Skip to main content
Log in

Naturalising Ethics: The Implications of Darwinism for the Study of Moral Philosophy

  • Published:
Science & Education Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

The nature of moral values has occupied philosophers and educationalists for centuries and a variety of claims have been made about their origin and status. One tradition suggests they may be thoughts in the mind of God; another that they are eternal truths to be reached by rational reflection (much like the truths of mathematics) or alternatively through intuition; another that they are social conventions; and another (from the logical positivists) that they are not verifiable facts but simply the expression of emotional likes and dislikes. Standard introductory texts (e.g., Bowie 2004; Vardy and Grosch 1999) on the subject of ethics rarely mention Darwin or Darwinism (Mepham 2005 is a useful exception) possibly mindful of the fact that the relationship of evolutionary biology to moral questions has had a troublesome history. The effect of this has been that whole generations of moral philosophers have given the biological sciences a wide berth and consequently often remain poorly informed about recent advances in evolutionary thought and the neurosciences. On the other hand, scientists have developed interesting models of the evolution of the moral sentiments and are using new imaging techniques to explore the centres of the brain associated with emotion and motivation, but many have been fearful of committing the naturalistic fallacy and so have steered clear of extrapolating their findings to ethical questions. No one after all wants to be seen to be committing an elementary logical blunder. But in the last 20 years, evolutionary biologists have regained the confidence to explore the implications of evolution for the study of ethics (de Waal 1996; Wilson 1998; Wright 1994; Greene 2003). This paper is designed to encourage those entrusted with the teaching of ethics to be open to the potential of Darwinism as a source of ideas on the origins and status of ethical thought and behaviour. It is also hoped that it will illustrate for science educators the enormous explanatory power inherent in Darwinian thought.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Fig. 1
Fig. 2
Fig. 3
Fig. 4
Fig. 5
Fig. 6
Fig. 7

Similar content being viewed by others

References

  • Alexander, R. D. (1987). The biology of moral systems. New York: Aldine de Gruter.

    Google Scholar 

  • Allchin, D. (1999). Teaching Darwin seriously: Addressing evolution and ethics. American Biology Teacher, 61, 350–355.

    Google Scholar 

  • Allchin, D. (2007). Social un-darwinism. American Biology Teacher, 69, 113–115.

    Google Scholar 

  • Arnhart, L. (2005). Incest taboo as Darwinian natural right. In A. P. Wolf & W. H. Durham (Eds.), Inbreeding, Incest and the Incest taboo. Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Axelrod, R., & Hamilton, W. D. (1981). The evolution of co-operation. Science, 211, 1390–1396.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Barash, D. (1982). Sociobiology and behaviour. New York: Elsevier.

    Google Scholar 

  • Barash, D. (2003). The survival game. New York: Times Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bevc, I., & Silverman, I. (1993). Early proximity and intimacy between siblings and incestuous behaviour: A test of the Westermarck hypothesis. Ethology and Sociobiology, 14, 171–181.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bittles, A. H. (1995). The influence of consanguineous marriage on reproductive behaviour in India and Pakistan. In C. G. N. Mascie-Taylor & A. J. Boyce (Eds.), Mating patterns. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bittles, A. H. (2004). Genetic aspects of inbreeding and incest. In A. P. Wolf & W. H. Durham (Eds.), Inbreeding, incest and the incest taboo. Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bittles, A. H., & Makov, U. (1988). Inbreeding in human populations: Assessment of the costs. In C. G. N. Mascie-Taylor & A. J. Boyce (Eds.), Mating patterns. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bowie, R. (2004). Ethical studies. Cheltenham: Nelson Thornes.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brem, S. K., Ranney, M., & Schindel, J. (2003). Perceived consequences of evolution: College students perceive negative personal and social impact in evolutionary theory. Science Education, 87, 181–206.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cartwright, J. (2008). Evolution and human behaviour. London: Palgrave.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chambers, R. (1844). Vestiges of the natural history of creation (2nd ed.). London: John Churchill.

    Google Scholar 

  • Committee on Culture, Science and Education. (2007). ‘The danger of creationism in education’, Council of Europe Doc. 11065.

  • Cronin, H. (1991). The ant and the peacock. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Curry, O. (2005). Morality as natural history. Ph.D. Thesis, London School of Economics (LSE), London.

  • Darwin, C. (1860). Letter to Charles Lyell, 25/2/1860. In F. Burkhardt & S. Smith (Eds.), The correspondence of Charles Darwin. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. 1991.

    Google Scholar 

  • Darwin, C. (1906). The descent of man and selection in relation to sex (2nd ed.). London: John Murray.

    Google Scholar 

  • Darwin, F. (Ed.). (1887). The life and letters of Charles Darwin. London: John Murray.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dawkins, R. (1976). The selfish gene. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • de Waal, F. (1996). Good natured: The origins of right and wrong in humans and other animals. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Delaney, T. (2009). Social spencerism. Philosophy Now, 71, 20–21.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dennett, D. (1995). Darwin’s dangerous idea. London: Allen Lane.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ekman, P. (1973). Cross cultural studies of facial expressions. In P. Ekman (Ed.), Darwin and facial expression. London: Academic Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fessler, D. M. T., & Navarrete, C. D. (2004). Third-party attitudes towards sibling incest. Evidence for Westermarck’s hypotheses. Evolution and Human Behaviour, 25, 277–294.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gallese, V., Fadiga, L., et al. (1996). Action recognition in the premotor cortex. Brain, 119, 593–609.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Greene, J. (2003). From neural ‘is’ to moral ‘ought’: What are the moral implications of neuroscientific moral psychology? Nature Reviews Neuroscience, 4, 846–849.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Greene, J. D. (2007). The secret joke of Kant’s soul. In W. Sinnott-Armstrong (Ed.), Moral psychology, Vol. 3: The neuroscience of morality: Emotion, disease, and development. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gwynne, D. T., & Simmons, L. W. (1990). Experimental reversal of courtship roles in an insect. Nature, 346, 172–174.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hamilton, W. D. (1964). The genetical evolution of social behaviour. Journal of Theoretical Biology, 7, 1–16.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hardin, G. (1968). The tragedy of the commons. Science, 162, 1243–1248.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hare, R. D. (1993). Without conscience: The disturbing world of the pyschopaths among us. New York: Simon and Schuster.

    Google Scholar 

  • Harpending, H., & Sobus, J. (1987). Sociopathy as an adaptation. Ethology and Sociobiology, 8, 63–72.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Huxley, T. H. (1894). Evolution and ethics. London: Macmillan and Co.

    Google Scholar 

  • Huxley, L. (1900). Life and letters of T H Huxley 2 vols. New York: Appleton.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kitcher, P. (1985). Vaulting ambition. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lalumiere, M. L., & Seto, M. C. (1998). What’s wrong with psychopaths? Psychiatry Rounds, 2, 6.

    Google Scholar 

  • Larson, E. J. (1997). Summer for the gods: The scopes trial and America’s continuing debate over science and religion. New York: Basic Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lieberman, D., Tooby, J., et al. (2003). Does morality have a biological basis? An empirical test of the factors governing moral sentiments relating to incest. Proceedings of the Royal Society of London. Series B, 270, 819–826.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mealey, L. (1997). The sociobiology of sociopathy: An integrated evolutionary model. In S. Baron-Cohen (Ed.), The maladapted mind. Hove: Psychology Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mepham, B. (2005). Bioethics. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nowak, M., & Sigmund, K. (1998). Evolution of indirect reciprocity by image scoring. Nature, 393, 573–576.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • O’Neill, P., & Petrinovich, L. (1998). A preliminary cross-cultural study of moral intuitions. Evolution and Human Behaviour, 19(6), 349–367.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Oldroyd, D. R. (1980). Darwinian impacts: An introduction to the Darwinian revolution. Buckingham: Open University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pearce, D., Markandya, A., & Barbier, E. B. (1989). Blueprint for a green economy. London: Earthscan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pedersen, F. A. (1991). Secular trends in human sex ratios: Their influence on individual and family behaviour. Human Nature, 2, 271–291.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Petrinovich, L., O’Neill, P., et al. (1993). An empirical study of moral intuitions: Towards an evolutionary ethics. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 64, 467–478.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pusey, A. (2004). Inbreeding avoidance in primates. In A. P. Wolf & W. H. Durham (Eds.), Inbreeding, incest and the incest taboo. Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rachels, J. (1990). Created from animals: The moral implications of Darwinism. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Richards, R. J. (1987). Darwin and the emergence of evolutionary theories of mind and behaviour. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Richards, J. R. (2000). Human nature after Darwin. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ridley, M. (1993). The red queen. London: Viking.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ridley, M. (1996). The origins of virtue. London: Viking (Penguin Group).

    Google Scholar 

  • Rizzolatti, G., Fogassi, L., et al. (2006). Mirrors in the mind. Scientific American, 295(5), 30–37.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Roes, F. L., & Raymond, M. (2003). Belief in moralising gods. Evolution and Human behaviour, 24(2), 126–135.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rutledge, M. L., & Sadler, K. C. (2007). Reliability of the measure of acceptance of the Theory of Evolution (MATE) instrument with University students. The American Biology Teacher, 69, 332–335.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schmitt, D. (2005). Universal sex differences in the desire for sexual variety: Tests from 52 nations, 6 continents and 13 islands. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 85(1), 85–104.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schneider, M. A., & Hendrix, L. (2000). Olfactory sexual inhibition and the Westermarck effect. Human Nature, 11(1), 65–91.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sherper, J. (1971). Mate selection among second generation kibbutz adolescents and adults: Incest avoidance and negative imprinting. Archives of Sexual Behaviour, 1(4), 293–307.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Simpson, J. A., & Gangestad, S. W. (1991). Individual differences in sociosexuality: Evidence for convergent and discriminant validity. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 60, 870–883.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Singer, P. (1981). The expanding circle: Ethics and sociobiology. New York: Farrar Straus & Giroux.

    Google Scholar 

  • Singer, P. (1998). Evolutionary workers’ party, The Times Higher Educational Supplement, 15 May, pp. 15–17.

  • Slevin, P. (2005). Battle on teaching evolution sharpens, Washington Post, p. A01.

  • Spain, D. H. (1991). Muddled theory and misinterpreted data. Behavioural and Brian Sciences, 14, 278–279.

    Google Scholar 

  • Trivers, R. (1985). Social evolution. California: Benjamin Cummings.

    Google Scholar 

  • Vardy, P., & Grosch, P. (1999). The puzzle of ethics. London: Harper Collins.

    Google Scholar 

  • Walter, A. (2006). The anti-naturalistic fallacy: Evolutionary moral psychology and the insistence of brute facts. Evolutionary Psychology, 4, 33–48.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wilson, E. O. (1998). Consilience. New York: Knopf.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wolf, A. P. (1993). Westermarck redivivus. Annual Review of Anthropology, 22, 157–175.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wright, R. (1994). The moral animal. London: Little, Brown and Co.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to John Cartwright.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Cartwright, J. Naturalising Ethics: The Implications of Darwinism for the Study of Moral Philosophy. Sci & Educ 19, 407–443 (2010). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11191-009-9205-7

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11191-009-9205-7

Keywords

Navigation