propose definitions, which are then “refuted” by a couple of counterexamples, upon which the definition is modified, etc. Such debates can go on until the participants must quit from sheer exhaustion (Kitcher 2012). In a broader societal context, philosophers have not on the whole been very effective in the creationism/intelligent design debate. If they don’t manage to demarcate science from religion or pseudoscience (Nickles 2006), who can do better? I suggest that rather than resting on their “quietist” oars philosophers reflect, for instance, on how it is that science museologists cope very well with the demarcation of science, for instance from art (Wagensberg 2006). What is their secret?

  9. Philosophers of biology, being by and large scientific realists, have devoted little attention to prediction as distinguished from explanation after Hempel’s “symmetry thesis” was given up (Salmon 1989). But many scientists, including biologists, continue to invoke predictive power as a major virtue of theory. The US National Academy of Sciences (http://www.nap.edu/openbook.php?record_id=11876&page=11) states: “One of the most useful properties of scientific theories is that they can be used to make predictions about natural events or phenomena that have not yet been observed. … The evolutionary biologists who discovered Tiktaalik … predicted that they would find fossils intermediate between fish and limbed terrestrial animals in sediments that were about 375 million years old. Their discovery confirmed the prediction made on the basis of evolutionary theory. In turn, confirmation of a prediction increases confidence in that theory.”

  10. One can safely bet that as one of Holton’s (1973) “themata,” reduction will remain on the agenda, the current “anti-reductionist consensus” in the philosophy of biology notwithstanding.

  11. I agree with Hull (1988, p. 494): “one of the persistent goals of scientists is to present theories that are as universal and coherent as possible. … It is not a valid criticism of a theory that it is not currently totally global and coherent.” Aiming for generality within a theory should not be conflated with “the ideal of providing the single complete and comprehensive truth about a domain” (Kellert et al. 2006, p. xxiv).

  12. By way of example: Hull’s “conceptual systems” at any one time are almost as heterogeneous as biological species. This conceptual heterogeneity even increases if one follows them through time. One could say that heterogeneity is constitutive of evolving entities. Hull also argued that the lack of conceptual homogeneity in science is often compensated by the social coherence resulting from the imperative to cooperate.

  13. Theories are needed in all walks of life and well beyond. While most cognitive scientists agree today that explicit theories are not required to explain what humans do in many contexts, “there are important arenas of individual and organizational behavior where mental models or theories do play an important role” (Nelson 2008, p. 78).

  14. Cf. Hull (1988, p. 485) on the “bracketing” of a widely held theory to see what the relevant phenomena look like without this presupposition, and Nelson and Winter (1982, p. 414) on how a different angle can provide “relief from distorting shadows.” See also the section, “Toward a Perspectivist Theoretical Biology.”

  15. Isabella Sarto-Jackson correctly points out to me that “speculation”—a term that is often pejoratively loaded (cf. below)—should not be equated with “theorizing.” My claim derives from Mitroff’s (1984) tripartition of scientists into “experimentalists,” “middle-of-the-road,” and “speculative theorists” on the basis of a case study of the psychology of senologists (Rowan 1981, p. 39), in which “speculation” has a pejorative or positive connotation according to scientists’ position in the field. Experimentalists were characterized as analytical and precise, collecting data and publishing them with little interpretation, and often priding themselves on “not speculating at all.” Speculative theorists were said to be extremely brilliant, creative, and aggressive; biased and rigid in defense of their position; excelling at extrapolating from data (their own, or others’); and relishing theorizing about them, and synthesizing (coming out with a “big picture”). The majority of the senologists Mitroff studied were “middle of the road,” flexible in being able to get good data and interpret them in interesting ways. Prestige in the field was lowest for the experimentalists (sometimes dismissed as “technicians with PhDs”), and highest for speculative theorists—contradicting the widespread impression that medical research is anti-theoretically biased. Mitroff’s evidence was obviously limited; but I am quite confident that an investigation of other fields—say, animal behavior and cognition studies, or ecology—would reveal a similar pattern.

  16. See Krohs and Callebaut (2007) and Callebaut (2012). The crude empiricist “forgets that even the greatest amount of collected facts as little constitutes a science as a heap of bricks constitutes a house” (von Bertalanffy 1932, p. 2); cf. Hull (1988, p. 488) on “the vision of armies of unlettered data gatherers” in pheneticism. It is this crude form of empiricism that invited Rutherford to tease that physics is the only real science, and the rest are just “stamp collecting.”

