skip to main content
article

Accelerating Turing Machines

Published:01 May 2002Publication History
Skip Abstract Section

Abstract

Accelerating Turing machines are Turing machines of a sort able to perform tasks that are commonly regarded as impossible for Turing machines. For example, they can determine whether or not the decimal representation of π contains n consecutive 7s, for any n; solve the Turing-machine halting problem; and decide the predicate calculus. Are accelerating Turing machines, then, logically impossible devices? I argue that they are not. There are implications concerning the nature of effective procedures and the theoretical limits of computability. Contrary to a recent paper by Bringsjord, Bello and Ferrucci, however, the concept of an accelerating Turing machine cannot be used to shove up Searle's Chinese room argument.

References

  1. Ambrose, A. (1935), 'Finitism in Mathematics (I and II)', Mind 35, pp. 186-203, pp. 317-340.Google ScholarGoogle ScholarCross RefCross Ref
  2. Benacerraf, P. (1962), 'Tasks, Super-Tasks, and the Modern Eleatics', Journal of Philosophy 59, pp. 765-784.Google ScholarGoogle ScholarCross RefCross Ref
  3. Black, M. (1951), 'Achilles and the Tortoise', Analysis 11, pp. 91-101.Google ScholarGoogle ScholarCross RefCross Ref
  4. Blake, R.M. (1926), 'The Paradox of Temporal Process', Journal of Philosophy 23, pp. 645-654.Google ScholarGoogle ScholarCross RefCross Ref
  5. Boolos, G.S., Jeffrey, R.C. (1980), Computability and Logic, 2nd edition, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Google ScholarGoogle ScholarDigital LibraryDigital Library
  6. Bringsjord, S., Bello, P. and Ferrucci, D. (2001), 'Creativity, the Turing Test, and the (Better) Lovelace Test', Minds and Machines 11, pp. 3-27. Google ScholarGoogle ScholarDigital LibraryDigital Library
  7. Chihara, C.S. (1965), 'On the Possibility of Completing an Infinite Process', Philosophical Review 74, pp. 74-87.Google ScholarGoogle ScholarCross RefCross Ref
  8. Church, A. (1936), 'A Note on the Entscheidungsproblem', Journal of Symbolic Logic 1, pp. 40-41.Google ScholarGoogle ScholarCross RefCross Ref
  9. Cleland, C.E. (1993), 'Is the Church-Turing Thesis True?', Minds and Machines 3, pp. 283-312.Google ScholarGoogle ScholarCross RefCross Ref
  10. Cleland, C.E. (1995), 'Effective Procedures and Computable Functions', Minds and Machines 5, pp. 9-23.Google ScholarGoogle ScholarCross RefCross Ref
  11. Copeland, B.J. (1997), 'The Broad Conception of Computation', American Behavioral Scientist 40, pp. 690-716.Google ScholarGoogle ScholarCross RefCross Ref
  12. Copeland, B.J. (1998a), Turing's O-machines, Penrose, Searle, and the Brain', Analysis 58, pp. 128- 138.Google ScholarGoogle ScholarCross RefCross Ref
  13. Copeland, B.J. (1998b), 'Even Turing Machines Can Compute Uncomputable Functions', in C. Calude, J. Casti, and M. Dinneen, eds., Unconventional Models of Computation, London: Springer-Verlag, pp. 150-164.Google ScholarGoogle Scholar
  14. Copeland, B.J. (1998c), 'Super Turing-Machines', Complexity 4, pp. 30-32. Google ScholarGoogle ScholarDigital LibraryDigital Library
  15. Copeland, BJ. (2000), 'Narrow Versus Wide Mechanism', Journal of Philosophy 96, pp. 5-32.Google ScholarGoogle Scholar
  16. Copeland, B.J. and Hamkins, J.D. (in preparation), 'Infinitely Fast Computation'.Google ScholarGoogle Scholar
  17. Copeland, B.J. and Proudfoot, D. (1996), 'On Alan Turing's Anticipation of Connectionism', Synthese 108: pp. 361-377.Google ScholarGoogle ScholarCross RefCross Ref
  18. Copeland, B.J. and Proudfoot, D. (1999), 'Alan Turing's Forgotten Ideas in Computer Science', Scientific American 280 (April), pp. 76-81.Google ScholarGoogle ScholarCross RefCross Ref
  19. Copeland, B.J. and Sylvan, R. (1999), 'Beyond the Universal Turing Machine', Australasian Journal of Philosophy 77, pp. 46-66.Google ScholarGoogle ScholarCross RefCross Ref
  20. Earman, J. (1986), A Primer on Determinism, Dordrecht: Reidel.Google ScholarGoogle Scholar
  21. Earman, J. and Norton, J.D. (1993), 'Forever Is a Day: Supertasks in Pitowsky and Malament-Hogarth Spacetimes', Philosophy of Science 60, pp. 22-42.Google ScholarGoogle ScholarCross RefCross Ref
  22. Earman, J. and Norton, J.D. (1996), 'Infinite Pains: The Trouble with Supertasks', in A. Morton and S.P. Stich, eds., Benacerraf and his Critics, Oxford: Blackwell.Google ScholarGoogle Scholar
  23. Geroch, R. (1977), 'Prediction in General Relativity', in J. Earman, C. Glymour and J. Stachel, eds., Foundations of Space-Time Theories, Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science, 8, Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.Google ScholarGoogle Scholar
  24. Gold, E.M. (1965), 'Limiting Recursion', Journal of Symbolic Logic 30, pp. 28-48.Google ScholarGoogle ScholarCross RefCross Ref
  25. Grünbaum, A. (1968), Modern Science and Zeno's Paradoxes, London: Allen and Unwin.Google ScholarGoogle Scholar
  26. Hamkins, J.D. and Lewis, A. (2000), 'Infinite Time Turing Machines', Journal of Symbolic Logic 65, pp. 567-604. Google ScholarGoogle ScholarDigital LibraryDigital Library
  27. Hilbert, D. and Ackermann, W. (1928), Grundziige der Theoretischen Logik, Berlin: Springer.Google ScholarGoogle Scholar
  28. Hinton, J.M and Martin, C.B. (1954), 'Achilles and the Tortoise', Analysis 14, pp. 56-68.Google ScholarGoogle ScholarCross RefCross Ref
  29. Hofstadter, D.R. (1980), Gödel, Escher, Bach: An Eternal Golden Braid, Harmondsworth: Penguin. Google ScholarGoogle ScholarDigital LibraryDigital Library
  30. Hogarth, M.L. (1992), 'Does General Relativity Allow an Observer to View an Eternity in a Finite Time?', Foundations of Physics Letters 5, pp. 173-181.Google ScholarGoogle ScholarCross RefCross Ref
  31. Hogarth, M.L. (1994), 'Non-Turing Computers and Non-Turing Computability', PSA 1994 1, pp. 126-138.Google ScholarGoogle ScholarCross RefCross Ref
  32. McCulloch, W.S., and Pitts, W. (1943), 'A Logical Calculus of the Ideas Immanent in Nervous Activity', Bulletin of Mathematical Biophysics 5, pp. 115-33.Google ScholarGoogle ScholarCross RefCross Ref
  33. Minsky, M.L. (1967), Computation: Finite and Infinite Machines, Englewood Cliffs, NJ.: Prentice-Hall. Google ScholarGoogle ScholarDigital LibraryDigital Library
  34. Post, E.L. (1936), 'Finite Combinatory Processes- Formulation 1', Journal of Symbolic Logic 1, pp. 103-105.Google ScholarGoogle ScholarCross RefCross Ref
  35. Putnam, H. (1965), 'Trial and Error Predicates and the Solution of a Problem of Mostowski', Journal of Symbolic Logic 30, pp. 49-57.Google ScholarGoogle ScholarCross RefCross Ref
  36. Russell, B.A.W. (1915), Our Knowledge of the External World as a Field for Scientific Method in Philosophy, Chicago: Open Court.Google ScholarGoogle Scholar
  37. Russell, B.A.W. (1936), 'The Limits of Empiricism', Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 36, pp. 131-150.Google ScholarGoogle ScholarCross RefCross Ref
  38. Searle, J. (1980), 'Minds, Brains, and Programs', Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3, pp. 417-424, 450-456.Google ScholarGoogle ScholarCross RefCross Ref
  39. Searle, J. (1989), Minds, Brains and Science, London: Penguin.Google ScholarGoogle Scholar
  40. Searle, J. (1990), 'Is the Brain's Mind a Computer Program?' Scientific American 262(1), pp. 20-25.Google ScholarGoogle ScholarCross RefCross Ref
  41. Searle, J. (1992), The Rediscovery of the Mind, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Google ScholarGoogle ScholarDigital LibraryDigital Library
  42. Sorensen, R. (1999), 'Mirror Notation: Symbol Manipulation without Inscription Manipulation', Journal of Philosophical Logic 28, pp. 141-164.Google ScholarGoogle ScholarCross RefCross Ref
  43. Stewart, I. (1991), 'Deciding the Undecidable', Nature 352, pp. 664-665.Google ScholarGoogle ScholarCross RefCross Ref
  44. Taylor, R. (1951), 'Mr. Black on Temporal Paradoxes', Analysis 12, pp. 38-44.Google ScholarGoogle ScholarCross RefCross Ref
  45. Thomson, J.F. (1954), 'Tasks and Super-Tasks', Analysis 15, pp. 1-13.Google ScholarGoogle ScholarCross RefCross Ref
  46. Thomson, J.F. (1970), 'Comments on Professor Benacerraf's Paper', in W.C. Salmon, ed., Zeno's Paradoxes, Indianapolis: Bobbs-Merrill.Google ScholarGoogle Scholar
  47. Turing, A.M. (1936), 'On Computable Numbers, with an Application to the Entscheidungsproblem', Proceedings of the London Mathematical Society, Series 2, 42 (1936-37), pp. 230-265.Google ScholarGoogle Scholar
  48. Turing, A.M. (1938), 'Systems of Logic Based on Ordinals'. Dissertation presented to the faculty of Princeton University in candidacy for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy. Published in Proceedings of the London Mathematical Society 45 (1939), pp. 161-228.Google ScholarGoogle Scholar
  49. Turing, A.M. (1948), 'Intelligent Machinery', National Physical Laboratory Report, in B. Meltzer and D. Michie, eds., Machine Intelligence 5, Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press. A digital facsimile of the original document may be viewed in The Turing Archive for the History of Computing. ¿http://www.AlanTuring.net/intelligent_machinery¿.Google ScholarGoogle Scholar
  50. Turing, A.M. (1950), 'Programmers' Handbook for Manchester Electronic Computer', University of Manchester Computing Laboratory. A digital facsimile of the original may be viewed in The Turing Archive for the History of Computing document. ¿http://www.AlanTuring.net/programmers_handbook¿.Google ScholarGoogle Scholar
  51. Watling, J. (1952), 'The Sum of an Infinite Series', Analysis 13, pp. 39-46.Google ScholarGoogle ScholarCross RefCross Ref
  52. Weyl, H. (1927), Philosophie der Mathematik und Naturwissenschaft, Munich: R. Oldenbourg.Google ScholarGoogle Scholar
  53. Weyl, H. (1949), Philosophy of Mathematics and Natural Science, Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google ScholarGoogle Scholar

Index Terms

  1. Accelerating Turing Machines

      Recommendations

      Comments

      Login options

      Check if you have access through your login credentials or your institution to get full access on this article.

      Sign in

      Full Access