Skip to main content
Log in

Aristotelian diagrams for semantic and syntactic consequence

  • Published:
Synthese Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Several authors have recently studied Aristotelian diagrams for various metatheoretical notions from logic, such as tautology, satisfiability, and the Aristotelian relations themselves. However, all these metalogical Aristotelian diagrams focus on the semantic (model-theoretical) perspective on logical consequence, thus ignoring the complementary, and equally important, syntactic (proof-theoretical) perspective. In this paper, I propose an explanation for this discrepancy, by arguing that the metalogical square of opposition for semantic consequence exhibits a natural analogy to the well-known square of opposition for the categorical statements from syllogistics, but that this analogy breaks down once we move from semantic to syntactic consequence. I then show that despite this difficulty, one can indeed construct metalogical Aristotelian diagrams from a syntactic perspective, which have their own, equally elegant characterization in terms of the categorical statements. Finally, I construct several metalogical Aristotelian diagrams that incorporate both semantic and syntactic consequence (and their interaction), and study how they are influenced by the underlying logical system’s soundness and/or completeness. All of this provides further support for the methodological/heuristic perspective on Aristotelian diagrams, which holds that the main use of these diagrams lies in facilitating analogies and comparisons between prima facie unrelated domains of investigation.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Fig. 1
Fig. 2
Fig. 3
Fig. 4
Fig. 5
Fig. 6
Fig. 7

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Diaconescu (2015) studies several metalogical Aristotelian diagrams for abstract (Tarski-style) consequence relations, which transcend the distinction between syntax and semantics. However, he does not deal with any Aristotelian diagrams for syntactic consequence in particular.

  2. Note that this argumentation for an analogy (between the metalogical notion of semantic consequence and the categorical statements from syllogistics) is itself perfectly in line with the methodological/heuristic perspective on Aristotelian diagrams.

  3. Throughout this paper I will make use of the well-known mnemonic vowels (A, I, E, O) for the categorical statements. These are the first two vowels from each of the Latin verb forms ‘affirmo’ and ‘nego’.

  4. The precise interpretation of the principle of existential import in syllogistics has been a matter of substantial scholarly debate (Parsons 2017), but this need not concern us here.

  5. In particular, these models can be first-order models, relational structures, etc. These details do not matter here.

  6. In particular, the system can be a Gentzen-style or a Fitch-style natural deduction system. Again, these details do not matter here. (Also see Footnote 5.).

  7. The problematic nature of this quantifier mismatch should not be exaggerated. Ultimately, \( \Gamma \,{ \vdash }\,\varphi \) and \( \Gamma \,{ \vdash }\,\neg \varphi \) are effectively contrary to each other, regardless of whether their definitions can be characterized as universal (A- and E-) statements. In the literature there exist other, object-logical examples of squares of opposition that exhibit a similar quantifier mismatch. For example, in the square of opposition for public announcement logic, the formulas <!p> q and <!p> \( \neg \) q are contrary to each other, although the semantics of these formulas involves an existential, rather than a universal quantification (over public announcements of p) (Demey 2012, 2017b).

  8. Thanks to an anonymous reviewer of Demey (2017a) for some useful discussion on this.

  9. Furthermore, Theorem 1 cannot be used to provide a definition of syntactic consequence, since that would clearly result in circularity: the theorem characterizes syntactic consequence in terms of MCS, and thus of consistency, but as we have seen in the beginning of Sect. 3, the latter notion is itself defined in terms of syntactic consequence.

  10. The sets \( \Gamma \) for which it does hold that \( \Gamma \,{ \vdash }\,\varphi \) or \( \Gamma \,{ \vdash }\,\neg \varphi \) for all \( \varphi \), are called deductively complete.

  11. Many logicians have a rather ‘asymmetric’ perspective on soundness and completeness: soundness is usually taken to be a kind of minimal criterion that has to be met by any serious candidate proof system, while failure of completeness is seen as much more tolerable. However, based on certain technical results on so-called Scott consequence relations, one can argue for a more ‘symmetric’ perspective, which treats soundness and completeness more on a par with each other (Scott 1971, 1974; Brown 2015). In particular, a logical system that is complete but not sound is deemed equally worthy of attention as a system that is sound but not complete. Thanks to an anonymous reviewer for some interesting remarks about this issue.

  12. Cf. Lenzen (2017, p. 11) for a typical example, and Smessaert and Demey (2014, pp. 530–531) for further discussion.

References

  • Beall, J. C., Brady, R. T., Hazen, A. P., Priest, G., & Restall, G. (2006). Relevant restricted quantification. Journal of Philosophical Logic, 35, 587–598.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Béziau, J.-Y. (2012). The power of the hexagon. Logica Universalis, 6, 1–43.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Béziau, J.-Y. (2013). The metalogical hexagon of opposition. Argumentos, 5, 111–122.