  17. In the Dutch psychologist de Groot’s (1961) influential formulation, the cycle consists of five sequential stages, viz.: (1) observation: collecting and grouping of empirical facts; (2) induction: formulation of hypotheses; (3) deduction: inferring special consequences from the hypotheses in the form of testable predictions; (4) testing of the hypothesis/hypotheses on new evidence; (5) evaluation of the results of testing in relation to the proposed hypothesis/hypotheses or theory/theories, and in relation to possible new, follow-up research.

  18. In reviews of this article, Stuart Glennan and Kim Sterelny made the important point that biologists tend to contrast data with models rather than theories. Given the intricate intertwining of modeling and theorizing (“Semantic Views and Their Limitations” and “Theory (Re)vindicated” sections), this may make much work in biology look less theoretical than it actually is. According to Sterelny, “it is the complexity and variability of living systems, not the empiricism of life scientists, that make the issue problematic.” I can agree as far as most biology most philosophers of biology are dealing with is concerned, but would exempt other fields, in particular “big data biology,” from his verdict.

  19. The German botanist Johannes Reinke (1849–1931) introduced the idea of a “theoretical biology” in 1901: “The results of empirical biology are the objects of theoretical biology” (Reinke 1911, p. V). The German zoologist and developmental biologist Julius Schaxel (1887–1943), a student of Haeckel, was an early critic of the anti-science movement in Weimar culture: “Only one natural science, which … is not unambiguous, meets with approval. That is biology” (Schaxel 1919, p. 6). Schaxel emigrated to the Soviet Union in 1933, where he died in mysterious circumstances. Ludwig von Bertalanffy (1901–1972), who trained as a biologist in Austria (“One can always become a philosopher later!”), moved to the US in 1950. He is remembered most as one of the founders of General Systems Theory, which he hoped would provide “pre-Copernican” biology with a more solid scientific grounding.

  20. “Anthropology still painfully remembers the stomach-ache it got from the too easy generalizations of many nineteenth century ‘arm-chair ethnologists’” (Kluckhohn 1939, p. 328).

  21. At about the same time, another theoretical biologist, Rudolf Ehrenberg (1923, p. 5) wrote: “The fundamental biological law that will have to carry everything else will be characterized as ‘the law of the necessity of death.’ ” Freud’s “death drive” has been viewed as the psychological counterpart of this idea, which von Bertalanffy (1932, p. 3) criticized for being no more than the application of a brilliant, yet questionable aperçu. Like the paleontologist Louis Dollo (“evolution is irreversible”) before him, Ehrenberg was inspired by the entropy law of thermodynamics.

  22. To a large extent, this scholastic tendency may be the direct result of institutional constraints the analytic mainstream imposes on scholars (Preston 2007). To some extent, I’m afraid, it just reflects many philosophers’ unworldliness—“Why should I talk to biologists? I’m a philosopher, I read [other philosophers]!”

  23. While researching for this article I have found no good reasons, for the purposes at hand, to drive a philosophical wedge between the “conceptual” level (the term preferred by cognitive scientists) and the “theoretical” level. But see Downes (1992, p. 143) on putting a limit on what can be sensibly considered as a theory. Carnap’s conceptual–theoretical distinction is analyzed in Nersessian (1984).

  24. In Callebaut (2012) I attempt to specify what Woese meant by a “guiding vision” in terms of “perspectives” and “images.”

  25. In parallel, psychologists voice concern about the implications for their field of “evidence-based practice” (EBP), a generalization of “evidence-based medicine” that has grown to encompass many other disciplines and professions. EBP norms privilege quantitative studies at the expense of theoretical and qualitative studies. Dennis Wendt, for one, deplores “a rhetoric of objectivity that clouds over the interpretive and practical demands of the discipline, and the positivist assumption that discrete empirical findings somehow magically put themselves together in a coherent fashion.” He encourages psychologists “to take the evidence-based turn so seriously, as to become evidence-based nuisances in uncovering absurd claims by our colleagues” (http://www.theoreticalpsychologyblog.org/2012/06/06/bringing-the-evidence-based-turn-full-circle-critical-thinking-about-disciplinary-practices/).

  26. A report brief is available at http://dels.nas.edu/resources/static-assets/materials-based-on-reports/reports-in-brief/role_of_theory_final.pdf.

  27. Like Bertalanffy and others before them, the authors of the report fail to specify what it could mean for theory and evidence to be given “commensurate” attention. Hull’s “relevance to a powerful theory as the mark of a good description” seems to me a good starting point.

  28. In a “Washington Watch” of the American Institute of Biological Sciences, science reporters Menninger and Gropp (2008) begin their overall positive presentation of the report thus: “Compared with other scientific disciplines, some leaders in the science community have said, biology is too heavily centered on facts, with too little emphasis on underlying theory. The propagation of this misperception in recent years has very likely contributed to a drive to allocate larger portions of the federal research budget to nonbiological disciplines” (emphasis added).

