Skip to main content

Advertisement

Log in

Criminalising Anti-Social Behaviour

  • Original Paper
  • Published:
Criminal Law and Philosophy Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

This paper considers the justifiability of criminalising anti-social behaviour through two-step prohibitions such as the Anti-Social Behaviour Order (ASBO). The UK government has recently proposed to abolish and replace the ASBO; however, the proposed new orders would retain many of its most controversial features. The paper begins by criticising the definition of anti-social behaviour employed in both the current legislation and the new proposals. This definition is objectionable because it makes criminalisation contingent upon the irrational judgements of (putative) victims, and its often modest preventive benefits come at a high cost to citizens’ liberty and autonomy. The paper then goes on to propose a new definition of anti-social behaviour that would meet these objections: that is, as a course of conduct that causes others to experience serious and justifiable anxiety about the safety of their local community. Whilst this definition identifies a serious form of wrongdoing, its precise scope is inevitably uncertain. The paper thus concludes that we have good reason to use two-step prohibitions such as the ASBO to regulate such conduct, so as to enable the use of the criminal law against it whilst minimising possible concerns of legality arising from the proposed definition’s uncertain scope.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Some behaviour that causes harassment, alarm or distress to others constitutes an offence under the Public Order Act 1986, s. 5. However, for the purposes of this offence, it must be shown that the defendant intended his behaviour to be, or was reckless as to his behaviour being, ‘threatening, abusive or insulting’: s. 6(4). The definition of anti-social behaviour, by contrast, has no such mens rea requirement.

  2. This paper concerns only these latter, principled criticisms. For an in-depth critique of anti-social behaviour legislation and policy from a socio-legal perspective, see Burney (2009).

  3. Numerous prominent commentators have criticised the ASBO and other two-step orders on these or similar grounds: see e.g. Ashworth (2004), Ashworth and Zedner (2010), Gardner et al. (1998), Simester and von Hirsch (2011, ch. 12), von Hirsch et al. (1995).

  4. For a survey, see Husak (2008, pp. 58–61). More recent entries include the various contributions to Duff et al. (2010) and Simester and von Hirsch (2011).

  5. Husak argues that this constraint is also implied by the doctrines of the general part of the criminal law itself: (2008, pp. 72–76).

  6. Some strict retributivists disagree, holding that moral wrongness alone provides the only principled constraint on, as well as the only valid positive reason for, criminalisation, and that the state is obliged to create institutions that aim to punish the morally deserving: see e.g. Moore (1997, chs. 2–4).

  7. The seminal philosophical treatments of the harm principle are those of Mill (1859) and Feinberg (1984). There are well-documented problems with the harm principle as a way of constraining the scope of the criminal law, which I will not dwell on here: see Duff (2007, ch. 6).

  8. The word ‘offence’ in this context is usually understood to refer to negative mental states generally, rather than to its ordinary-language synonyms such as ‘affront’ and ‘disgust’: see Feinberg (1985, p. 1).

  9. For clarity’s sake, assume that my abilities as a pilot are such that I would not physically endanger the passengers by performing this manoeuvre.

  10. In particular, see Thomson (1990, ch. 10.3).

  11. For further defence of the view that belief-mediation alone cannot explain why we ought not to treat negative feelings as we treat other kinds of harm, see Tadros (2011, pp. 39–42).

  12. Compare Feinberg (1985), who believed that the reasonableness of feelings should play no role in criminalisation decisions. Critics of Feinberg in this regard include Duff and Marshall (2006) and Simester and von Hirsch (2011).

  13. On the idea of criminal offences as presumptive wrongs for which the state may call us to answer, see Duff (2007, ch. 9).

  14. For further analysis of the role of the balance between liberty and security in criminalisation decisions, see Tadros (2008).

  15. On the importance of analysing the non-ideal effects of a prohibition in criminalisation decisions, see Schonsheck (1994, pp. 70–79), Tadros (2008, pp. 949–951).

  16. For an alternative kind of approach, which aims to rationalise anti-social behaviour legislation and policy in its current form, see Ramsay (2004, 2008).

  17. I use ‘threat’ here in its broadest sense, to refer to the possibility of any unwelcome state of affairs.

  18. For example, many of the most serious cases of anti-social behaviour involve ‘nuisance neighbours’. Whilst such cases are comparatively rare, they are much more likely than cases of other kinds to have a high impact on the quality of the lives of their victims: see Millie (2009, pp. 23–25). The explanation for this is, presumably, that such behaviour is more likely to inhibit victims’ peaceful enjoyment of their home lives.

  19. This insight—that wellbeing is significantly related to the extent to which some spheres of our lives are accessible to others—is sometimes thought to be the foundation of a right to privacy: see e.g. Gavison (1980).

  20. Typologies of anti-social behaviour have evolved in a way that reflects this. Most now include such categories as misuse of public space and ‘environmental’ damage alongside the previously familiar categories of neighbour disputes and direct intimidation: see e.g. Donoghue (2010, pp. 18–23), Millie (2009, pp. 11–13).

  21. See Protection from Harassment Act 1997 ss 1, 2 and 4.

  22. In this respect, I concur with James Q Wilson and George Kelling’s ‘broken windows’ theory of neighbourhood disorder: see Wilson and Kelling (1982). The UK experience seems to support this claim: perceptions of anti-social behaviour are higher in those neighbourhoods with high levels of ‘physical disorder’ (Flatley et al. 2010, p. 117). However, this claim should be distinguished from Wilson and Kelling’s more controversial hypothesis that the prevalence of these kinds of behaviour in a given neighbourhood in fact tends to lead to more serious crime occurring there. Contemporary criminology is generally against this idea: see Burney (2009, pp. 24–28) for a summary of the relevant literature.

  23. For an exploration of this idea, see Husak (2004).

  24. The idea that the wrongness of conduct provides a reason for, as well as a necessary condition of, criminalisation is a defining feature of what Duff calls ‘positive’ legal moralism: (2007, ch. 4.3).

  25. Noise Act 1996 ss. 3–5; Permitted Level of Noise (England) Directions 2008.

  26. Attorney-General v PYA Quarries Ltd [1957] 2 QB 169,184.

  27. For further reflection on the relative merits of concrete ‘rules’ and abstract ‘standards’ in criminal law, see Schlag (1985), Alexander and Ferzan (2009, ch. 8).

  28. For theoretical treatments of these requirements of the rule of law, see Fuller (1969, ch. 2), Raz (1979, ch. 11). On the importance of such requirements to justice more generally conceived, see Finnis (1980, pp. 270–273).

  29. For further development of this kind of criticism of two-step prohibitions, see Simester and von Hirsch (2011, pp. 219–220).

References

  • Alexander, L., & Ferzan, K. (2009). Crime and culpability. Cambridge: CUP.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ashworth, A. (2004). Social control and ‘anti-social behaviour’: The subversion of human rights? Law Quarterly Review, 120, 263–291.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ashworth, A., & Zedner, L. (2010). Preventive orders: A problem of under-criminalization? In R. A. Duff, et al. (Eds.), The boundaries of the criminal law (pp. 59–87). Oxford: OUP.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Burney, E. (2009). Making people behave: Anti-social behaviour, politics and policy (2nd ed.). Collumpton: Willan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Donoghue, J. (2010). Anti-social behaviour orders: A culture of control? Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Duff, R. A. (2007). Answering for crime. Oxford: Hart.

    Google Scholar 

  • Duff, R. A., & Marshall, S. E. (1998). Criminalization and sharing wrongs. Canadian Journal of Law and Jurisprudence, 11, 7–22.

    Google Scholar 

  • Duff, R. A., & Marshall, S. E. (2006). How offensive can you get? In A. von Hirsch & A. P. Simester (Eds.), Incivilities: Regulating offensive behaviour (pp. 57–90). Oxford: Hart.

    Google Scholar 

  • Duff, R. A., et al. (Eds.). (2010). The boundaries of the criminal law. Oxford: OUP.

    Google Scholar 

  • Feinberg, J. (1984). Harm to others. Oxford: OUP.

    Google Scholar 

  • Feinberg, J. (1985). Offense to others. Oxford: OUP.

    Google Scholar 

  • Finnis, J. (1980). Natural law and natural rights. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Flatley, J., et al. (Eds.). (2010). Crime in England and Wales 2009/10. London: Home Office.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fuller, L. (1969). The morality of law (2nd ed.). New Haven, CT: Yale University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gardner, J., et al. (1998). Neighbouring on the oppressive: The government’s ‘anti-social behaviour order’ proposals. Criminal Justice, 16, 7–14.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gavison, R. (1980). Privacy and the limits of law. Yale Law Journal, 89, 421–471.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Home Office. (2011). More effective responses to anti-social behaviour. London: Home Office.

    Google Scholar 

  • Husak, D. (2004). The criminal law as last resort. Oxford Journal of Legal Studies, 24, 207–235.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Husak, D. (2008). Overcriminalization: The limits of the criminal law. Oxford: OUP.

    Google Scholar 

  • Labour Party. (1995). A quiet life: Tough action on criminal neighbours. London: Labour Party.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lamond, G. (2007). What is a crime? Oxford Journal of Legal Studies, 27, 609–632.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Macdonald, S. (2006). A suicidal woman, roaming pigs and a noisy trampolinist: Refining the ASBO’s definition of ‘anti-social behaviour’. Modern Law Review, 69, 183–213.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • May, T. (2010). Moving beyond the ASBO. Speech available online. http://www.homeoffice.gov.uk/media-centre/speeches/beyond-the-asbo. Accessed September 2, 2011.

  • Mill, J. S. (1859). On liberty. London: Parker.

    Google Scholar 

  • Millie, A. (2009). Anti-social behaviour. Maidenhead: Open University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Moore, M. (1997). Placing blame: A general theory of the criminal law. Oxford: OUP.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ramsay, P. (2004). What is anti-social behaviour? Criminal Law Review, 908–925.

  • Ramsay, P. (2008). The theory of vulnerable autonomy and the legitimacy of the civil preventive order. In B. McSherry, A. Norrie, & S. Bronitt (Eds.), Regulating deviance: The redirection of criminalisation and the futures of criminal law (pp. 109–139). Oxford: Hart.

    Google Scholar 

  • Raz, J. (1979). The authority of law. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schlag, P. J. (1985). Rules and standards. UCLA Law Review, 33, 379–430.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schonsheck, J. (1994). On criminalization: An essay in the philosophy of criminal law. Dordrecht: Kluwer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Simester, A. P., & von Hirsch, A. (2002). Rethinking the offense principle. Legal Theory, 8, 269–295.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Simester, A. P., & von Hirsch, A. (2011). Crimes, harms and wrongs: On the principles of criminalisation. Oxford: Hart.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tadros, V. (2008). Crimes and security. Modern Law Review, 71, 940–970.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tadros, V. (2011). Harm, sovereignty and prohibition. Legal Theory, 17, 35–65.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Thomson, J. J. (1990). The realm of rights. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Von Hirsch, A. et al. (1995). Overtaking on the right. New Law Journal, 1501–1516.

  • Wilson, J. Q., & Kelling, G. L. (1982). Broken windows. Atlantic Monthly, 249, 28–38.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

I am grateful to Andrew Ashworth and Victor Tadros for their comments on earlier versions of this piece, and to an anonymous reviewer for the journal for some detailed and challenging suggestions.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Andrew Cornford.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Cornford, A. Criminalising Anti-Social Behaviour. Criminal Law, Philosophy 6, 1–19 (2012). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11572-011-9134-9

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11572-011-9134-9

Keywords

Navigation