Skip to main content
Log in

Is What is Worse More Likely?—The Probabilistic Explanation of the Epistemic Side-Effect Effect

  • Published:
Review of Philosophy and Psychology Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

One aim of this article is to explore the connection between the Knobe effect and the epistemic side-effect effect (ESEE). Additionally, we report evidence about a further generalization regarding probability judgments. We demonstrate that all effects can be found within German material, using ‘absichtlich’ [intentionally], ‘wissen’ [know] and ‘wahrscheinlich’ [likely]. As the explanations discussed with regard to the Knobe effect do not suffice to explicate the ESEE, we survey whether the characteristic asymmetry in knowledge judgments is caused by a differing perception of probabilities concerning the occurrence of the side-effects. Our findings show that a negative side-effect is judged more probable, even if the objective probabilities would suggest otherwise. We argue that the best explanation for these results is that the Knobe effect applies to the perception of probabilities as well: a probabilistic side-effect effect.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Fig. 1
Fig. 2
Fig. 3
Fig. 4
Fig. 5

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Mean = 28.66 SD = 9.92.

  2. Welch’s (1947) t-test: Intentionality: t(236.17) = −17.94, p < 0.001, d = 2.33. Knowledge: t(203.88) = −3.35, p < 0.001, d = 0.47.

  3. t(268) = −15.19, p < 0.001, d = 1.86.

  4. Welch’s t-test : Intentionality: t(256.96) = −12.95, p < 0.001, d = 1.62. Knowledge: t(235.11) = −3.13, p < 0.005, d = 0.41.

  5. Welch’s t-test: Profit story: t(229,83) = −4,75, p < 0.001, d = 0.63. Guideline story: t(224.97) = −2.974, p < 0.005, d = 0.40.

  6. Profit story: total effect: t(268) = 3.41, p < 0.001, direct effect: t(267) = 2, p < 0.05 indirect effect: 99 % C.I.: 0.87 – 8.82.

    Guideline story: total effect: t(268) = 3.17 p < 0.01 direct effect: t(267) = 2.49, p < 0.05 indirect effect: 99 % C.I. = 0.09 – 5.77.

  7. Profit story:

    Main effect: intentionality: F(1,269) = 0.14, p > 0.05; knowledge: F = 0.002, p > 0.05; specific probability: F = 0.87, p > 0.05.

    Interaction: intentionality: F(1,269) = 1.5, p > 0.05; knowledge: F = 1.01, p > 0.05; specific probability: F = 0.05, p > 0.05.

    Guideline story:

    Main effect: intentionality: F(1,269) = 0.4, p > 0.05; knowledge: F = 0.52, p > 0.05; specific probability: F = 0.35, p > 0.05.

    Interaction: intentionality: F(1,269) = 0.09, p > 0.05; knowledge: F = 0.72, p > 0.05; specific probability: F = 4, p > 0.05.

  8. Unfortunately Egré (2013) broad account cannot be elaborated here.

  9. Mean = 40.23 SD = 15.62.

  10. Film story:

    Main effect: intentionality: F(1,340) = 1.28, p > 0.05; knowledge: F = 0.07, p > 0.05; specific probability: F = 3.24, p > 0.05.

    Interaction: intentionality: F(1,340) = 0.81, p > 0.05; knowledge: F = 0.03, p > 0.05; specific probability: F < 0.01, p > 0.05.

    Reorganization story:

    Main effect: intentionality: F(1,340) = 0.6.91, p < 0.01; knowledge: F = 0.09, p > 0.05; specific probability: F = 0.87, p > 0.05.

    Interaction: intentionality: F(1,340) = 0.04, p > 0.05; knowledge: F = 0.04, p > 0.05; specific probability: F = 5.64, p = 0.018.

  11. Again, we used the Preacher and Hayes (2008) SPSS macro and calculated bias-corrected bootstrap confidence intervals based on 5000 bootstrap samples.

    Film story: total effect: t(339) = 6.43, p < 0.001, direct effect: t(338) = 5.75, p < 0.05 indirect effect: 99 % C.I.: 0.87 – 8.82.