  29. The mathematician G. H. Hardy, FRS, writing in the twentieth century, was even more adamant: “there is no scorn more profound, or on the whole more justifiable, than that of the men who make for the men who explain. Exposition, criticism, appreciation, is work for second-rate minds” (Hardy 1940, p. 1). Synthetic biologists could add this to their favorite Richard Feynman quote, “What I cannot create, I do not understand” (O’Malley 2009).

  30. In a way, Aristotelianism married biology (teleology) and psychology (intentionality) while “postponing” the separation between the physical and the biological that we have come to view as obvious (Schaxel 1919).

  31. Structuralism in contemporary philosophy of science is a way of representing theoretical, model, and data structures that aims to capture relevant relations—“horizontally,” between theories and models; and “vertically,” between models and data. Structuralists urge a shift in focus from object-oriented ontologies that “come and go through the history of science” to structures that “remain through theory change” (Steven French); see da Costa and French (2003), Ladyman et al. (2007), van Fraassen (2008).

  32. Russell (1917, p. 173) famously said: “To me it seems that … the reason why physics has ceased to look for causes is that, in fact, there are no such things. The law of causality, I believe, like much that passes muster among philosophers, is a relic of a bygone age, surviving, like the monarchy, only because it is erroneously supposed to do no harm.” Quine similarly thought of causation as an outdated, anthropomorphic notion. This view is still endorsed today by the physicist Anderson (2011, p. 270), whose alternative is “searching for the simplest schematic structure which will explain all the observations.” For Anderson, the epistemology of modern science is “basically Bayesian induction with a very great emphasis on its Ockham’s razor consequences.” Notice, however, that Bayesians have never come up with a convincing explanation of why simplicity would be relevant to credibility or truth (Churchland 1990).

  33. http://www.aaas.org/news/press_room/evolution/qanda.shtml.

  34. http://www.nap.edu/openbook.php?record_id=11876&page=11.

  35. On reliability, see, e.g., Wimsatt (2009), Ziman (1978). The revival of realism, which as a “metaphysical” issue was anathema to the logical empiricists, is nicely documented in Zammito (2004).

  36. The NAS gives an interesting twist to the meaning of the notion of fact: “In science, a ‘fact’ typically refers to an observation, measurement, or other form of evidence that can be expected to occur the same way under similar circumstances. However, scientists also use the term ‘fact’ to refer to a scientific explanation that has been tested and confirmed so many times that there is no longer a compelling reason to keep testing it or looking for additional examples. In that respect, the past and continuing occurrence of evolution is a scientific fact. Because the evidence supporting it is so strong, scientists no longer question whether biological evolution has occurred and is continuing to occur. Instead, they investigate the mechanisms of evolution, how rapidly evolution can take place, and related questions.”

  37. These rules were accounted for in quite different ways by inductivists, falsificationists, and Bayesians.

  38. But see Simon’s (1947) and Williams’ (1970) axiomatizations of Newtonian mechanics and evolutionary theory, respectively.

  39. On Giere’s (1988, p. 84) original account, for instance, models were “nonlinguistic, though abstract entities.” But as we have seen in the “Hopes Set on Biological Theory in an Evidence-Based World” section, the category has since been relaxed to include verbal, mathematical, visual, and physical models. If theories are defined solely in terms of models, but models are allowed to be purely verbal, there seems to be no good reason to subsume verbal theories under the semantic view.

  40. Meta-mathematics studies mathematics itself by means of formal (logical and mathematical) methods. It includes model theory, the study of (classes of) mathematical structures such as graphs or universes of set theory.

  41. A state space is a directed graph where each possible state of a dynamical system is represented by a vertex, and there is a directed edge from a to b if and only if f(a= b, where f defines the dynamical system.

  42. Giere’s (1988) account remains the most accessible and elegant introduction to the whole debate. Krohs (2004, pp. 165–171) has an accessible discussion of the structuralist account of Sneed and Stegmüller.

  43. Historians such as Israel (1996) and Morgan (2012) have argued that model-based science is, historically speaking, a relatively recent phenomenon. Godfrey-Smith (2006) compares John Maynard Smith and Eörs Szathmáry’s work on major transitions in evolution with Leo Buss’ work on the evolution of individuality, and argues that the former typifies a model-building approach whereas the latter doesn’t.

  44. “Far from following through the alleged similarities between scientific theories and those of meta-mathematics, Giere brings in as many interpretations of the term ‘model’ as suit his ends” (Downes 1992, p. 150). “One puzzling aspect of Griesemer’s account is his insistence that he is enriching the semantic view of theories. By the time we have admitted laboratory specimens and physical objects to the domain of models, the idea that theories are families of models becomes quite inclusive” (p. 150). Godfrey-Smith (2006) similarly rejects the semanticists’ claim that the sense of “model” that is applied is either the logician’s sense, or something relevantly close to it.

  45. “The effect of evolution on our sensory apparatus is known to have been particularly strong. Animals are capable of incredibly fine discriminations among objects in their environment without benefit of social conventions. And so—being fairly intelligent, talking primates—are we. … For at least some perceptual judgments, therefore, the fact of widespread agreement does not require a social explanation. The explanations of evolutionary biology and physiology are sufficient” (Giere 1988, p. 109). This is reminiscent of Quine (1969, p. 133): “A sense of comparative similarity … is one of man’s animal endowments. Insofar as it fits in with regularities of nature, so as to afford us reasonable success in our primitive inductions and expectations, it is presumably an evolutionary product of natural selection.” Quine employed this evolutionary argument to counter the appearance that science, in its reliance on subjunctive conditionals and singular causal statements, “is rotten to the core.”

  46. Whereas van Fraassen’s pragmatic, erotetic account of explanation (“an explanation is an answer to a why-question”) trivializes it (Kitcher), Giere (1988, p. 105) more radically suggests abandoning philosophical accounts of explanation altogether, and replacing them by accounts in terms of the standards of the cognitive sciences. An “empirical theory of explaining” would be judged by “the sorts of evidence relevant to theories of other higher level cognitive activities such as language comprehension and problem solving.”

  47. Both Downes (1992) and Godfrey-Smith (2006) hint at the necessity to carve out a space for a specifically philosophical account of theorizing as distinguished from cognitive-science approaches à la Nersessian (2003). I recognize this is an important issue, but cannot pursue it here.

References

  • Alexandrescu V (ed) (2009) Branching off: the early Moderns in quest for the unity of knowledge. Zeta Books, Bucharest

    Google Scholar 

  • Anderson PW (2011) More and different: notes from a thoughtful curmudgeon. World Scientific, Singapore

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Apostel L (1953) Logique et preuve. Methodos 5:279–321

    Google Scholar 

  • Apostel L (1960) Towards the formal study of models in the non-formal sciences. Synthese 12:125–161

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Baetu T (2012) Mechanistic constraints on evolutionary outcomes. Philos Sci 79:276–294

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bechtel W (2006) Discovering cell mechanisms: the creation of modern cell biology. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Berg N, Gigerenzer G (2010) As-if behavioral economics: neoclassical economics in disguise? Hist Econ Ideas 18:133–165

    Google Scholar 

  • Bonner JT (2013) Randomness in evolution. Princeton University Press, Princeton

    Google Scholar 

  • Brenner S (2010) Sequences and consequences. Philos Trans R Soc B 365:207–212

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bressler SL, Kelso JAS (2001) Cortical coordination dynamics and cognition. Trends Cogn Sci 5:26–36

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Callebaut W (1993) Taking the naturalistic turn, or how real philosophy of science is done. University of Chicago Press, Chicago

    Google Scholar 

  • Callebaut W (2005) Again, what the philosophy of biology is not. Acta Biotheor 53:93–122

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Callebaut W (2007) Simon’s silent revolution. Biol Theory 2:76–86

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Callebaut W (2010) Innovation from EvoDevo to culture. In: O’Brien MO, Shennan SJ (eds) Innovation in cultural systems: contributions from evolutionary anthropology. MIT Press, Cambridge, MA, pp 81–95

    Google Scholar 

  • Callebaut W (2011) Beyond generalized Darwinism. Biol Theory 6:338–365

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Callebaut W (2012) Scientific perspectivism: a philosopher of science’s response to the challenge of big data biology. Stud Hist Philos Biol Biomed Sci 43:69–80

    Google Scholar 

  • Campbell DT (1997) From evolutionary epistemology via selection theory to a sociology of scientific validity. Evol Cogn 3:5–38

    Google Scholar 

  • Cartwright N, Shomar T, Suárez M (1995) The tool box of science: tools for building of models with a superconductivity example. In: Herfel WE et al (eds) Theories and models in scientific processes. Rodopi, Amsterdam, pp 137–139

    Google Scholar 

  • Churchland PM (1990) On the nature of theories: a neurocomputational perspective. In: Savage CW (ed) Scientific theories. University of Minnesota Press, Minneapolis, pp 59–101

