Skip to main content
Log in

Experimental individuation and philosophical retail arguments

  • Published:
Synthese Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

This paper aims to defend the use of the notion of experimental individuation, which has recently been developed by Ruey-Lin Chen, as a criterion for the reality of theoretical entities. In short, when scientists experimentally individuate an entity, a realist conclusion about that entity is warranted. We embed this claim regarding experimental individuation within a framework that allows for other criteria of reality. And we understand so-called retail arguments regarding the reality of a particular theoretical entity as arguments that concern choosing an appropriate criterion of reality for that entity and determining whether the relevant first-order scientific evidence satisfies that criterion. We argue that such retail arguments are philosophical because defending criteria of reality, and showing that they are or are not satisfied in particular cases, involves work that is distinctively philosophical. And we illustrate this philosophical work by applying our criterion of experimental individuation to three historical cases: Davy’s potassium, Lavoisier’s muriatic radical, and Thomson’s electrified particles.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Fig. 1

Reproduced from Thomson (1897, p. 296)

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. We thank an anonymous reviewer for pointing out this important distinction. It’s worth noting that so-called selective realist positions differ from one other and from other positions in the realism debate, not in terms of the argumentative strategy they adopt but in terms of the theoretical content to which they are committed. For example, entity realists commit to the reality of entities, structural realists to structures, and deployment realists to theoretical components that contribute to generating novel predictive successes.

  2. Dicken (2013) raises an important challenge to retailism on this basis. Responding to this challenge falls outside of the scope of the present paper.

  3. Retrieved January 27, 2016 from http://www.nobelprize.org/educational/physics/vacuum/experiment-1.html. See also Harré (2002[1981]) and Whittaker (1989).

  4. For the identification of Thomson’s corpuscles with electrons, see Rutherford (2004[1904], p. 53) and the reprint of Thomson (1897) in Magie (1969, pp. 583–597), in which Magie makes the identification.

  5. Bueno (2018) argues for a similar point from an empiricist perspective. He uses three cases of trapping quantum particles in experiments in order to argue that Hacking’s manipulation criterion cannot successfully serve as a criterion of reality.

  6. See Lavoisier (1965[1789], p. 156).

  7. See Hricko (2018) for a detailed discussion of this case.

  8. See Kirwan (1789, pp. 4–5).

  9. One might suspect that Lavoisier’s error regarding muriatic acid was disconnected from the main posits of his oxygen theory. However, Chang (2012b, p. 8) identifies Lavoisier’s theory of acidity as one of “[t]hree major pillars of Lavoisier’s system of chemistry,” and points out that Lavoisier chose the term ‘oxygen’ (which literally means ‘acid-generator’ in Greek) because of its central role in his system as the acidifying principle (2012b, p. 9).

  10. It’s worth noting that neither Hardin and Rosenberg nor Psillos discuss dephlogisticated acid of salt. That said, it follows from Psillos’s claims regarding the reference of ‘phlogiston’ that dephlogisticated acid of salt is a non-existent entity.

  11. See Hricko (2018, pp. 273–275) for a retail argument for this conclusion regarding Scheele’s dephlogisticated acid of salt.

  12. For a detailed history, see Buchwald (1995a, b).

  13. Hacking (1983, pp. 22–23) draws a stronger conclusion when he claims that he would not have been a realist about electrons even in 1908, when Millikan measured the charge of the electron.

References

  • Boyd, R. (1981). Scientific realism and naturalistic epistemology. In PSA: Proceedings of the Biennial Meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association, Vol. 1980, Volume Two: Symposia and Invited Papers (pp. 613–662).

  • Buchwald, J. Z. (1995a). The creation of scientific effects: Heinrich Hertz and electric waves. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Buchwald, J. Z. (1995b). Why Hertz was right about cathode rays. In J. Z. Buchwald (Ed.), Scientific practice: Theories and stories of doing physics (pp. 151–169). Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bueno, O. (2018). Can quantum objects be tracked? In O. Bueno, R.-L. Chen, & M. B. Fagan (Eds.), Individuation, process, and scientific practices (pp. 239–258). New York: Oxford University Press. https://doi.org/10.1093/oso/9780190636814.003.0011.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Chang, H. (2012a). Beyond case-studies: History as philosophy. In S. H. Mauskopf & T. Schmaltz (Eds.), Integrating history and philosophy of science: Problems and prospects (pp. 109–124). Netherlands: Springer. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-007-1745-9_8.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Chang, H. (2012b). Is water H2O? Evidence, realism and pluralism. Dordrecht: Springer. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-007-3932-1.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Chen, R.-L. (2007). The structure of experimentation and the replication degree: Reconsidering the replication of Hertz’s cathode ray experiment. In C. M. Mi & R.-L. Chen (Eds.), Naturalized epistemology and the philosophy of science (pp. 129–149). Amsterdam: Rodopi Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chen, R.-L. (2016). Experimental realization of individuality. In A. Guay & T. Pradeu (Eds.), Individuals across the sciences (pp. 348–370). New York: Oxford University Press. https://doi.org/10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199382514.003.0018.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Chen, R.-L. (2018). Experimental individuation: Creation and presentation. In O. Bueno, R.-L. Chen, & M. B. Fagan (Eds.), Individuation, process, and scientific practices (pp. 192–213). New York: Oxford University Press. https://doi.org/10.1093/oso/9780190636814.003.0009.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Davy, H. (1808). The Bakerian Lecture [for 1807]: On some new phenomena of chemical changes produced by electricity, particularly the decomposition of the fixed alkalies, and the exhibition of the new substances which constitute their bases; and on the general nature of alkaline bodies. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society of London, 98, 1–44.

    Google Scholar 

  • Davy, H. (1809). The Bakerian Lecture [for 1808]: An account of some new analytical researches on the nature of certain bodies, particularly the alkalies, phosphorus, sulphur, carbonaceous matter, and the acids hitherto undecompounded; with some general observations on chemical theory. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society of London, 99, 39–104.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Davy, H. (1810). Researches on the oxymuriatic acid, its nature and combinations; and on the elements of the muriatic acid. With some experiments on sulphur and phosphorus, made in the laboratory of the Royal Institution. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society of London, 100, 231–257.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Davy, H. (1811). The Bakerian Lecture [for 1810]: On some of the combinations of oxymuriatic gas and oxygene, and on the chemical relations of these principles, to inflammable bodies. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society of London, 101, 1–35.

    Google Scholar 

  • Davy, H. (1813). Letter to Berzelius, written 1813/08/04. Retrieved from http://www.davy-letters.org.uk/cms/search/letter.php?id=337. Accessed 10 Oct 2018.

  • Dicken, P. (2013). Normativity, the base-rate fallacy, and some problems for retail realism. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science, 44(4), 563–570. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.shpsa.2013.09.005.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fitzpatrick, S. (2013). Doing away with the no miracles argument. In V. Karakostas & D. Dieks (Eds.), EPSA11 perspectives and foundational problems in philosophy of science (pp. 141–151). Berlin: Springer. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-01306-0_12.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Gay-Lussac, J. L., & Thénard, L. J. (1808). Sur la décomposition et la recomposition de l’acide boracique. Annales de Chimie, 68, 169–174.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hacking, I. (1983). Representing and intervening: Introductory topics in the philosophy of natural science. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Hardin, C. L., & Rosenberg, A. (1982). In defense of convergent realism. Philosophy of Science, 49(4), 604–615. https://doi.org/10.1086/289080.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Harré, R. (2002[1981]). Great scientific experiments: 20 experiments that changed our view of the world. New York: Dover Publications.

  • Hricko, J. (2018). Retail realism, the individuation of theoretical entities, and the case of the muriatic radical. In O. Bueno, R.-L. Chen, & M. B. Fagan (Eds.), Individuation, process, and scientific practices (pp. 259–278). New York: Oxford University Press. https://doi.org/10.1093/oso/9780190636814.003.0012.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Kirwan, R. (1789). An essay on phlogiston and the constitution of acids (2nd ed.). London: J. Johnson.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ladyman, J. (2011). Structural realism versus standard scientific realism: The case of phlogiston and dephlogisticated air. Synthese, 180(2), 87–101. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-009-9607-8.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lavoisier, A. L. (1965[1789]). Elements of chemistry. New York: Dover.

  • Lyons, T. D. (2002). Scientific realism and the pessimistic meta-modus tollens. In T. D. Lyons & S. Clarke (Eds.), Recent themes in the philosophy of science: Scientific realism and common sense (pp. 63–90). Dordrecht: Kluwer. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-017-2862-1_4.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Magie, W. F. (Ed.). (1969). A source book in physics. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Magnus, P. D., & Callender, C. (2004). Realist ennui and the base rate fallacy. Philosophy of Science, 71(3), 320–338. https://doi.org/10.1086/421536.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Park, S. (2016). Extensional scientific realism vs. intensional scientific realism. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science, 59(1), 46–52. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.shpsa.2016.06.001.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Psillos, S. (1999). Scientific realism: How science tracks truth. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Psillos, S. (2005). Scientific realism and metaphysics. Ratio, 18(4), 385–404. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1467-9329.2005.00301.x.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Putnam, H. (1978). Meaning and the moral sciences. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Radder, H. (1995). Experimenting in the natural sciences: A philosophical approach. In J. Z. Buchwald (Ed.), Scientific practice: Theories and stories of doing physics (pp. 56–86). Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rutherford, E. (2004[1904]). Radio-activity. Mineola: Dover.

  • Saatsi, J. (2010). Form-driven vs. content-driven arguments for realism. In P. D. Magnus & J. Busch (Eds.), New waves in philosophy of science (pp. 8–28). Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Scheele, C. W. (1931[1774]). On manganese or magnesia; and its properties. In The collected papers of Charles Wilhelm Scheele, translated from the Swedish and German originals by Leonard Dobbin (pp. 17–49). London: G. Bell and Sons.

  • Stanford, P. K. (2006). Exceeding our grasp: Science, history, and the problem of unconceived alternatives. New York: Oxford University Press. https://doi.org/10.1093/0195174089.001.0001.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Thomson, J. J. (1897). Cathode rays. Philosophical Magazine, 44(269), 293–316. https://doi.org/10.1080/14786449708621070.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Thomson, J. J. (1967[1906]). Carriers of negative electricity. Nobel Lecture, December 11, 1906. In Nobel Lectures: Physics, 19011921 (pp. 145–153). Amsterdam: Elsevier.

  • van Fraassen, B. C. (1980). The scientific image. Oxford: Clarendon Press. https://doi.org/10.1093/0198244274.001.0001.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Whittaker, E. T. (1989). A history of the theories of aether and electricity. New York: Dover.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

We’d first like to thank three anonymous reviewers for valuable comments that substantially improved and strengthened the arguments in this article. We’d also like to thank audiences at the International Workshop on Scientific Realism at Kyoto University and the Twenty-Fifth Biennial Meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association in Atlanta, Georgia, and especially Juha Saatsi, Hasok Chang, and Timothy Lyons for helpful comments. This work was supported by the Ministry of Science and Technology in Taiwan (MOST 105-2410-H-194-072-MY3, MOST 106-2410-H-010-001).

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Ruey-Lin Chen.

Ethics declarations

Conflict of interest

The authors declare that they have no conflict of interest.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Chen, RL., Hricko, J. Experimental individuation and philosophical retail arguments. Synthese 198, 2313–2332 (2021). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-019-02207-8

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-019-02207-8

Keywords

Navigation