    Reorganization story: total effect: t(339) = 3.17 p < 0.01 direct effect: t(338) = 2.49, p < 0.05 indirect effect: 99 % C.I. = 0.09 – 5.77.

References

  • Adams, F., and A. Steadman. 2004a. Intentional action in ordinary language: Core concept or pragmatic understanding? Analysis 64(2): 173–181.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Adams, F., and A. Steadman. 2004b. Intentional action and moral considerations: Still pragmatic. Analysis 64(3): 268–276.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Beebe, J.R., and W. Buckwalter. 2010. The epistemic side-effect effect. Mind and Language 25(4): 474–498.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Beebe, J.R., and M. Jensen. 2012. Surprising connections between knowledge and action: The robustness of the epistemic side-effect effect. Philosophical Psychology 25(5): 689–715.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Buckwalter, W., and S. Stich. 2013. Gender and philosophical intuition. In Experimental philosophy, vol. 2, ed. J. Knobe and S. Nichols. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cullen, S. 2010. Survey-driven romanticism. Review of Philosophy and Psychology 1(2): 275–296.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cushman, F., and A. Mele. 2008. Intentional action: Two-and-a-half folk concepts? In Experimental philosophy, ed. J. Knobe and S. Nichols, 171–188. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Deutsch, M. 2009. Experimental philosophy and the theory of reference. Mind and Language 24(4): 445–466.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Egré, P. 2010. Qualitative judgments, quantitative judgments, and norm-sensitivity. [Commentary on J. Knobe's "Person as Scientist, Person as Moralist"]. Brain and Behavioral Sciences 33(4): 335–336.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Egré, P. 2013. Intentional action and the semantics of gradable expressions (On the Knobe Effect). In Causation in grammatical structures, ed. B. Copley and F. Martin. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Feltz, A. 2007. The Knobe effect: A brief overview. The Journal of Mind and Behavior 28: 265–277.

    Google Scholar 

  • Guglielmo, S., and B.F. Malle. 2010. Can unintended side effects be intentional? resolving a controversy over intentionality and morality. Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin 36(12): 1635–1647.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hayes, A.F. 2009. Beyond Baron and Kenny: Statistical mediation analysis in the new millennium. Communication Monographs 76: 408–420.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Knobe, J. 2003. Intentional action and side-effects in ordinary language. Analysis 63(3): 190–193.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Knobe, J. 2004a. Folk psychology and folk morality: Response to critics. Journal of Theoretical and Philosophical Psychology 24(2): 270–279.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Knobe, J. 2004b. Intention, intentional action and moral considerations. Analysis 64(2): 181–187.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Knobe, J., and G. Mendlow. 2004. The good, the bad, and the blameworthy: Understanding the role of evaluative reasoning in folk psychology. Journal of Theoretical and Philosophical Psychology 24(2): 252–258.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Knobe, J., and A. Burra. 2006. The folk concepts of intention and intentional action: A cross-cultural study. Journal of Cognition and Culture 6(1–2):113–132.

    Google Scholar 

  • Knobe, J., W. Buckwalter, P. Robbins, H. Sarkissian, T. Sommers, and S. Nichols. 2012. Experimental philosophy. Annual Review of Psychology 63(50): 72–73.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lane, J.D., H.M. Wellman, S.L. Olson, J. LaBounty, and D.C.R. Kerr. 2010. Theory of mind and emotion understanding predict moral development in early childhood. British Journal of Developmental Psychology 28: 871–889.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lanteri, A. 2012. Three-and-a-half folk concepts of intentional action. Philosophical Studies 158(1): 17–30.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Leslie, A., J. Knobe, and A. Cohen. 2006. Acting intentionally and the side-effect effect: “Theory of mind” and moral judgment. Psychological Science 17: 421–427.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Machery, E., R. Mallon, S. Nichols, and S. Stich. 2004. Semantics, cross-cultural style. Cognition 92(3): B1–B12.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Machery, E., R. Mallon, S. Nichols, and S. Stich. 2012. If folk intuitions vary, then what? Philosophy and Phenomenological Research. doi:10.1111/j.1933-1592.2011.00555.x.