    Google Scholar 

  • Committee on Defining and Advancing the Conceptual Basis of Biological Sciences in the 21st Century (2007) The role of theory in advancing 21st century biology: catalyzing transformative research. National Academies Press, Washington, DC

    Google Scholar 

  • da Costa NCA, French S (2003) Science and partial truth: a unitary approach to models and scientific reasoning. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Danchin A (2002) The Delphic boat: what genomes tell us (Quayle A, trans). Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA. French orig. 1998

  • Daston L, Stolleis M (eds) (2008) Natural law and laws of nature in early Modern Europe. Ashgate, Farnham

    Google Scholar 

  • de Chadarevian S, Hopwood N (eds) (2004) Models: the third dimension of science. Stanford University Press, Stanford

    Google Scholar 

  • de Groot AD (1961) Methodologie: grondslagen van onderzoek en denken in de gedragswetenschappen. Mouton, ‘s Gravenhage

  • De Mey M (1992) The cognitive paradigm: cognitive science, a newly explored approach to the study of cognition applied in an analysis of science and scientific knowledge. University of Chicago Press, Chicago. Orig. 1982

  • de Regt H, Leonelli S, Eigner K (2009) Scientific understanding: philosophical perspectives. University of Pittsburgh Press, Pittsburgh

    Google Scholar 

  • Downes SM (1992) The importance of models in theorizing: a deflationary semantic view. In: Hull D et al (eds) PSA 1992, vol 1. Philosophy of Science Association, East Lansing, pp 142–153

    Google Scholar 

  • Ehrenberg R (1923) Theoretische Biologie vom Standpunkt der Irreversibilität des elementaren Lebensvorganges. Julius Springer, Berlin

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Freeman C (1993) The economics of hope: essays on technical change, economic growth, and the environment. Pinter, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Frigg R, Hartmann S (2012) Models in science. In: Zalta EN (ed) The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy, Fall. http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2012/entries/models-science/. Accessed 20 March 2013

  • Frisch DP (2010) Recent developments in sociobiology and the scientific method. Trends Ecol Evol 26:57–58

    Google Scholar 

  • Fry I (2012) Is science metaphysically neutral? Stud Hist Philos Biol Biomed Sci 43:665–673

    Google Scholar 

  • Fuller S (2009) Philosophy of science in an age of neo-Darwinian apologetics. Ludus Vitalis 17:247–257

    Google Scholar 

  • Giere RN (1988) Explaining science: a cognitive approach. University of Chicago Press, Chicago

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Giere RN (1999) Science without laws. University of Chicago Press, Chicago

    Google Scholar 

  • Giere RN (2006a) Scientific perspectivism. University of Chicago Press, Chicago

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Giere RN (2006b) Modest evolutionary naturalism. Biol Theory 1:52–60

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Giere RN (2006c) The role of agency in distributed cognitive systems. Philos Sci 75:710–719

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Giere RN (2009) Essay review: scientific representation and empiricist structuralism. [Review of Van Fraassen 2008.]. Philos Sci 76:101–111

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gigerenzer G, Todd PM (2012) Ecological rationality: the normative study of heuristics. Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp 487–497, 498–551 (references)

  • Glennan S (2002) Rethinking mechanistic explanation. Philos Sci 69:S342–S353

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Godfrey-Smith P (2006) The strategy of model-based science. Biol Philos 21:725–740

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gorelick R (2011) What is theory? Ideas Ecol Evol 4:1–10

    Google Scholar 

  • Griesemer JR (2004) Three-dimensional models in philosophical perspective. In: de Chadarevian S, Hopwood N (eds) Models. Stanford University Press, Stanford, pp 433–442

    Google Scholar 

  • Griesemer J (2011) Philosophy and tinkering. Biol Philos 26:269–279

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Griesemer JR, Wimsatt WC (1989) Picturing Weismannism: a case study of conceptual evolution. In: Ruse M (ed) What the philosophy of biology is: essays for David Hull. Kluwer, Dordrecht, pp 75–137

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Habermas J (1976) Zur Rekonstruktion des historischen Materialismus. Suhrkamp, Frankfurt

    Google Scholar 

  • Hackett EJ et al (eds) (2007) The handbook of science and technology studies, 3rd edn. MIT Press, Cambridge, MA

    Google Scholar 

  • Hallyn F (ed) (2000) Metaphor and analogy in science. Kluwer, Dordrecht

    Google Scholar 

  • Halvorson H (2012) What scientific theories could not be. Philos Sci 79:183–206

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hanahan D, Weinberg RA (2000) The hallmarks of cancer. Cell 100:57–70