    Google Scholar 

  • Béziau, J.-Y. (2016). Disentangling contradiction from contrariety via incompatibility. Logica Universalis, 10, 157–170.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Béziau, J.-Y., & Payette, G. (2012). Preface. In J.-Y. Béziau & G. Payette (Eds.), The square of opposition. A general framework for cognition (pp. 9–22). Bern: Peter Lang.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brown, B. (2015). Stipulation and symmetrical consequence. In J.-Y. Béziau, M. Chakraborty, & S. Dutta (Eds.), New directions in paraconsistent logic (pp. 335–352). Berlin: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Chisholm, R. (1963). Supererogation and offence: A conceptual scheme for ethics. Ratio, 5, 1–14.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ciucci, D., Dubois, D., & Prade, H. (2014). The structure of opposition in rough set theory and formal concept analysis. Toward a bridge between the two settings. In C. Beierle & C. Meghini (Eds.), Foundations of information and knowledge systems (FoIKS 2014) (pp. 154–173). Berlin: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Ciucci, D., Dubois, D., & Prade, H. (2016). Structures of opposition induced by relations. The boolean and the gradual cases. Annals of Mathematics and Artificial Intelligence, 76, 351–373.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Demey, L. (2012). Structures of oppositions in public announcement logic. In J.-Y. Béziau & D. Jacquette (Eds.), Around and beyond the square of opposition (pp. 313–339). Berlin: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Demey, L. (2015). Interactively illustrating the context-sensitivity of aristotelian diagrams. In H. Christiansen, I. Stojanovic, & G. Papadopoulous (Eds.), Modeling and using context. Lecture Notes in Computer Science (Vol. 9405, pp. 331–345). Berlin: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Demey, L. (2017a). Using syllogistics to teach metalogic. Metaphilosophy, 48, 575–590.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Demey, L. (2017b). The logical geometry of Russell’s theory of definite descriptions. Unpublished manuscript.

  • Demey, L. (2018a). Aristotelian diagrams in the debate on future contingents. Sophia. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11841-017-0632-7

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Demey, L. (2018b). Metalogic, metalanguage, and logical geometry. Logique et Analyse.

  • Demey, L. (2018c). The role of Aristotelian diagrams in scientific communication. Talk delivered at the 8th Visual Learning Conference. Budapest.

  • Demey, L., & Smessaert, H. (2014). Logische geometrie en pragmatiek. In F. Van de Velde, H. Smessaert, F. Van Eynde, & S. Verbrugge (Eds.), Patroon en argument (pp. 553–564). Leuven: Leuven University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Demey, L., & Smessaert, H. (2016). Metalogical decorations of logical diagrams. Logica Universalis, 10, 233–292.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Demey, L., & Smessaert, H. (2018). Combinatorial bitstring semantics for arbitrary logical fragments. Journal of Philosophical Logic, 47, 325–363.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Diaconescu, R. (2015). The algebra of opposition (and universal logic interpretations). In A. Koslow & A. Buchsbaum (Eds.), The road to universal logic (pp. 127–143). Berlin: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dubois, D., Prade, H., & Rico, A. (2015). The cube of opposition. A structure underlying many knowledge representation formalisms. In Q. Yang & M. Wooldridge (Eds.), Proceedings of the twenty-fourth international joint conference on artificial intelligence (IJCAI 2015) (pp. 2933–2939). New York: AAAI Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hare, R. M. (1967). Some alleged differences between imperatives and indicatives. Mind, 76, 309–326.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hart, H. L. A. (1982). Essays on Bentham. Jurisprudence and political theory. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Hess, E. (2017). The open future square of opposition: A defense. Sophia, 56, 573–587.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kenny, A. (1963). Action, emotion and will. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kienzler, W. (2013). The logical square and the table of oppositions. Five puzzles about the traditional square of opposition solved by taking up a hint from Frege. Logical Analysis and History of Philosophy, 15, 398–413.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lenzen, W. (2012). How to square knowledge and belief. In J.-Y. Béziau & D. Jacquette (Eds.), Around and beyond the square of opposition (pp. 305–311). Berlin: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Lenzen, W. (2016). Leibniz’s logic and the “cube of opposition”. Logica Universalis, 10, 171–189.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lenzen, W. (2017). Caramuel’s theory of opposition. South American Journal of Logic, 3, 1–27.

    Google Scholar 

  • Marcus, R. B. (1966). Iterated deontic modalities. Mind, 75, 580–582.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Parsons, T. (2017). The traditional square of opposition. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy (Summer 2017 Edition). Stanford, CA: CSLI.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pfeifer, N., & Sanfilippo, G. (2017). Probabilistic squares and hexagons of opposition under coherence. International Journal of Approximate Reasoning, 88, 282–294.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rini, A., & Cresswell, M. (2012). The world-time parallel. Tense and modality in logic and metaphysics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Scott, D. (1971). On engendering an illusion of understanding. Journal of Philosophy, 68, 787–807.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Scott, D. (1974). Completeness and axiomatizability in many-valued logic. In L. Henkin (Ed.), Proceedings of the Tarski symposium (pp. 411–435). Providence, RI: American Mathematical Society.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Seuren, P. (2014). Metalogical hexagons in natural logic. Unpublished manuscript.

  • Smessaert, H., & Demey, L. (2014). Logical geometries and information in the square of oppositions. Journal of Logic, Language and Information, 23, 527–565.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sosa, E. (1964). The analysis of ‘knowledge that P’. Analysis, 25, 1–8.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Vranes, E. (2006). The definition of ‘norm conflict’ in international law and legal theory. European Journal of International Law, 17, 395–418.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Yao, Y. (2013). Duality in rough set theory based on the square of opposition. Fundamenta Informaticae, 127, 49–64.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ziegeler, D. (2017). On the empty O-corner of the aristotelian square: A view from singapore english. Journal of Pragmatics, 115, 1–20.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

Thanks to Hans Smessaert, Margaux Smets and three anonymous reviewers for their valuable feedback on an earlier version of this paper. The author holds a Postdoctoral Fellowship of the Research Foundation–Flanders (FWO). The research reported in this paper was partially carried out during a research stay at the Institut für Philosophie II of the Ruhr-Universität Bochum, which was financially supported by an FWO travel grant.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Lorenz Demey.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Demey, L. Aristotelian diagrams for semantic and syntactic consequence. Synthese 198, 187–207 (2021). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-018-01994-w

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-018-01994-w

Keywords

Navigation