    Google Scholar 

  • Machery, E., C.Y. Olivola, and M. De Blanc. 2009. Linguistic and metalinguistic intuitions in the philosophy of language. Analysis 69(4): 689–694.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mallon, R., E. Machery, S. Nichols, and S. Stich. 2009. Against arguments from reference. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 79(2): 332–356.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Marti, G. 2009. Against semantic multiculturalism. Analysis 69(1): 42–48.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McCann, H.J. 2005. Intentional action and intending: Recent empirical studies. Philosophical Psychology 18(6): 737–748.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mele, A. 1992. Recent work on intentional action. American Philosophical Quarterly 29(3): 199–217.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mele, A. (ed.). 1997. The philosophy of action. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Michelin, C., S. Pellizzoni, M.A. Tallandini, and M. Siegal. 2010. Evidence for the side-effect effect in young children: Influence of bilingualism and task presentation format. European Journal of Developmental Psychology 7(6): 641–652.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nadelhoffer, T. 2004. On praise, side effects, and folk ascriptions of intentionality. Journal of Theoretical and Philosophical Psychology 24(2): 196–213.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nagel, J. 2012. Intuitions and experiments: A defense of the case method in epistemology. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 85(3): 495–527.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nichols, S., and J. Ulatowski. 2007. Intuitions and individual differences: The Knobe effect revisited. Mind and Language 22(4): 346–365.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nichols, S., S. Stich, and J.M. Weinberg. 2003. Metaskepticism: Meditations in ethnoepistemology. In The skeptics, ed. S. Luper, 227–247. Aldershot (Hampshire): Ashgate.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pellizzoni, S., M. Siegal, and L. Surian. 2009. Foreknowledge, caring, and the side-effect effect in young children. Developmental Psychology 45(1): 289–295.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pettit, D., and J. Knobe. 2009. The pervasive impact of moral judgment. Mind and Language 24(5): 586–604.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pighin, S., J.-F. Bonnefon, and L. Savadori. 2011. Overcoming number numbness in prenatal risk communication. Prenatal Diagnosis 31(8): 809–813.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Preacher, K.J., and A.F. Hayes. 2008. Asymptotic and resampling strategies for assessing and comparing indirect effects in multiple mediator models. Behavior Research Methods 40: 879–891.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sripada, C.S. 2010. The deep self model and asymmetries in folk judgments about intentional action. Philosophical Studies 15(2): 159–176.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sripada, C.S., and S. Konrath. 2011. Telling more than we can know about intentional action. Mind and Language 26(3): 353–380.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stich, S., and W. Buckwalter. 2011. Gender and the philosophy club. The Philosopher's Magazine 52: 60–65.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sytsma, J., and J. Livengood. 2011. A new perspective concerning experiments on semantic intuitions. Australasian Journal of Philosophy 89(2): 315–332.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Turner, J. 2004. Folk intuitions, asymmetry, and intentional side effects. Journal of Theoretical and Philosophical Psychology 24(2): 214–219.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Uttich, K., and T. Lombrozo. 2010. Norms inform mental state ascriptions: A rational explanation for the side-effect effect. Cognition 116: 87–100.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Weinberg, J.M., S. Nichols, and S. Stich. 2001. Normativity and epistemic intuitions. Philosophical Topics 29(1–2): 429–460.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Welch, B.L. 1947. The generalization of “student’s” problem when several different population variances are involved. Biometrika 34(1–2): 28–35.

    Google Scholar 

  • Young, L., F. Cushman, R. Adolphs, D. Tranel, and M. Hauser. 2006. Does emotion mediate the effect of an action’s moral status on its intentional status? Neuropsychological evidence. Journal of Cognition and Culture 6: 265–78.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Nikolaus Dalbauer.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Dalbauer, N., Hergovich, A. Is What is Worse More Likely?—The Probabilistic Explanation of the Epistemic Side-Effect Effect. Rev.Phil.Psych. 4, 639–657 (2013). https://doi.org/10.1007/s13164-013-0156-1

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s13164-013-0156-1

Keywords

Navigation