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hardy GH (1940) A mathematician’s apology. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Holton G (1973) Thematic origins of scientific thought: Kepler to Einstein. Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA

    Google Scholar 

  • Hull DL (1988) Science as a process: an evolutionary account of the social and conceptual development of science. University of Chicago Press, Chicago

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Israel G (1996) La mathématisation du réel. Seuil, Paris

    Google Scholar 

  • Jasanoff S et al (eds) (1995) Handbook of science and technology studies, 2nd edn. SAGE, Thousand Oaks

    Google Scholar 

  • Jha SR (2002) Reconsidering Michael Polanyi’s philosophy. University of Pittsburgh Press, Pittsburgh

    Google Scholar 

  • Kammerer P (1915) Allgemeine Biologie. Deutsche Verlags-Anstalt, Stuttgart

    Google Scholar 

  • Kellert SH, Longino HE, Waters CK (2006) Introduction: the pluralist stance. In: Kellert SH et al (eds) Scientific pluralism. University of Minnesota Press, Minneapolis, pp vii–xxix

    Google Scholar 

  • Khalifa K (2012) Inaugurating understanding or repackaging explanation? Philos Sci 79:15–37

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kitcher P (1993) The advancement of science: science without legend, objectivity without illusions. Oxford University Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Kitcher P (2012) Preludes to pragmatism: toward a reconstruction of philosophy. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Kluckhohn C (1939) The place of theory in anthropological studies. Philos Sci 6:328–344

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Krakauer DC, Collins JP, Erwin D, Flack JC, Fontana W, Laubichler MD, Prohaska SJ, West GB, Stadler PF (2011) The challenges and scope of theoretical biology. J Theor Biol 276:269–276

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Krohs U (2004) Eine Theorie biologischer Theorien. Status und Gehalt von Funktionsaussagen und informationstheoretischen Modellen. Springer, Berlin

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Krohs U, Callebaut W (2007) Data without models merging with models without data. In: Boogerd FC et al (eds) Systems biology: philosophical foundations. Elsevier, Amsterdam, pp 181–213

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Kuhn TS (1970) The structure of scientific revolutions, 2nd edn. University of Chicago Press, Chicago

    Google Scholar 

  • Ladyman J, Ross D, Spurrett D, Collier J (2007) Every thing must go: metaphysics naturalized. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Laubichler MD, Müller GB (eds) (2007) Modeling biology: structures, behaviors, evolution. MIT Press, Cambridge, MA

    Google Scholar 

  • Lehrer J (2012) Kin and kind: a fight about the genetics of altruism. N Yorker, March 5

  • Leonelli S (2009) Understanding in biology: the impure nature of biological knowledge. In: de Regt HW et al (eds) Scientific understanding. University of Pittsburgh Press, Pittsburgh, pp 189–209

    Google Scholar 

  • Leonelli S (2012) Classificatory theory in data-intensive science: the case of open biomedical ontologies. Int Stud Philos Sci 26:47–65

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Leontief V (1971) Theoretical assumptions and nonobserved facts. Am Econ Rev 61:1–7

    Google Scholar 

  • Levins R (1966) The strategy of model building in population biology. Am Sci 54:421–431

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewontin RC (1970) The units of selection. Annu Rev Ecol Syst 1:1–18

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lewontin RC (1974) The genetic basis of evolutionary change. Columbia University Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewontin RC (2000) The triple helix: gene, organism, and environment. Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA

    Google Scholar 

  • Lloyd EA (1988) The structure and confirmation of evolutionary theory. Greenwood Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Machamer PK, Darden L, Craver C (2000) Thinking about mechanisms. Philos Sci 57:1–25

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Malafouris L, Renfrew C (eds) (2010) The cognitive life of things: recasting the boundaries of the mind. McDonald Institute for Archaeological Research, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Mayr E (1982) The growth of biological thought: diversity, evolution, and inheritance. Belknap Press of Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA

    Google Scholar 

  • McKinsey JCC, Sugar AC, Suppes P (1953) Axiomatic foundations of classical particle mechanics. J Ration Mech Anal 2:253–272

    Google Scholar 

  • McMullin E (1983) Values in science. PSA 1982 2:3–28

    Google Scholar 

  • Medawar PB, Medawar JS (1983) Aristotle to zoos: a philosophical dictionary of biology. Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA

    Google Scholar 

  • Meheus J (ed) (2002) Inconsistency in science. Kluwer, Dordrecht

    Google Scholar 

  • Menninger H, Gropp R (2008) Theory and funding for 21st century biology—maybe. Bioscience 58:198

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mitroff II (1984) The subjective side of science: philosophical inquiry into the psychology of the Apollo moon scientists. Elsevier, Amsterdam

    Google Scholar 

  • Morgan MS (2012) The world in the model: how economists work and think. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Morgan MS, Morrison M (eds) (1999) Models as mediators: perspectives on natural and social science. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Morrison M (2007) Where have all the theories gone? Philos Sci 74:195–228

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Morrison M, Morgan MS (1999) Introduction. In: Morgan MS, Morrison M (eds) Models as mediators. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, pp 1–9

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Musil R (1953–1954) The man without qualities, vol I, 1953; vol II, 1954. Coward-McCann, New York. German orig. 1930–1933

  • Nagel E (1961) The structure of science: problems in the logic of scientific explanation. Routledge and Kegan Paul, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Nelson RR (2008) Bounded rationality, cognitive maps, and trial and error learning. J Econ Behav Organ 67:78–89

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nelson RR, Winter SG (1982) An evolutionary theory of scientific change. Belknap Press of Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA

    Google Scholar 

  • Nersessian NJ (1984) Faraday to Einstein: constructing meaning in scientific theories. Kluwer, Dordrecht

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Nersessian NJ (2003) Kuhn, conceptual change, and cognitive science. In: Nickles T (ed) Thomas Kuhn. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, pp 178–211

    Google Scholar 

  • Nickles T (ed) (2003a) Thomas Kuhn. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Nickles T (2003b) Normal science: from logic to case-based and model-based reasoning. In: Nickles T (ed) Thomas Kuhn. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, pp 142–177

    Google Scholar 

  • Nickles T (2006) Problem of demarcation. In: Sarkar S, Pfeifer J (eds) The philosophy of science: an encyclopedia, vol 1. Routledge, New York, pp 188–197

    Google Scholar 

  • Olson R (1971) Science as metaphor: the historical role of scientific theories in forming Western culture. Wadsworth, Belmont, CA

  • O’Malley MA (2009) Making knowledge in synthetic biology: design meets kludge. Biol Theory 4:378–389

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • O’Malley MA, Elliott KC, Burian RM (2010) From genetic to genomic regulation: iterativity in microRNA research. Stud Hist Philos Biol Biomed Sci 41:407–417

    Google Scholar 

  • Pardo-Guerra JP (2012) Financial automation, past, present, and future. In: Knorr Cetina K, Preda A (eds) The Oxford handbook of the sociology of finance. Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp 567–586

    Google Scholar 

  • Paton R (1992) Towards a metaphorical biology. Biol Philos 7:279–294

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Paton R (1997) Glue, verb and text metaphors in biology. Acta Biotheor 45:1–15

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Preston A (2007) Analytic philosophy: the history of an illusion. Continuum, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Preston B (2013) A philosophy of material culture: action, function, and mind. Routledge, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Priest G (1987) In contradiction: a study of the transconsistent. Nijhoff, Dordrecht

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Quine WV (1969) Ontological relativity and other essays. Columbia University Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Rádl E (1909) Geschichte der biologischen Theorien. II. Teil. Geschichte der Entwicklungstheorien in der Biologie des XIX. Jahrhunderts. Wilhelm Engelmann, Leipzig

    Google Scholar 

  • Rádl E (1913) Geschichte der biologischen Theorien in der Neuzeit. I. Teil. Zweite gänzlich umgearbeitete Auflage. Wilhelm Engelmann, Leipzig. Orig. 1905

  • Rádl E (1930) The history of biological ideas (Hatfield EJ, trans). Oxford University Press, Oxford; Humphrey Milford, London. Abridged version of 1909 Czech Orig.

  • Reinke J (1911) Einleitung in die theoretische Biologie. Zweite umgearbeitete Auflage. Gebrüder Patel, Berlin. Orig. 1901

  • Rouse J (2002) How scientific practices matter: reclaiming philosophical naturalism. University of Chicago Press, Chicago

    Google Scholar 

  • Rowan J (1981) The subjective side of science by Ian Mitroff: an appreciation. In: Reason P, Rowan J (eds) Human inquiry: a sourcebook of new paradigm research. Wiley, Chichester, pp 37–41

    Google Scholar 

  • Rueger A (2005) Perspectival models and theory unification. Br J Philos Sci 56:579–594

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Russell B (1917) Mysticism and logic. Allen and Unwin, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Salmon WC (1989) Four decades of scientific explanation. University of Minnesota Press, Minneapolis

    Google Scholar 

  • Schaxel J (1919) Grundzüge der Theorienbildung in der Biologie. Gustav Fischer, Jena

