Skip to main content

The Interaction Between Logic and Geometry in Aristotelian Diagrams

  • Conference paper
  • First Online:
Diagrammatic Representation and Inference (Diagrams 2016)

Part of the book series: Lecture Notes in Computer Science ((LNAI,volume 9781))

Included in the following conference series:

Abstract

We develop a systematic approach for dealing with informationally equivalent Aristotelian diagrams, based on the interaction between the logical properties of the visualized information and the geometrical properties of the concrete polygon/polyhedron. To illustrate the account’s fruitfulness, we apply it to all Aristotelian families of 4-formula fragments that are closed under negation (comparing square and rectangle) and to all Aristotelian families of 6-formula fragments that are closed under negation (comparing hexagon and octahedron).

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 54.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 69.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    See www.logicalgeometry.org.

  2. 2.

    See [15] for some historical background on this nomenclature.

  3. 3.

    One counterexample is Chow [7], who studies Aristotelian diagrams that satisfy the logical condition, but not the geometrical condition.

  4. 4.

    In [20, p. 77] this formula is applied to a fragment of 4 formulas (so \(n=2\)).

  5. 5.

    In this paper, we will mainly focus on regular polygons and polyhedra (the only exception being the brief discussion of rectangles in Sect. 4). However, this restriction is only made for reasons of space; in principle, the account presented here can be applied to regular and non-regular shapes alike.

  6. 6.

    The idea of working up to symmetry can already be found in [4, p. 315], where it is stated that Aristotelian squares that are symmetrical variants of each other should be “counted as being of the same type”. The assumed irrelevance of symmetry considerations for diagram design is also in line with work on other types of diagrams, such as Euler diagrams [27]: several of their visual characteristics have been investigated [1, 3], but it has been found that rotation has no significant influence on user comprehension of Euler diagrams [2].

  7. 7.

    Note that both fractions have the same numerator (since the two Aristotelian diagrams have the same logical properties, viz. they both visualize the fragment \(\mathcal {F}\)), but different denominators (since the two diagrams have different geometrical properties, viz. \(\mathcal {P}\) is less symmetric than \(\mathcal {P}'\)).

  8. 8.

    These considerations can be viewed as an application of the congruity/isomorphism principle in diagram design [18, 36]: the visual properties of the diagram should closely correspond to the logical properties of the visualized fragment.

  9. 9.

    We are using the term ‘square’ in a strictly historical sense here, regardless of its concrete geometrical properties.

  10. 10.

    In particular: (i) a contrariety between \(\varphi \) and \(\psi \) yields subalternations from \(\varphi \) to \(\lnot \psi \) and from \(\psi \) to \(\lnot \varphi \); (ii) a subcontrariety between \(\varphi \) and \(\psi \) yields subalternations from \(\lnot \varphi \) to \(\psi \) and from \(\lnot \psi \) to \(\varphi \); (iii) a subalternation from \(\varphi \) to \(\psi \) yields a contrariety between \(\varphi \) and \(\lnot \psi \) and a subcontrariety between \(\lnot \varphi \) and \(\psi \).

  11. 11.

    For reasons of space, our discussion of the visualizations of these 5 families will be fairly brief; however, much more can (and should) be said about each of them.

  12. 12.

    This result is in line with earlier work on visualizations for JSB fragments [13, 16].

  13. 13.

    Hexagons 1, 3 and 6 in [6, pp. 131–132] visualize an SC fragment using three distinct fundamental forms, viz. those shown in Figs. 2(b), 5(e) and (f), respectively.

  14. 14.

    The hexagons in Fig. 6(a) and (c) strike a balance between the (sub)contrarieties and subalternations, by distributing visual prominence equally among them.

  15. 15.

    The term ‘polytope’ is a generalization of the terms ‘polygon’ and ‘polyhedron’ to arbitrary dimensions [9].

  16. 16.

    One might object that higher-dimensional cross-polytopes can be visualized, by considering their lower-dimensional projections. This objection fails to take into account, however, that such projections will break some of the cross-polytopes’ symmetries, and thus not be useful for our current purposes. This phenomenon can already be observed in very low dimensions; for example, the hexagon in Fig. 2(a) can be seen as the 2D projection of the octahedron in Fig. 3(c), but this projection drastically reduces the number of symmetries (from the octahedron’s 48 to the hexagon’s 12).

References

  1. Benoy, F., Rodgers, P.: Evaluating the comprehension of Euler diagrams. In: 11th International Conference on Information Visualization, pp. 771–778. IEEE Computer Society (2007)

    Google Scholar 

  2. Blake, A., Stapleton, G., Rodgers, P., Cheek, L., Howse, J.: Does the orientation of an Euler diagram affect user comprehension? In: 18th International Conference on Distributed Multimedia Systems, pp. 185–190. Knowledge Systems Institute (2012)

    Google Scholar 

  3. Blake, A., Stapleton, G., Rodgers, P., Cheek, L., Howse, J.: The impact of shape on the perception of Euler diagrams. In: Dwyer, T., Purchase, H., Delaney, A. (eds.) Diagrams 2014. LNCS, vol. 8578, pp. 123–137. Springer, Heidelberg (2014)

    Google Scholar 

  4. