Skip to main content
Log in

From Phoebus to witches to death clocks: why we are taking predictive technologies to the extreme

  • Main Paper
  • Published:
AI & SOCIETY Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

In the following article, I shall focus on emerging technologies that increasingly try to predict our death, i.e. when we will die and from what cause. More precisely, I shall focus on the possible answer to the following philosophical question: why are we taking predictive technologies to the extreme? First, I shall reflect upon the results of recent empirical research. Second, I shall address the issue of taking predictive technologies to the extreme, i.e. predicting one’s death, through philosophical tools, from thought experiments to a philosophical perspective on the possible key reason why we are using emerging technologies’ unprecedented power of prediction to improve more and more our knowledge of when we will die and from what cause. The philosophical answer I propose is the following: even death clocks, together with other kinds of emerging technologies that gain an unprecedented power of prediction, may somehow save us by reactivating our sensemaking whenever our life is uncertain and demanding to the point that we cannot face our open future by planning and acting by ourselves. If it is true that the price we pay, i.e. a kind of automation of our own future, is extremely high, it is also true that, in our unprecedentedly uncertain and demanding time, autonomous sensemaking seems to scare us even more.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Data availability

Not applicable.

Notes

  1. As far as the case of predicting artefacts’ performances is concerned, which I shall not address in what follows, digital twins should be especially considered (see at least Glaessgen and Stargel 2012 and Grieves 2014 as seminal publications).

  2. As far as technological development’s increasing focus on prediction is concerned, see at least Siegel 2012 (also offering a rather exhaustive list of instructive cases in point), Agrawal et al. 2018 and 2022, Tulchinsky 2022 and Tulchinsky and Mason 2023.

  3. As representatives of the philosophical debate of the last decades.

  4. I extensively worked on the relationship between nonprofessionals and epistemic validity in Chiodo 2020.

  5. See at least the following websites as instructive cases in point: https://www.death-clock.org/, http://www.deathclock.com/, https://thedeathclock.co/ and https://www.medindia.net/patients/calculators/death_clock.asp.

  6. Even the title of Mary Shelley’s novel is literally Frankenstein, or, the modern Prometheus.

  7. “And the Lord God commanded the man, ‘You are free to eat from any tree in the garden; but you must not eat from the tree of the knowledge of good and evil, for when you eat from it you will certainly die’”.

  8. “Only Tiresias, on whose cheek the down was just darkening, still ranged with his hounds the holy place. And, athirst beyond telling, he came unto the flowing fountain, wretched man! And unwillingly saw that which is not lawful to be seen. And Athena was angered, yet said to him: ‘What god, o son of Everes, led thee on this grievous way? Hence shalt thou never more take back thine eyes!’”.

  9. “I [Socrates] am wiser than this man [considered wisest]; for neither of us really knows anything fine and good, but this man thinks he knows something when he does not, whereas I, as I do not know anything, do not think I do either”.

  10. “Human reason has the peculiar fate in one species of its cognitions that it is burdened with questions which it cannot dismiss, since they are given to it as problems by the nature of reason itself, but which it also cannot answer, since they transcend every capacity of human reason”.

  11. “Philosophy sets limits to […] what can be thought; and, in doing so, to what cannot be thought. It must set limits to what cannot be thought by working outwards through what can be thought”.

  12. Rousseau (1997 [1761], 578) lingers on details: “the use she made of her last moments, her words, her sentiments, her soul, all that belongs to Julie alone. She did not live like other women: no one, so far as I know, has died as she did. […] an instant. Without attributing great importance to her illness, she foresaw that it would prevent her for some time from fulfilling her share of that same care, and instructed us all to divide up that share in addition to our own. She expatiated on all her plans, on yours, on the means most apt to bring them to fruition, on the observations she had made and which could favour or thwart them, in short on everything that would enable us to compensate for her maternal functions for as long as she were obliged to suspend them”.

  13. In the case of Germany (the case of Spain is also tested). Note that 8.2% are uncertain (see Gigerenzer and Garcia-Retamero 2017, 186).

  14. In the case of Germany (the case of Spain is also tested). Note that 6.4% are uncertain (see Gigerenzer and Garcia-Retamero 2017, 186).

  15. As far as the relationship between shame and identity is concerned, Williams 1993 is illuminating.

  16. I extensively worked on trading human autonomy for technological automation in Chiodo 2023a and 2023b.

  17. As far as sensemaking is concerned, I mean what is generally described as what starts with a rationalisation of one’s actions (see, for instance, Weick, Sutcliffe and Obstfeld 2005). Other references may be considered to further reflect on the contemporary notion of sensemaking (even though the length of the article necessarily limits my possibility to develop them in what follows), especially at the intersection between phenomenology and cognitive sciences, starting with enactivism’s contributions (see, for instance, Durt et al. 2017, Vörös 2017, Di Paolo 2021 and Marin 2022). Also, contributions that may be complementary to the rationalisation on one’s actions proposed by Weick, Sutcliffe and Obstfeld 2005 can be found in Solomon 1993, as far as the relationship between sensemaking and emotions is concerned, and in Andersen et al. 2020, as far as the relationship between sensemaking and social sciences is concerned.

  18. On the general issue of achievement subjectivity, see at least Han 2015.

References

  • Aeschylus (1926) Prometheus bound (PB). Harvard University Press, Cambridge (Translated by H.W. Smith)

    Google Scholar 

  • Agrawal A, Gans J, Goldfarb A (2018) Prediction machines The simple economics of artificial intelligence. Harvard Business Review Press, Boston

    Google Scholar 

  • Agarwal A, Alomar A, Shah D (2020) TspDB. Time series predict DB. Proc Mach Learn Res 1:1–31

    Google Scholar 

  • Agrawal A, Gans J, Goldfarb A (2022) Power and prediction. The disruptive economics of artificial intelligence. Harvard Business Review Press, Boston

    Google Scholar 

  • Andersen D, Ravn S, Thomson R (2020) Narrative sense-making and prospective social action. Methodological challenges and new directions. Int J Soc Res Methodol 23(4):367–375

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Belsky DW et al (2020) Quantification of the pace of biological aging in humans through a blood test, the DunedinPoAm DNA methylation algorithm. eLife 9:1–25

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bradley B (2009) Well-being and death. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Bradley B, Feldman F, Johansson J (eds) (2013) The Oxford handbook of philosophy of death. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Buck RC (1963) Reflexive predictions. Philos Sci 30(4):359–369

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Callimachus (1921). In: Mair AW (ed) Hymn to Athena. Heinemann-G.P. Putnam’s sons, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Cawthon RM et al (2003) Association between telomere length in blood and mortality in people aged 60 years or older. The Lancet 9355(361):393–395

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chen BH et al (2016) DNA methylation-based measures of biological age: meta-analysis predicting time to death. Aging 9(8):1844–1865

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chiodo S (2020) Technology and anarchy. A reading of our era. Lexington Books-The Rowman & Littlefield Publishing Group, Lanham-Boulder-New York-London

    Google Scholar 

  • Chiodo S (2023a) Technology and the overturning of human autonomy. Springer, Cham

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Chiodo S (2023b) Trading human autonomy for technological automation. In: Lindgren S (ed) Handbook of critical studies of artificial intelligence. Edward Elgar Publishers, Cheltenham, pp 67–78

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Cholbi M (ed) (2015) Immortality and the philosophy of death. Rowman and Littlefield, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Corbyn Z (2022) “Morgan Levine: ‘Only 10–30& of our lifespan is estimated to be due to genetics’”, The guardian, https://www.theguardian.com/science/2022/may/07/morgan-levine-only-10-30-of-our-lifespan-is-estimated-to-be-due-to-genetics. Accessed 8 May 2023

  • Di Paolo EA (2021) Enactive becoming. Phenomenol Cogn Sci 20:783–809

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dougherty C (2006) Prometheus. Taylor & Francis, London

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Durt C, Fuchs T, Tewes C (2017) Embodiment, enaction, and culture. Investigating the constitution of the shared world. The MIT Press, Cambridge

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Eiriksdottir T et al (2021) Predicting the probability of death using proteomics. Commun Biol 758(4):1–11

    Google Scholar 

  • Feldman F (1992) Confrontations with the reaper. Oxford University Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Fischer JM (ed) (1993) The metaphysics of death. Stanford University Press, Stanford

    Google Scholar 

  • Fischer JM (2020) Death, immortality, and meaning in life. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Fischer K et al (2014) Biomarker profiling by nuclear magnetic resonance spectroscopy for the prediction of all-cause mortality. An observational study of 17.345 persons. PLoS Med 11(2):1–12

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Foreman KJ et al (2018) Forecasting life expectancy, years of life lost, and all-cause and cause-specific mortality for 250 causes of death. Reference and alternative scenarios for 2016–40 for 195 countries and territories. Lancet 10159(392):2052–2090

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gaille M et al (2020) Ethical and social implications of approaching death prediction in humans. When the biology of ageing meets existential issues. BMC Med Ethics 64(21):1–13

    Google Scholar 

  • Gao X et al (2019) Comparative validation of an epigenetic mortality risk score with three aging biomarkers for predicting mortality risks among older adult males. Int J Epidemiol 48(6):1958–1971

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gartziou-Tatti A (2010) Blindness as punishment. In: Christopoulos M, Karakantza E, Levaniouk O (eds) Light and darkness in ancient Greek myth and religion. Lexington Books, Lanham

    Google Scholar 

  • Gigerenzer G, Garcia-Retamero R (2017) Cassandra’s regret. The psychology of not wanting to know. Psychol Rev 124(2):179–196

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Glaessgen E, Stargel D (2012) “The digital twin paradigm for future NASA and US Air Force vehicles”, in 53rd AIAA/ASME/ASCE/AHS/ASC structures, structural dynamics and materials conference, American Institute of Aeronautics and Astronautics, 1–14

  • Grieves M (2014) Digital twin. Manufacturing excellence through virtual factory replication. NASA, Washington

    Google Scholar 

  • Hamzelou J (2022) Aging clocks aim to predict how long you’ll live. MIT Technol Rev 125(4):14–15

    Google Scholar 

  • Han B-C (2015) The burnout society. Stanford University Press, Stanford (Translated by E. Butler)

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Horvath S (2013) DNA methylation age of human tissues and cell types. Genome Biol 14:2–19

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Horvath S, Raj K (2018) DNA methylation-based biomarkers and the epigenetic clock theory of ageing. Nat Rev Genet 19:371–384

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kagan S (2012) Death. Yale University Press, New Haven

    Google Scholar 

  • Kahn AD (1970) Every art possessed by man comes from Prometheus. The Greek tragedians and science and technology. Technol Cult 11(2):133–162

    Google Scholar 

  • Kamm FM (2021) Almost over. Aging, dying, dead. Oxford University Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Kant I (1988, 1781) In: Guyer P, Wood A (eds) Critique of pure reason. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge-New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Levine ME (2013) Modelling the rate of senescence. Can estimated biological age predict mortality more accurately than chronological age? J Gerontol 68(6):667–674

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Levine ME et al (2018) An epigenetic biomarker of aging for lifespan and healthspan. Aging 10(4):573–591

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lin Q et al (2016) DNA methylation levels at individual age-associated CpG sites can be indicative for life expectancy. Aging 8(2):394–401

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Luper S (2009) The philosophy of death. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Luper S (ed) (2014) The Cambridge companion to life and death. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Marin L (2022) Enactive principles for the ethics of user interactions on social media. How to overcome systematic misunderstandings through shared meaning-making. Topoi 41:425–437

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Marioni RE et al (2015) DNA methylation age of blood predicts all-cause mortality in later life. Genome Biol 25(1):1–12

    MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  • Merton RK (1948) The self-fulfilling prophecy. Antioch Rev 8(2):193–210

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nietzsche F (2001) In: Williams B (ed) The gay science. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Overall C (2003) Aging, death, and human longevity. A philosophical inquiry. University of California Press, Berkeley

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Peters MJ et al (2015) The transcriptional landscape of age in human peripheral blood. Nat Commun 6:1–14

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pirracchio R et al (2015) Mortality prediction in intensive care units with the super ICU learner algorithm (SICULA). A population-based study. Lancet Respir Med 3(1):42–52

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Plato (1966) In: Fowler HN (ed) Apology. Harvard University Press-Heinemann, Cambridge-London

    Google Scholar 

  • Popper K (1957) The poverty of historicism. Routledge, London-New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Robbins R (2017) “This company wants to analyse your saliva—try to predict when you’ll die”, Stat, https://www.statnews.com/2017/03/13/insurance-dna-death-prediction/. Accessed 8 May 2023