    Google Scholar 

  • Shadish WR, Cook TD, Campbell DT (2002) Quasi-experimental designs for generalized causal inference. Houghton Mifflin, Boston

    Google Scholar 

  • Simon HA (1947) The axioms of Newtonian mechanics. Philos Mag Ser 7 38:888–905

    Google Scholar 

  • Simon HA (1997) An empirically based microeconomics. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Spiegel-Rösing I et al (eds) (1977) Science, technology and society: a cross-disciplinary perspective. SAGE, Beverly Hills

    Google Scholar 

  • Stanley J (2011) Know how. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Suppe F (ed) (1977) The structure of scientific theories. University of Illinois Press, Urbana

    Google Scholar 

  • Suppes P (1967) What is a scientific theory? In: Morgenbesser S (ed) Philosophy of science today. Basic Books, New York, pp 55–67

    Google Scholar 

  • Swann WFG (1940) The significance of scientific theories. Philos Sci 7:273–287

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Teller P (2001) Twilight of the perfect model. Erkenntnis 55:393–415

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Thompson P (1989) The structure of biological theories. State University of New York Press, Albany

    Google Scholar 

  • Trout JD (2002) Scientific explanation and the sense of understanding. Philos Sci 69:212–233

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • van Fraassen BC (2008) Scientific representation: paradoxes of perspective. Clarendon, Oxford

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Van Valen L (1973) A new evolutionary law. Evol Theory 1:1–30

    Google Scholar 

  • von Bertalanffy L (1932) Theoretische Biologie. Erster Band: Allgemeine Theorie, Physikochemie, Aufbau und Entwicklung des Organismus. Borntraeger, Berlin-Zehlendorf

  • von Bertalanffy L (1942) Theoretische Biologie. Zweiter Band: Stoffwechsel, Wachstum. Borntraeger, Berlin-Zehlendorf

    Google Scholar 

  • Wagensberg J (2006) The total museum through conversation between architects and museologists. Sacyr, Barcelona

    Google Scholar 

  • Wartofsky MW (1967) Metaphysics as heuristic for science. In: Cohen RS, Wartofsky MW (eds) In memory of Norwood Hanson. Reidel, Dordrecht, pp 164–170

    Google Scholar 

  • Waters KC (2011) Okasha’s unintended argument for toolbox theorizing. Philos Phenomenol Res 82:232–240

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Weinberg RA (2010) Point: hypotheses first. Nature 464:678

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Weisberg M (2007) Who is a modeler? Br J Philos Sci 58:207–233

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Whitehead AN (1933) Adventures of ideas. Macmillan, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Williams M (1970) Deducing the consequences of evolution: a mathematical model. J Theor Biol 29:343–385

    Google Scholar 

  • Wimsatt WC (2007) Re-engineering philosophy for limited beings: piecewise approximations to reality. Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA

    Google Scholar 

  • Woese CR (2004) A new biology for a new century. Microbiol Mol Biol Rev 68:173–186

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wray KB (2011) Kuhn’s evolutionary social epistemology. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Zammito JH (2004) A nice derangement of epistemes: post-positivism in the study of science from Quine to Latour. University of Chicago Press, Chicago

    Google Scholar 

  • Ziman J (1978) Reliable knowledge. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

Warm thanks to my co-organizers, Massimo Pigliucci and Kim Sterelny; to the other participants in the 25th Altenberg Workshop in Theoretical Biology on “The Meaning of ‘Theory’ in Biology”; to KLI fellows, in particular Tudor Baetu, Rachael Brown, and Stuart Glennan; and in particular to Isabella Sarto-Jackson for her real biologist’s questioning. Error clause as usual. I gratefully acknowledge the financial support of the KLI Board, which made this event possible. I trust that my friend Ulrich Krohs will forgive me for borrowing the title of his (2004) book and giving it a twist in my own title. According to Suppes (1967, p. 57), “most philosophers find it easier to talk about theories than about models of theories.” Considering the difficult gestation of this article, I am no longer sure I can agree. I dedicate it, imperfect as it is, to the memory of Leo Apostel (1925–1995), my mentor at the University of Ghent, who was one of the first to take seriously the multiple roles models play in scientific practice (Apostel 1960; Frigg and Hartmann 2012). Apostel (1953) also paved the way for the pragmatic turn to theorizing that epitomized our workshop; after reading this article, Jean Piaget invited him to Geneva for what was to become a lifelong collaboration.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Werner Callebaut.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Callebaut, W. Naturalizing Theorizing: Beyond a Theory of Biological Theories. Biol Theory 7, 413–429 (2013). https://doi.org/10.1007/s13752-013-0122-2

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s13752-013-0122-2

Keywords

Navigation