1 Introduction

The topic of this paper is a particular kind of cognitive performance—guessing. As Sosa (2015) sees it, guessing is like judging, but not quite. Both guessing and judging have an alethic aim. When we guess, as well as when we judge, we aim to get it right. But judgment, on Sosa’s view, does not aim merely to get it right. Judgment has a further epistemic aim, which is to get it right aptly. And getting it right aptly involves competent risk assessment.

Competent risk assessment—and not just hitting the relevant target any old way—is obviously important when engaged in sports, such as basketball. Suppose you shoot from far beyond your threshold of reliable competence—by chucking the ball toward the basket from the half court line. This (assuming the shot clock is not expiring) is very poor shot selection in the context of a basketball game. Your coach and teammates will rightly berate you for taking such a foolish shot, even if it happens to go in. Things are very similar in the cognitive arena: even if a wild guess turns out to be right by happenstance—and even though (like the shot taken from half court) you aimed by guessing to get it right, something is lacking. A correct but wild guess (like the shot from half court that lands in the basket) is not apt, which is to say, its accuracy does not manifest the shooter’s competence to make the shot reliably enough.Footnote 1

Of course, half-court shots in basketball games are very rarely ever taken. Likewise, in inquiring, we very rarely—unless practically forcedFootnote 2—aim to get it right by means of a wild guess.Footnote 3 However, compare shooting from half-court (beyond one’s threshold for reliability) with shooting just barely within one’s threshold for reliability, though in a circumstance where you can’t tell that you are in fact within this threshold. This case is clearly different from the case where you shot from half-court. Your shot in this case is apt, accurate because adroit. Yet, there is still a kind of credit-reducing luck which taints the assessment of the performance. Put simply, for all you knew, when you shot, you were outside your threshold of reliability. You just happened to be within this threshold. More carefully: your performance was first-order safe, but not second-order safe.Footnote 4 You are just reliable enough from that distance that not too easily would you fail to make your shot from there. But because you are unaware of where this threshold lies, you too easily could have shot inaptly, from just beyond your threshold of sufficient reliability.

Just as a basketball shot, under these circumstances, is not fully apt, neither is what Sosa takes to be the cognitive analogue to such a basketball shot: a guess under conditions under which you are just above the threshold for sufficient reliability, but aren’t aware of this. Such a guess (unlike a wild guess) would be first-order safe. But it would not be second-order safe because, unaware of where the threshold lies, you too easily could have guessed inaptly. Such a guess would be apt, but not fully apt; it would aspire to animal, but not reflective, knowledge.Footnote 5

The foregoing captures only in very broad brush strokes Sosa’s thinking about guessing, and how guessing relates to other notions within his virtue epistemology. He has many more illuminating things to say. In fact, his remarks on the topic of guessing (and its analogues, in the case of practical performances) crop up at various places throughout Judgment and Agency. In particular, what Sosa says about guessing plays an important and focused role in his explication in Chapter 3 of the concept—central to Judgment and Agency—of a fully apt performance. This distinguishes guessing as important to Sosa’s wider project in the book, given that he applies the concept of a fully apt performance in his account of the nature and normativity of human judgment—the latter being his primary aim.

In this paper, I offer a focused critique of Sosa’s discussion of guessing, with particular attention paid to the role which guessing plays in Sosa’s dialectical project in Chapter 3, and to a lesser extent Chapters 6 and 8 of Judgment and Agency. In response to the objections raised, I offer an alternative way of thinking about guessing which avoids these objections and yet which remains compatible with Sosa’s wider virtue epistemological framework.

Here is the plan. Section 2 details Sosa’s account of guessing, taking as a starting point his EYE EXAM case, which is an important reference point in Chapter 3. Section 3 introduces the notion of performative defeat and highlights, with reference to performative defeaters, some structural differences between EYE EXAM and other cases Sosa presents as on a performative par with EYE EXAM. Section 4 draws from the Jamesian insight that is that the aim of possessing the truth is best understood as a mixture of two competing aims—truly representing and not misrepresenting—to suggest that guesses, including reliable ones, generate defeaters in a way that (contra Sosa) disqualifies them from knowledge, animal or otherwise. Section 5 discusses the approach to guessing sketched thus far in the wider context of unreliable achievements, and distinguishes various species of guesses in connection with what are presented as practical performative analogues.

2 Sosa on guessing

Sosa (2015) gives the following example:

EYE EXAM: When I go for my exam, I am asked to read the lines of a chart with letters that shrink line by line from a huge single letter at the top, to those barely visible at the bottom. At some point I start to lose confidence that I am getting the letters right, but I keep going until the technician tells me to stop and then records some result. At that point there are many cases where I am quite unsure as to whether it is an “E” or an “F”, say, or a “P” rather than an “F”, etc. Suppose, however, it turns out that (unbeknownst to me) I am in fact unfailingly right year after year at a line where I am thus unsure. At that point I am in effect “guessing.” I do affirm, to myself in private and to the technician in public, and I do so in the endeavor to get it right. That is after all what the test requires: that I try to answer correctly. And we can surely stipulate that I thereby manifest a competence, one I do not recognize as reliable enough. This latter is why I resort to guessing, when I continue to affirm as I undergo the test. Unbeknownst to me, however, my affirmations turn out to be surprisingly reliable (2015, pp. 74–5).

EYE EXAM—specifically, the circumstance where one reliably reads the last line, while unaware that one is reliable in doing so—features what we can call reliable guessing. It’s reliable because the examinee is unfailingly right in affirming the final line in the eye test. But, as Sosa tells us, it’s nonetheless guessing; you don’t regard your competence as reliable enough in the case of reading the last line, even though you are.

Here are three central claims Sosa makes about reliable guessing. Firstly, reliable guessing—like guessing more generally—has a (merely) alethic aim; in EYE EXAM, the agent aims by guessing to get it right, but not to get it right aptly.Footnote 6

Second, the reliable guesser’s belief is a kind of subcredal animal knowledge (2005, p. 76): his guesses are not right by luck (Ibid., p. 76); rather, the guesser affirms in a way that manifests a reliable first-order visual-perceptual competence which is however not recognised by the guesser as reliable enough.Footnote 7

Thirdly, what distinguishes the knowledge the examinee enjoys of the large top-row letters from the kind of (subcredal) animal knowledge she enjoys of the small, bottom row in virtue of, in the latter case, reliably guessing? Sosa’s answer here is nuanced. He first considers, and then, rejects, that the epistemically relevant difference between these two cases of affirming with the aim of getting it right is just that the examinee affirms with comparatively more confidence the higher-row letters than the bottom-row letters (even though that is of course the case).Footnote 8

Rather, Sosa thinks, the difference in epistemic status is to be explained specifically in terms of a difference in reflective, or second-order, competence in the two cases. His remarks on this point are illuminating:

Compare someone who gains not just confidence but also confirmation that he remains reliably right even when the letters shrink. This is perhaps the gain that raises him to a higher epistemic level. Now he might attain the knowledge requiring judgment, not just a guess. His knowledge would then comprise not only more confidence but also the proper meta-assurance that, even for those very small letters, his level of competence limits epistemic risk within proper bounds. Absent such additional confirmation, the vision-test subject lacks well-founded confidence on the second order that his first-order affirmations are more than sheer guesses. Even if by hypothesis his guesses are not right just by luck, he cannot be sure of that, not competently. By contrast, when the letters near the top are clearly and distinctly discernible, we do not just guess, which comports with our knowledge that we can identify those letters for what they are, that our affirmations at those rows would be apt (2015, p. 76).

In short, Sosa’s reliable guesser lacks a certain kind of meta-assurance—viz., assurance that his level of (first-order) competence limits epistemic risk within proper bounds. The reliable guesser ex hypothesi can’t tell whether his guesses would be, if right, right by luck.

But note that the second-order assurance the reliable guesser lacks (though which is not lacked when she affirms the larger letters on the top row) would not be secured simply by having more confidence that her first order affirmations are reliable enough.Footnote 9 Such confidence could be incompetently, or unfoundedly, gained, as would be the case were the reliable guesser to believe, on the basis of a wish, that her first-order affirmations were reliable, even when they were reliable.Footnote 10 Rather, what the reliable guesser lacks is knowledge that she can identify those letters for what they are, and so that her affirmations at this row would be apt. For all the reliable guesser can knows, they would not be.

3 Performative defeaters

Sosa’s reliable guesser in EYE EXAM is supposed to be on a kind of ‘performative par’ with two other characters from Chapter 3:

  1. (i)

    the basketball shooter (noted in Sect. 1) who aptly makes a shot from just barely above his threshold of reliability. The shooter, who succeeds in endeavour to make the basket, is unaware that he is above his threshold of reliability, and so too easily would have shot inaptly.

  1. (ii)

    a huntress who, despite drinking much wine, aptly shoots a scurrying rabbit in twilight fog. Sosa stipulates that the huntress’s shot was apt—successful because adroit—although (like the reliable guesser and the basketball shooter) not reflectively competent, because the huntress is unaware that her shot in these conditions would be apt and has thus underestimated her prowess.

I think, though, that these three cases—the reliable guesser, the basketball shooter and the huntress—betray some subtle but ultimately important differences. The differences end up mattering, I’ll suggest, for whether we should agree that the reliable guesser in EYE EXAM attains a form of animal knowledge, what Sosa calls ‘subcredal’ animal knowledge, even if we grant Sosa’s stipulation that the reliable guesser affirms the bottom-row letters aptly. And, the diagnosis for why this is so will lead us to a better account of guessing (or so I hope to show).

In order to draw out the differences between the three cases, it will be important to first note a key second-order difference between the case of the huntress and the basketball player. The basketball player is what we can call second-order oblivious to the threshold of his own reliability. As Sosa describes the case, the shooter:

shoots indiscriminately at distances too near his threshold of sufficient reliability [...] In that zone—barely above the threshold—he is still likely enough to succeed, even without knowing that he is. So, even in his ignorance he can still perform with animal aptness, but full aptness is now beyond him (2015, p. 70).

Being second-order oblivious about whether you are above or below your threshold for sufficient reliability is different from being second-order mistaken about your threshold for sufficient reliability, even though being either second-order oblivious or second-order mistaken about your threshold for sufficient reliability is enough to prevent your first-order endeavour from being reflectively competent and thus fully apt.

Sosa’s shooter is second-order oblivious, although to find an individual who is second-order mistaken, we need only to consider again his huntress, Diana. As Sosa describes the case, Diana thinks there is little chance of success (in light of her having drunk much wine, and the twilight fog of the conditions), and in thinking this, ‘underestimates her prowess’ (2015, p. 68).

Unlike the basketball shooter, Diana actually thinks that she’s outside our threshold of reliability, though she happens to be within it. The basketball shooter doesn’t think this. The basketball shooter doesn’t, like Diane does, underestimate (or for that matter overestimate) his prowess. He simply shoots aptly whilst lacking any appreciation that he is within his threshold for sufficient reliability.

The difference between the basketball shooter and Diana can be accounted for in terms of what we can call performative defeat.Footnote 11 In traditional epistemological discussions of defeaters,Footnote 12 defeaters are beliefs or doubts which count against (in the case of rebutting defeaters) the truth of a target belief, or (in the case of undercutting defeat) against the reliability of the target belief’s formation.

Call a subject S’s belief that p a performative defeater if, with respect to some occasion of endeavour E, S’s belief that p (in the rebutting case) counts against S’s attaining success in E and (in the undercutting case) calls into doubt the reliability of S’s competence in E by indicating that were S to succeed in E, the success would not be apt. Framed this way, it is of course possible for these defeaters to overlap. For example, suppose that the occasion of endeavour in question is that of sinking a simple two-foot putt. Suppose though that, through irrationality, a golfer believes that she has severe Ehlers-Danlos syndrome, an invisible but debilitating connective tissue disorder. The golfer’s belief that she has Ehlers-Danlos is a rebutting performative defeater. It counts against her successfully attaining her aim (sinking the putt) on this occasion of endeavour. But it is also undercutting (in the sense described) because it indicates that were she to succeed, the success would not be apt—it would not be because of adroitness but because the ball happened to go in despite unreliable form.

Though rebutting and undercutting performative defeaters can also come apart. Consider that, as described, performative defeaters are psychological or mental state defeatersFootnote 13: they defeat, as Lackey puts it, simply ‘by being had’, and not by being rational or true. Accordingly, there will be cases where the two kinds of defeat can come apart.

For example, suppose Sosa’s skilled huntress, Diana, is told that a prankster has set up invisible forcefields around many, but not all, of the targets in the field. Suppose further the targets—with and without forcefields—are far away enough that only one with great skill, such as Diana, would be able to successfully hit one at such a range. By acquiring the belief that some of these targets are surrounded by invisible forcefields, the huntress acquires a performative rebutting defeater, one that counts against her succeeding on an occasion of endeavour to shoot and hit one of the targets in the field in these conditions. However, this belief arguably does not indicate that were the huntress’s shot to be successful, that it would thereby not be apt. Such a successful shot would surely be creditable in large part to the huntress’ impressive competence.Footnote 14

Rebutting and undercutting performative defeaters can come apart in the other direction as well, where an agent has an undercutting performative defeater, but not a rebutting performative defeater. Singer Adele Adkins, for example, reports a dejected experience prior to singing on stage: though she does not have any doubts about how to sing the notes she is meant to sing—it is not as though she scrambles to double-check the lyrics or worries irrationally that she is suddenly too hoarse to sing them—she reports worrying, in a nebulous sense (perhaps irrationally), that she will bomb the performance. Adele, to stress, does not report having any beliefs, about any particular notes or songs, that she does not know how to sing them. She rather has doubts about herself—viz., that her performing a set of songs on stage will manifest her competence to sing them. Thus: an undercutting performative defeater in the absence of a rebutting performative defeater.

With the foregoing picture of performative defeaters in mind, we can now diagnose in a more principled way the key difference between Sosa’s basketball shooter, second-order oblivious, and the huntress, second-order mistaken, both of whom (like the reliable guesser in EYE EXAM) perform aptly at the first-order but, without second-order reflective competence, not fully aptly. Here is the difference: the second-order oblivious basketball shooter does not have a performative defeater (rebutting or undercutting),Footnote 15 but the huntress does. The huntress has at least an undercutting performative defeater, given how Sosa has described the case, plausibly also a performative rebutting defeater.Footnote 16 This is the case even though both are alike in that their respective performances are apt but not reflectively competent and so not fully apt.

Now, I think it matters for whether Sosa is right that his reliable guesser in EYE EXAM attains subcredal animal knowledge, whether the reliable guesser is more like the basketball shooter (who is second-order oblivious, with no performative defeater) or the huntress (who is second-order mistaken, with a performative defeater). In the next section, I want to argue that the reliable guesser is in fact like the huntress, not the basketball player, vis-a-vis performative defeat. This, it will be suggested, a consequence of the particular way that guessing, as a representational attitude distinct from ordinary belief, should be understood as having an alethic aim.

4 Guessing, the truth aim, and defeat

A point familiar from James (1897) is that the aim of possessing the truth is best understood as a mixture of two competing aims: truly representing and not misrepresenting.Footnote 17 This would be relatively uninteresting if these aims were in no way in competition with one another.Footnote 18

However, there is an important sense in which truly representing and not misrepresenting are competing aims. This point can be made in terms of risk: one can only fulfil the first aim by putting oneself at risk of not fulfilling the second. Weighting the second aim, not misrepresenting, more would lead one to be more cautious so as to avoid possible misrepresentation. Correspondingly, weighting the first aim more would lead one to be bolder in order to possess more truths.

In Carter, Jarvis and Rubin (Forthcoming), we showed how different ways of mixing these two aims correspond to doxastic attitudes at different places in the hierarchy of representational attitudes. Here is a brief overview of this idea:

There are attitudes like being-sure, where the second aim is appropriately weighted more (so that misrepresentation is worse and failing to truly represent isn’t so bad), and there are attitudes like suspecting, where the first aim is appropriately weighted more (so that failing to truly represent is worse and misrepresentation isn’t so bad). But, the aim of all of these doxastic attitudes is to possess the truth by having the attitude. It’s just the mixture of the twin aims—how important they should be in different situations—that varies.

Guessing is very much like suspectingFootnote 19 in the following sense: both are attitudes that, by taking them up, we aim at truth, but in a sense that is weaker, or less cautious, than belief.Footnote 20 With states like suspecting and guessing, more error possibilities are tolerable in order take a chance on possessing the truth.Footnote 21 I won’t rehearse our argument for this picture here.Footnote 22 However, to the extent that the model proposed is a plausible one—viz., that in taking up the attitude of suspecting, or guessing, we aim at the truth in a way that affords more weight to truly representing than to not-misrepresenting (and vice versa for the attitude of being-sure-that)—we have cause to wonder whether ‘knowledge’ (animal or otherwise) is really what we should call whatever achievements ensue from reliable guessing or suspecting.

In order to appreciate this point, contrast Sosa’s reliable guesser with a slight variation on EYE EXAM, involving a reliable believer. Suppose the reliable believer and the reliable guesser’s first-order visual-perceptual competence is identical. Both affirm the top letters more easily. The reliable guesser affirms by resorting to guessing at the bottom row, the reliable believer affirms by believing. What is the difference between the two?Footnote 23 Saying there is no difference is of course not a viable optionFootnote 24. But, the most viable way to account for what such a difference would be will ultimately be in tension with Sosa’s diagnosis of the reliable guesser’s achievement as animal knowledge (subcredal or otherwise). I’ll now explain this point.

Firstly, consider that the reliable believer is best understood as on a performative par with Sosa’s basketball shooter. Recall that the basketball shooter, who makes a shot from just above his threshold for sufficient reliability, but unaware of this, was second-order oblivious, not second-order mistaken, and this was the more fine grained characterisation of why the shooter lacked reflective competence. So described, we said that Sosa’s basketball shooter did not have a performative defeater, as the huntress surely did. The same is the case for a ‘belief’ variation on Sosa’s reliable guesser. That is, if we hold fixed the first-order competence of Sosa’s reliable guesser in affirming the bottom row letters–in which case the letters still appear somewhat blurry, even though they are affirmed correctly–but suppose that the attitude taken up is a belief rather than a guess, we are now in the same position as the basketball shooter: we have a first-order apt performance that is not reflectively competent because the performance is second-order oblivious.

But Sosa’s reliable guesser is not second-order oblivious, like she would be were she taking up the attitude of belief. And here I think (i) the heirarchial model of representational attitudes as a function of mixing the competing aims of truly representing and not misrepresenting, along with the notion of (ii) performative defeat introduced in Sect. 1, can help us to diagnose just why.

Here it will be helpful, initially, to consider the classic case of the chicken-sexerFootnote 25. This is paradigmatic case of an individual with a reliable competence but who is not reflectively competent because second-order oblivious. The chicken sexer purports to believe of each chick, what its sex is—the chicken sexer would not tell you she was guessing. She is believing. This is so even though the chicken sexer cannot furnish you with any grounds for her belief. As Sosa (2015, p. 76) rightly suggests, the chicken sexer attains an apt belief, and so animal knowledge.

Now, let’s run a quick variation on the chicken-sexer case. Suppose that the chicken-sexer took herself to resort to guessing, rather than believing. Suppose she tells you she was guessing. Does she attain animal knowledge, provided we assume the first-order reliable competence (at sexing chickens) is the same as it is in the original case? Provided she is sincere, the answer should be no, and the explanation for this has two parts. The chicken sexer, in regarding herself as guessing, plausibly has acquired a psychological defeater that is lacked by the believing chicken-sexer. Indeed, unless one is guessing while regarding oneself as believing, one is, resorting to guessing, acquiring a psychological defeater—namely, that she is guessing—which undermines (unless defeated) one’s animal knowledge.

Why is this? Why is mere awareness that one’s aim at truth is a guess, itself enough to constitute a defeater, one that suffices to defeat animal knowledge? The answer is that regarding oneself as guessing is as the same time regarding oneself as aiming at truth in a way that tolerates more error possibilities than are plausibly tolerated by knowledge.Footnote 26 Guesses can be apt, no doubt. But when they are, the ensuing achievement is not reliable enough to qualify as knowledge, animal or otherwise, because of the type of bold attempt at truth which a guess is, one which weights representing truly much more than not-representing falsely.Footnote 27

The basketball-performative analogue to the chicken-sexer-cum guesser and also to Sosa’s own reliable guesser will be a player who regards herself as having attempted to score in a manner that tolerates greater-than-average error possibility—by shooting-via-chucking the ball—than in normal circumstances. Even if, by stipulation, the basketball player’s chucking form is actually reliable enough, the fact that the basketball player regards herself as chucking the ball—a method she appreciates to be less reliable than usual—rather than shooting normally, the shooter acquires a performative defeater which renders the shot on par with the chicken-sexer-cum-guesser—namely that they are aiming at attaining the truth by guessing, and so thereby by tolerating greater than normal error.

Sosa’s reliable guesser in EYE EXAM is on a performative par with the following three reflectively incompetent individuals: the chicken-sexer-cum-guesser and the basketball player who acquires a performative defeater in light of knowingly chucking the ball,Footnote 28 unknowingly doing so reliably, and Diana, who is second-order mistaken by underestimating her prowess from the range at which she is shooting. None of these characters is second-order oblivious; each is second-order mistaken in a way that generates a performative defeater. The basketball chucker because he regards himself as issuing a shot from what he takes to be a less-than-reliable enough form, and the chicken-sexer-cum guesser and Sosa’s reliable guesser because both have a belief which counts against their affirmations being reliable enough–namely that they are aiming at attaining the truth by guessing, and so by tolerating greater than normal error.

There is an important disanalogy then between these three reflectively incompetent individuals and another three reflectively incompetent individuals: the (ordinary) chicken sexer, and Sosa’s basketball shooter (unaware that he is just above his threshold for reliability), and as his EYE EXAM examinee would be were the examinee to have trafficked in beliefs rather than guesses.

5 Some new parallels

To the extent that the previous section’s discussion is right, then if there is such a thing as sub-credal animal knowledge, it will not be acquired in cases where an individual, no matter how reliable she is in the relevant domain of endeavour, takes herself to be guessing. The way that, when guessing, we aim at truth is a way which gives disproportionate weight to representing truly versus not misrepresenting, and as such is distinguished as an attitude which, just by taking up this attitude, we take a chance on attaining the truth by tolerating more error possibilities than usual, more than is plausibly tolerated by knowledge. As such, by regarding oneself as guessing—that is, when one guesses and is not mistaken that one is guessing—one thereby acquires a defeater which one would need to defeat in order to attain animal knowledge.Footnote 29 One way to defeat this defeater would be to, say, learn from the eye professional that one is extremely reliable, such that then one no longer regards herself as guessing when she affirms the letters on the lower row, so that now she believes what she affirms at the bottom row.

I want to conclude by doing three final things. Firstly, to make some remarks about unreliable achievements, secondly, to sharpen the discussion of weighting representing truly more so than not misrepresenting, in the case of guessing, and thirdly, to advance—from within Sosa’s own programme—some performative parallels that I think map on to a range of different kinds of guesses.

5.1 Unreliable achievements

Even if guesses cannot aspire to knowledge, animal or otherwise, this is not to say that guesses cannot be apt. In fact, Sosa’s reliable guesser’s beliefs are surely apt, in that their accuracy manifests a first-order reliable competence.

In Carter et al. (2015), we suggested that, just as there are varieties of representational attitudes that aim at truth differently (by corresponding, in the proper governance of these states, with different ways in which the twin goods of attaining truth and avoiding error are weighted), there are also varieties of cognitive achievements. An advantage of our model was an explanation for why knowledge, cum cognitive achievement, must ordinarily be safe, and this is because of the particular kind of attempt at success that belief is—namely, an attempt that places the premium it does on avoiding error.

Some achievements, including physical and artistic achievements, are of course highly unreliable, issued by means that ordinarily wouldn’t be successful. Here’s one blatant such example, suggested by Turri (Forthcoming):

BABY STEPS: Geno is eleven months old. He’s daily been gaining confidence in his ability to balance on two feet. Today he stood holding onto the couch when an object in Dad’s hand commanded his attention. Inspired, Geno let go and, to his parents’ delight, took his first two steps in Dad’s direction (Turri, Forthcoming, p. 14).

Likewise, consider the case of a potter:

POTTER: Ben produces his signature pottery, which is highly regarded, by methods that very often produce cracked and broken failures. In order to produce a new work, he may, in the typical instance, have to make several (or many) attempts. Ordinarily, his ways of making pottery is unsafe.Footnote 30

BABY STEPS and POTTER are examples of a phenomenon perhaps best captured with reference to the case of Red Sox batting champion Ted Williams: arguably the greatest hitter in the history of baseball, and who hit safely only 40% of the time. What BABY STEPS, POTTER and the case of Ted Williams suggest is just that some achievements are unreliable, in that they are issued by unsafe methods.

In the cognitive case, this is to be expected as well. When, for example, Sherlock Holmes makes an educated guessFootnote 31—one that turns out to be right—this is a cognitive achievement, one creditable to his abductive prowess, though it is not knowledge, animal or otherwise. This is the case even if Sherlock’s guessing turns out to be as reliable as Sosa’s reliable guesser in EYE EXAM. Sherlock, like the reliable guesser, provided they appreciate that they are guessing, acquire a defeater—that, in taking a chance on attaining truth, they’ve by guessing tolerated more error possibilities than in normal circumstances, and more than is plausibly tolerated by knowledge.

5.2 Guesses and weighting

Suppose a fair coin is flipped, and then covered up. What is your credence that the coin has landed heads? It should be .5. You of course shouldn’t believe that that the coin has landed heads. And this is as it should be; belief corresponds with a mixture of the weighting the aims of believing truly and not misrepresenting which places a premium on not misrepresenting. In short, this situation is riskier than what befits belief.Footnote 32

But do you guess that the coin is heads? Perhaps only if there is some practical pressure to affirm one way or the other. Nothing you know favours heads over tails. But you can nonetheless, in this circumstance, take a reckless chance on possessing the truth—and if it turns up heads, you were right.

Call the representational attitude—one that gives a maximal weight to representing truly and affords no weight to not misrepresenting—a blind guess.Footnote 33 The performative analogue, in basketball, would be taking a shot, with no appreciation of one’s orientation with respect to the basket—viz., a shot in total darkness. This is an attempt at success which tolerates nearly all error possibilities.Footnote 34 It is fitting that blind guesses are sometimes referred to as shots in the dark.

But not all guesses are blind. Sosa’s reliable guesser is not after all, entirely insensitive to the aim of misrepresenting, even if he takes himself to be guessing. Granted during the examination, as the letters get smaller, Sosa describes ‘I start to lose confidence that I am getting the letters right’. But plausibly some confidence is retained, such that from the perspective of the guesser, some error possibilities are excluded. As Sosa describes the case, ‘there are many cases where I am quite unsure as to whether it is an “E” or an “F”, say, or a “P” rather than an “F”, etc. (2015, p. 74).’ This is a familiar situation: one where we affirm, due to some practical pressure to do so, while aware that some, though not all, relevant error possibilities remain live. Sosa’s guesser is not, plausibly, unsure whether the letter before him is an “I” rather than an “F”.

Guessing is a genus with different species. Guessing, as such, involves taking chance on attaining truth in a way that mixes the aims of truly representing and not misrepresenting less cautiously than belief, and in doing so tolerates comparatively more epistemic risk. Guesses can be more or less cautious, and I’ll elaborate on this point in the next section by drawing some athletic-performative analogues.

It is worth highlighting that the foregoing characterisation of guessing is compatible with Sosa’s account of the normativity of guessing–viz., as affirmation in the endeavour ‘to get it right, without affirming in the endeavor to get it right reliably enough’–even though the foregoing is incompatible with the suggestion that reliable guessing aspires to knowledge (subcredal, animal or otherwise).Footnote 35

5.3 Performative analogies

Recall now some performative parallels that have already been drawn: a blind guess is akin to taking a shot at making a basket in conditions where one lacks any appreciation of one’s orientation to the basket—viz., a shot in the dark. A more cautious attempt at gaining a truth is a wild guess, which involves affirming in the endeavour to get it right, but while tolerating more error possibilities than does Sosa’s reliable guesser, when the reliable guesser affirms while unsure whether a given letter is an “E”, an “F” or a “P”. The wild guesser by contrast affirms (for example) while unsure, of a given letter, whether it is (in this case) any somewhat wide letter, thus excluding letters such as “I”. If the guesser cannot even rule out the “I”, and so affirms without being able to rule out any contextually relevant error possibilities,Footnote 36 the guess is not wild but blind. I suggested in Sect. 1 the basketball-performative analogue to a wild guess is a shot from half-court, under normal conditions; one can control one’s shot choice so as to exclude shooting away from the basket, which cannot be ruled out when taking a shot in the dark, while nonetheless knowingly taking a chance on a basket that tolerates most error possibilities.

It’s convenient to give guesses such names as blind and wild when they tolerate all or most error possibilities, by involving affirming in a way that affords either no or barely any weight to the aim of not misrepresenting.

But there are plenty of other varieties of guess which are less easily named—though a helpful way to think about them is by juxtaposing them with their practical performance analogues. Specifically, we can do this by considering cases where the performative defeaters in cognitive and non-cognitive cases line up.

Sosa’s own reliable guesser was, I suggested, analogous not to the basketball shooter, second-order oblivious, who shoots from just above his threshold for reliability. That basketball shooter did not have a performative defeater. The shooter would, however, were he to have chucked (rather than shot normally) the ball in a way that was unbeknownst to him reliable enough. That’s the analogue to reliable guessing.

We can distinguish Sosa’s reliable guesser from a guesser in a slightly different situation, which is best appreciated by considering first an athletic-performative parallel. Suppose firstly that Sosa’s basketball shooter is at a range very slightly below his threshold for sufficient reliability, but that he knows that this is the case, and takes (and makes) the shot anyway. This is similar to, but not quite like, the case of the individual who chucks the ball, unbeknownst to her, reliably. It’s similar in that both regard themselves as tolerating above-normal risk (the former because she regards chucking to fall short of reliable enough form, the latter because she knows that from that distance, using normal form, she’s slightly below the threshold for sufficient reliability). But the cases are different in that the shooter—shooting normally but knowingly slightly below his threshold for sufficient reliability—is (unlike the chucker who is unknowingly reliable) actually not sufficiently reliable, even though the shot is successful. So reliable guessing cannot be the right cognitive analogue performance.

The right analogue here is, I think, what we can call a (mere) educated guess. This will be when one, for example, hears from the reliable testimony of the optician that the next row is (based on a very recent calculation) very near, but just below, her threshold for sufficient reliability, and indeed the individual affirms correctly, but through a competence she knows is just barely not sufficiently reliableFootnote 37.

A final species of guess, different from those noted so far, that I think merits attention is analogous to a more complex—but not entirely uncommon—kind of performative situation. Consider the following:

3-POINTER: Steph, an excellent 3-point shooter, often reads his detailed shooting statistics to assess whether he is reliable enough from various places outside the 3-point line, to warrant taking open shots. Steph had recently read a statistical analysis of his performance from various ranges. The source he consulted, http://www.fivethirtyeight.com, uses expert Bayesian modeling, and Steph has no reason do doubt the source’s reliability.Footnote 38 Steph is confident that if this source says he is above his threshold for sufficient reliability at a given range, then he is. Accordingly, on the basis of this source, Steph believes that he is reliable enough from 28 feet to warrant taking an open shot at 28 feet. However, Steph’s coach also read the piece, and told Steph prior to today’s game, that he is sure the number was 27, not 28. Steph thinks his coach is almost certainly wrong, and continues to believe that the number is 28—but nonetheless, in light of being unable (on the court) to dismiss this error possibility, Steph accepts that he does not know that he is reliable enough from 28 feet, despite his continuing to believe this. He takes an open shot from 28 feet and makes it.

