Skip to main content
Log in

How Morality Can Be Absent from Moral Arguments

  • Published:
Argumentation Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

What is a moral argument? A straightforward answer is that a moral argument is an argument dealing with moral issues, such as the permissibility of killing in certain circumstances. I call this the thin sense of ‘moral argument’. Arguments that we find in normative and applied ethics are almost invariably moral in this sense. However, they often fail to be moral in other respects. In this article, I discuss four ways in which morality can be absent from moral arguments in the thin sense. If these arguments suffer from an absence of morality in at least one of these ways, they are not moral arguments in what I will call the thick sense of ‘moral argument’. Because only moral arguments in the thick sense could possibly qualify as proper responses to moral problems, the absence of morality in thin arguments means that these arguments will fail to give us a reason to do whatever they claim that we ought to do, even if we see no independent reason to question the truth of the premises or the logical validity of the argument.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. My distinction between thin and thick is related to, but different from the distinctions between thin and thick in Gilbert Ryle (2009, originally published in 1968), Clifford Geertz (1973), Bernard Williams (1985) and Michael Walzer (1994).

  2. I would like to thank an anonymous reviewer for the suggestion to put the point in these terms.

  3. I am speaking of a tradition in the sense explained by Glock, as ‘held together both by ties of influence and by a family of partially overlapping features’ (2008: 223). Glock distinguishes a tradition from a school, the latter being ‘a tightly knit group based on relatively intimate personal contact and a direct transfer of certain doctrines of methods’ (2008: 220).

  4. For a recent overview of the discussion and helpful references, see Pleasants (2015).

  5. A reviewer has remarked that it is not really clear where to draw the line between moral change or evolution and moral revolution. I cannot deal with the issue at length here, but I can say, first, that an answer to this remark crucially depends on one’s understanding of ‘moral revolution’. If a moral revolution is a change so radical that our moral certainties such as ‘killing innocent people is wrong’ would no longer be certainties, then it is doubtful, as I have tried to make clear, whether we can conceive of anything like a moral revolution at all. If, on the other hand, a moral revolution is a radical change in our dealing with and thinking about moral matters, then there can be moral revolutions, but whether something is a revolution or an evolution will then depend on how radical the change is. I would say that the way in which we think about slavery has undergone a revolution rather than an evolution, while the way in which we treat animals has undergone an evolution but not (yet?) a revolution. Admittedly, the distinction is not clear-cut, and neither is the distinction between ‘radical’ and ‘not radical’. The fact that there is a grey zone here does not prove, in my view, that the distinction is useless, and I do not even know whether we should try to draw a clear line between evolutions and revolutions. See, on a related point, footnote 14.

  6. A good overview of the characteristics of certainties can be found in Rummens (2013). For reasons of space, I can only briefly mention them here. (1) Basic certainties cannot be meaningfully doubted. (2) Basic certainties cannot be justified. (3) Basic certainties are certainties of our acting. (4) Doubt regarding basic certainties is a form of insanity. (5) Basic certainties are the preconditions of local doubt. (6) Basic certainties form a system. (7) Basic certainties are not necessarily certain (they are not conceptual or a priori truths) (2013: 134).

  7. I would like to thank an anonymous reviewer for the suggestion to put the point in these terms.

  8. In an earlier version of this article, I maintained that a thick moral argument should embody what Lawrence Blum has called ‘a sense of shared humanity, of regarding the other as a fellow human being’ (1994: 177). Reviewers have remarked that this formulation raises questions about whether we should restrict the moral community to humans alone. I believe that ‘a participant attitude’ and ‘an attitude towards a soul’ are better ways of making the point, since these formulations do not exclude that we can take up these attitudes towards animals as well. This is not to say that we only have moral responsibilities towards other human beings and animals, and not, for example, towards the environment. The need for a participant attitude will boil down, in these cases, to the need for a participant attitude towards those we are arguing with, an attitude that shows awareness of our shared responsibility towards the environment.

  9. According to Gaita, ‘it is mere prejudice to believe that it is an obvious virtue of a philosophical account of ethics to characterise our sense of the ethical in such a way as to yield a decision procedure for what to do in any conceivable situation’ (2004: 73).

  10. Compare Murdoch: ‘[…] it is characteristic of morals that one cannot rest entirely at the conventional level, and that in some ways one ought not to’ (2001: 29).

  11. Note that I do not say ‘subjective’. The pairs personal-impersonal and subjective–objective are not equivalent, for the personal may be objective. While many philosophers will be inclined to say that morality is personal in some sense or another, not so many hold that it is subjective.

  12. Murdoch remarks: ‘It is all very well to say that ‘to copy a right action is to act rightly’ (Hampshire, Logic and Appreciation), but what is the form which I am supposed to copy? It is a truism of recent philosophy that this operation of discerning the form is fairly easy […]’ (2001: 29). Against ‘similar persons in similar circumstances’ arguments, see Gaita (2004: 67) and Rhees (1999: 50).

  13. Compare Murdoch’s description of someone’s moral activity as ‘peculiarly her own’ (2001: 22).

  14. The boundary between offering guidance and telling us what to do is blurred, and different persons confronted with the same argument may reasonably locate it on different sides of the boundary.

  15. Readers have remarked that, for example, Charles Taylor (1989) and Michael Walzer (1987, 1994) have made points similar to those developed in this article. I fully agree, but I cannot here spell out the similarities and differences between this article and their accounts.

  16. The absence of morality in one of these ways will often not be a matter of course: while Glock understands Singer’s argument as leading to the denial of a moral certainty, some will deny that this is so. The distinction between thin and thick arguments is not sharp, but that does not make it useless. Wittgenstein addresses the objection that ‘a boundary [in our case, the boundary between thin and thick moral arguments] which is not sharply defined is not really a boundary at all’ and that, consequently, we ‘haven’t accomplished anything at all’ (2009a: §99). The vagueness of our boundary between thin and thick moral arguments is not to be denied, but it does not stand in the way of our boundary being a boundary. What it does stand in the way of is our being able to say without doubt in every conceivable case whether a moral argument is thick or merely thin. Even if this boundary is vague, that does not prevent us from showing that a certain argument falls on this or that side of it.

  17. I would like to thank an anonymous reviewer for pressing this objection.

  18. An early version of the first part of this paper was presented at the 38th International Ludwig Wittgenstein Symposium in Kirchberg-am-Wechsel, Austria, 2015. I am grateful to Danièle Moyal-Sharrock and Anne-Marie Christensen for their comments. I am grateful to Stefan Rummens and to the members of the Reading Group Ethics of the Institute of Philosophy (KU Leuven) for their comments on a full version of this article.

References

  • Blum, Lawrence A. 1994. Moral perception and particularity. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Cavell, Stanley. 1999. The claim of reason. Wittgenstein, skepticism, morality, and tragedy. Oxford: Oxford University Press. First published in 1979.

  • de Waal, Frans. 2009. Primates and philosophers. How morality evolved. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • De Mesel, Benjamin. 2014. Moral modesty, moral judgment and moral advice. A Wittgensteinian approach. International Journal of Philosophy and Theology 75: 20–37.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • De Mesel, Benjamin. 2015. Do moral questions ask for answers? Philosophia 43: 43–61.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Diamond, Cora. 2002. ‘What if x isn’t the number of sheep?’ Wittgenstein and thought-experiments in ethics. Philosophical Papers 31: 227–250.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gaita, Raimond. 2004. Good and evil. An absolute conception. London: Routledge. Second edition. First published in 1991.

  • Geertz, Clifford. 1973. The interpretation of cultures. Selected essays. New York: Basic Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Glock, Hans-Johann. 2008. What is analytic philosophy?. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Hacker, P.M.S. 2009. Philosophy: a contribution not to human knowledge but to human understanding. In The nature of philosophy (Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement 65), ed. Anthony O’Hear, 129–153. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lovibond, Sabina. 1983. Realism and imagination in ethics. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • McGuinness, Brian (ed.). 1979. Wittgenstein and the Vienna Circle. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Murdoch, Iris. 2001. The sovereignty of good. London: Routledge. First published in 1970.

  • Pleasants, Nigel. 2008. Wittgenstein, ethics and basic moral certainty. Inquiry 51: 241–267.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pleasants, Nigel. 2015. If killing isn’t wrong, then nothing is. A naturalistic defence of basic moral certainty. Ethical Perspectives 22: 197–215.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rhees, Rush. 1965. Some developments in Wittgenstein’s view of ethics. The Philosophical Review 74: 17–26.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rhees, Rush. 1999. Moral questions. Basingstoke: MacMillan Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rummens, Stefan. 2013. On the possibility of a Wittgensteinian account of moral certainty. The Philosophical Forum 44: 125–147.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ryle, Gilbert. 2009. The thinking of thoughts. What is ‘le Penseur’ doing? In Collected papers volume 2. Collected essays 19291968, 494–510. London: Routledge. First published in 1968.

  • Singer, Peter. 2009. Speciesism and moral status. Metaphilosophy 40: 567–581.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Strawson, P.F. 2009. Freedom and resentment. In Free will, ed. Derk Pereboom, 148–171. Indianapolis: Hackett.

    Google Scholar 

  • Taylor, Charles. 1989. Sources of the self. The making of the modern identity. Cambridge (Mass.): Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Waismann, Friedrich. 1965. Notes on talks with Wittgenstein. The Philosophical Review 74: 12–16.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Walzer, Michael. 1987. Interpretation and social criticism. Cambridge (Mass.): Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Walzer, Michael. 1994. Thick and thin. Moral argument at home and abroad. Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Williams, Bernard. 1985. Ethics and the limits of philosophy. Cambridge (Mass.): Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wittgenstein, Ludwig. 1975. On certainty. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wittgenstein, Ludwig. 1999. Denkbewegungen: Tagebücher 1930–1932, 1936–1937. Frankfurt am Main: Fischer Taschenbuch Verlag.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wittgenstein, Ludwig. 2009a. Philosophical investigations. Oxford: Wiley-Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wittgenstein, Ludwig. 2009b. Philosophy of psychology—a fragment. In Philosophical investigations. Oxford: Wiley-Blackwell.

  • Wittgenstein, Ludwig. 2014. Lecture on ethics. Oxford: Wiley-Blackwell.

    Book  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Benjamin De Mesel.

Ethics declarations

Conflict of interest

The authors declare that they have no conflict of interest.

Research Involving Human Participants and/or Animals

This article does not contain any studies with human participants or animals performed by any of the authors.

Informed Consent

Informed consent was obtained from all individual participants included in the study.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

De Mesel, B. How Morality Can Be Absent from Moral Arguments. Argumentation 30, 443–463 (2016). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10503-015-9389-8

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10503-015-9389-8

Keywords

Navigation