Skip to main content

Reference in Context

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Exploring Contextualism and Performativity

Part of the book series: Perspectives in Pragmatics, Philosophy & Psychology ((PEPRPHPS,volume 30))

  • 131 Accesses

Abstract

In this paper, I offer some considerations on the contextual dimension of reference and, then, I expatiate on the possibility that referential NPs refer to objects but at the same time they are linked with a conceptual presupposition, that explains why reference only does not work and is not an efficient way to represent certain NPs. I compare this issue of a conceptual presuppositions with the considerations on pragmatic or conversational presuppositions in papers by Capone or Macagno and Capone.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 109.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 139.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 139.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    I am deepening some consequences of the public discussion by Donald Davidson and P.F. Strawson on the difference between objects and events. https://www.youtube.com/watch?v=hE71QAOYav4&t=2692s.

  2. 2.

    “In Frege’s account, a mind is directed at a particular by virtue of grasping a thought that has as a constituent a sense of the appropriate kind, determining that object as its associated Bedeutung” (McDowell 1998, p. 260).

  3. 3.

    Accommodation is a dynamic process in which we start with asymmetric presuppositions and the asymmetry is bridged by the understanding that the hearer accepts a proposition that the speaker is presupposing, because, if he (the latter) did not accept it, he would have to say so. Since he says nothing, and, in particular, he does not object to adding that proposition to the common ground, it is presumed that he has accepted the proposition in question.

  4. 4.

    The most obvious answer that comes to mind, is that something underspecified for semantics, as a pronominal, should be used to fix reference through contextual clues, and a relative clause of the non-restrictive type, that expresses a presupposition, should be used in combination. Non-restrictive relative clauses are known to be associated with presuppositions. The referential restrictions presumably would have to derive from contextual considerations, rather than from composition with non-restrictive relative clauses. There may be considerable difficulties with this proposal. It is not only the syntax that bothers me, but the syntax of logical form. How should we analyse ‘That man’? Presumably we need something like “He, who is a man and belongs to the non-empty set of men, and I am demonstrating through finger-pointing”. In this way we obtain for free the condition ‘There is an x, x is a man and x is unique in context C’, which is a presupposition of the presupposition.

  5. 5.

    Garcìa-Carpintero (2000, p. 114) also thinks that modes of presentation are essential parts of justification acts.

References

  • Asher, N. (2000). Events, facts, propositions and evolutive anaphora. In J. Higginbotham, F. Pianesi, & A. C. Varzi (Eds.), Speaking of events. OUP.

    Google Scholar 

  • Capone, A. (2010). Between Scylla and Carybdis. The semantics and pragmatics of attitudes ‘de se’. Intercultural Pragmatics, 7(3), 471–503.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Capone, A. (2013a). Consequences of the pragmatics of ‘de se’. In N. Feit & A. Capone (Eds.), Attitudes de se. Linguistics, epistemology and metaphysics (pp. 209–244). CSLI (Chicago University Press).

    Google Scholar 

  • Capone, A. (2013b). The pragmatics of quotation, explicatures and modularity of mind. Pragmatics & Society, 4(3), 259–284.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Capone, A. (2016). The pragmatics of indirect reports. In Socio-philosophical considerations. Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Capone, A. (2018a). Pragmemes (again). Lingua, 209, 88–104.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Capone, A. (2018b). Embedding explicatures in implicit indirect reports: Simple sentences and substitution failure cases. In A. Capone, M. Carapezza, & F. L. Piparo (Eds.), Further advances in pragmatics and philosophy (From theory to practice) (Vol. 1, pp. 97–137).