  • Robins Wahlin TB (2007) To know or not to know. A review of behaviour and suicidal ideation in preclinical Huntington’s disease. Patient Educ Couns 65(3):279–287

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Romanos GD (1973) Reflexive predictions. Philos Sci 40(1):97–109

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rousseau JJ (1997, 1761) Julie, or, the new Heloise. Letters of two lovers who live in a small town at the foot of the Alps, translated by P. Stewart and J. Vaché, Hanover: University Press of New England

  • Sanders JL, Newman AB (2013) Telomere length in epidemiology. A biomarker of aging, age-related disease, both, or neither? Epidemiol Rev 35(1):112–131

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sanders J et al (2012) Understanding the aging process using epidemiologic approaches. In: Newman A, Cauley J (eds) The epidemiology of aging. Springer, Dordrecht, pp 187–214

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Schumacher B (2010) Death and mortality in contemporary philosophy. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Shakespeare W (2013, 1623) The tragedy of Macbeth (Mac.), edited by B.A. Mowat and P. Werstine, New York: Folger Shakespeare Library

  • Shelley M (1994, 1818 and 1831) Frankenstein, or, the modern Prometheus. Penguin Books, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Siegel E (2012) Predictive analytics. The power to predict who will click, buy, lie, or die. Wiley, Hoboken

    Google Scholar 

  • Solomon RC (1993) The passion. Emotions and the meaning of life. Hackettm, Indianapolis

    Google Scholar 

  • Sophocles (1887) In: Jebb R (ed) Oedipus tyrannus (OT). Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Taylor JS (ed) (2013) The metaphysics and ethics of death. New essays. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • The holy bible (1983) New international version. New York International Bible Society, East Brunswick

    Google Scholar 

  • Tulchinsky I (2022) The age of prediction. How data and technology are driving exponential change, World Economic Forum, Davos, https://www.weforum.org/agenda/2022/05/age-of-prediction/. Accessed 8 May 2023

  • Tulchinsky I, Mason CE (2023) The age of prediction. Algorithms, AI, and the shifting shadows of risk. The MIT Press, Cambridge

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Vörös S (2017) Wrestling with the absurd. Enaction meets non-sense. J Mind Behav 38(2):155–165

    Google Scholar 

  • Weick K, Sutcliffe KM, Obstfeld D (2005) Organizing and the process of sensemaking. Organ Sci 16(4):409–421

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Williams B (1973) Problems of the self. Philosophical papers 1956–1972. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Williams B (1993) Shame and necessity. University of California Press, Berkeley

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Wittgenstein L (1963, 1921) In: Pears D, McGuinness B (eds) Tractatus logico-philosophicus. Routledge and Kegan Paul, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Zewe A (2022) “A tool for predicting the future. Researchers design a user-friendly interface that helps nonexperts make forecasts using data collected over time, MIT news. https://news.mit.edu/2022/tensor-predicting-future-0328. Accessed 8 May 2023

  • Zhang Y et al (2017) DNA methylation signatures in peripheral blood strongly predict all-cause mortality. Nat Commun 8:1–11

    Google Scholar 

  • Zhavoronkov A et al (2019) Artificial intelligence for aging and longevity research. Recent advances and perspectives. Ageing Res Rev 49:49–66

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Curmudgeon Corner

Curmudgeon Corner is a short opinionated column on trends in technology, arts, science and society, commenting on issues of concern to the research community and wider society. Whilst the drive for super-human intelligence promotes potential benefits to wider society, it also raises deep concerns of existential risk, thereby highlighting the need for an ongoing conversation between technology and society. At the core of Curmudgeon concern is the question: What is it to be human in the age of the AI machine? -Editor.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Simona Chiodo.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Springer Nature or its licensor (e.g. a society or other partner) holds exclusive rights to this article under a publishing agreement with the author(s) or other rightsholder(s); author self-archiving of the accepted manuscript version of this article is solely governed by the terms of such publishing agreement and applicable law.

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Chiodo, S. From Phoebus to witches to death clocks: why we are taking predictive technologies to the extreme. AI & Soc (2024). https://doi.org/10.1007/s00146-023-01821-y

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s00146-023-01821-y

Keywords

Navigation