This case is unlike any of the others so far. Firstly, like the reliable guesser, Steph is sufficiently reliable from 28 feet. (Suppose that Steph’s coach was incorrect). But, unlike the reliable guesser, Steph believes he is reliable enough from 28 feet, despite (in light of the on-court incorrect testimony from his coach) believing that he does not know this. Like the educated guesser, Steph has sought out reliable independent information about his reliability range. Unlike the educated guesser, Steph believes, before taking his shot, that he is from that distance reliable enough.

Does Steph have a performative defeater, in the sense articulated in Sect. 2? Yes. The on-court belief he acquires, that his coach insists the article noted 27 rather than 28 as his reliable-enough threshold, counts against the reliability of Steph’s competence from 28 feet by indicating that were Steph to succeed in from 28 feet, the success would not be apt. Steph, it was stipulated, has doubts about the accuracy of this defeater, but—standing on the court—he does not regard himself as able to rule it out, to defeat the defeater, and so regards himself as not knowing he is reliable enough from that range, despite believing that he is.

What species of guess will be the cognitive parallel to 3-POINTER? In order to get this right, let’s try to model this kind of performative defeater Steph has acquired as closely as we can, in the cognitive case:

PI: Elodin, a gambler, is attempting to memorise \(\pi \) to at least one digit past any of his friends, without making any errors (a single error nullifies the recitation, disqualifying him from winning the bet). Elodin has Cartesian certainty that the first three numbers are 3.14. Beyond that, his confidence ever so gradually wanes. Elodin’s record, in practice, is 60 digits before failing. But, after practicing many times, he’s concluded that he is reliable enough, in the context of the bet, only to attempt to recite \(\pi \) up 40 digits. The 40th digit of \(\pi \) is a “1”. the 39th digit is “7.Footnote 39” Prior to the bet, a friend tells him that his calculations of his own reliability are are very slightly off and that, on the basis of Elodin’s practice records, he’s in fact reliable enough only to attempt the first 39 digits, not the 40th. Elodin believes his friend is wrong, but, he realises he cannot conclusively rule this out. Elodin, believing—but believing that he does not know—that the 40th digit of \(\pi \) is a “1”, does not stop at the 39th digit. He affirms, correctly, that the 40th digit is a “1”.

Elodin affirms the “1” while believing he does not know he is reliable enough (given that knows he can’t rule out that his friend is right, despite believing his friend is wrong) in the context of his affirmation. This affirmation is as such a species of guess: an attempt at truth whereby one takes a chance on gaining a truth in a way that tolerates more than usual error. But the risk Elodin knowingly undertakes here is marginal. He does not believe he is not reliable enough; he merely believes he does not know he is reliable enough, while believing he is.

Call this species of guess a conjectural affirmation. In the case of Elodin, the doubt he has, though it is appreciated as undefeated in the context of the affirmation, is compresent with his competent belief that he is reliable enough. Elodin, as well as Steph, after all, believe on good grounds that they are reliable enough, and affirm and shoot respectively while maintaining they do not know they are reliable enough. Conjectural affirmations, like other guesses, do not aspire to knowledge (animal or otherwise).Footnote 40

6 Concluding remarks

In the foregoing, I’ve shown why Sosa’s view of guessing mistakenly identifies certain kinds of guesses as candidates for knowledge. I’ve argued for a different way of thinking about guessing, as a kind of attitude that by its very nature incurs a kind of defeater which is acquired when one takes a chance on truth by tolerating above-normal levels of risk. The rationale for the view advanced draws importantly from the Jamesian insight that the aim of possessing the truth is best understood as a mixture of two competing aims—truly representing and not misrepresenting. After situating my favoured approach to the attitude of guessing in the wider context of unreliable achievements, I concluded by distinguishing various species of guesses in connection with what are presented as their practical performative analogues.

I want to close by noting that I believe Sosa’s overarching project in Judgment and Agency is a tremendous achievement in epistemology. It is, I think, his most compelling presentation of his distinctive brand of virtue epistemology to date. The aim here has not been to challenge Sosa’s wider framework, as such, but to suggest how—from within this rich framework—a better account of guessing can be advanced, one which squares better with plausible insights about knowledge and epistemic defeat.Footnote 41