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Capone, A. (2019). Pragmatics and philosophy. In Ramifications and connections. Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Capone, A. (2020). Presuppositions as pragmemes: The case of exemplification acts. Intercultural Pragmatics, 17(1), 53–75.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Castañeda, H.-N. (1966). He’: A study in the logic of self-consciousness. Ratio, 8, 136–157.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chomsky, N. (2013a). What kind of creatures are we? Lecture 1. What is language? Journal of Philosophy, CX(12), 645–700.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chomsky, N. (2013b). What can we understand? Journal of Philosophy, 110(12), 663–684.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dascal, M. (2003). Interpretation and understanding. John Benjamins.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Donnellan, K. (1966). Reference and definite descriptions. The Philosophical Review, 75(3), 281–304.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Evans, G. (1982). The varieties of reference. Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Garcìa-Carpintero, M. (2000). A presuppositional account of reference fixing. Journal of Philosophy, XCVII/3, 109–147.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Goldberg, S. (2015). Assertion. OUP.

    Google Scholar 

  • Higginbotham, J. (2000). On events in linguistic semantics. In J. Higginbotham, F. Pianesi, & A. Varzi (Eds.), Speaking of events. OUP.

    Google Scholar 

  • Higginbotham, J. (2003). Remembering, imagining and the first person. In A. Barber (Ed.), Epistemology of language (pp. 496–533). OUP.

    Google Scholar 

  • Higginbotham, J. (n.d.). In F. Pianesi & A. Varzi (Eds.), Speaking of events. OUP.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jaszczolt, K. M. (2005). Default semantics. In Foundations of a compositional theory of acts of communication. OUP.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jaszczolt, K. M. (2018). Meaning in linguistic interaction. In Semantics, metasemantics and philosophy of language. OUP.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kecskes, I. (2019). English as lingua franca. In The pragmatic perspective. CUP.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kecskes, I. (Forthcoming). The socio-cognitive approach to communication and pragmatics. Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Levinson, S. (2000). Presumptive meanings. The MIT Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • McDowell, J. (1998). Meaning, knowledge and reality. Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mey, J. L. (2001). Pragmatics. Blackwell/Wiley.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nunberg, G. (1995). Transfers of meaning. Journal of Semantics, 12, 109–132.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Peacocke, C. (2014). The mirror of the world. OUP.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Perry, J. (1979). The problem of the essential indexical. Nôus, 13(1), 3–21.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pietroski, P. (2005). Meaning before truth. In Preyer & Peter (Eds.), Contextualism in philosophy (pp. 253–300). OUP.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sbisà, M. (1989). Linguaggio, ragione, interazione. Il Mulino.

    Google Scholar 

  • Searle, J. (1969). Speech acts. In An essay in the philosophy of language. CUP.

    Google Scholar 

  • Searle, J. R. (1985). Expression and meaning. In Studies in the theory of speech acts. CUP.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stainton, R. J. (2006). Words and thoughts. In Sub-sentences, ellipsis, and the philosophy of language. OUP.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stalnaker, R. (1977). Presuppositions. Journal of Philosophical Logic, 2, 447–457.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stalnaker, R. (1978). Assertion. In P. Cole (Ed.), Pragmatics: Syntax and pragmatics 9 (pp. 315–332). Academic.

    Google Scholar 

  • Strawson, P. F. (1997). Entity and identity and other essays. OUP.

    Google Scholar 

  • Strawson Peter, F. (1950). On referring. Mind, 59(235), 320–334.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Strawson, P. F. (1954). Critical notice. Philosophical investigations, by Ludwig Wittgenstein. Mind, 63(249), 70–99.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Strawson, P. F. (1964). Intention and convention in speech acts. The philosophical Review, 73(4), 439–460.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wittgenstein, L. (1953). Philosophical investigations. Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Yablo, S. (2014). Aboutness. Princeton.

    Book  Google Scholar 

Links

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Alessandro Capone .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2023 The Author(s), under exclusive license to Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Capone, A. (2023). Reference in Context. In: Capone, A., Penna, A. (eds) Exploring Contextualism and Performativity. Perspectives in Pragmatics, Philosophy & Psychology, vol 30. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-031-12543-0_1

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics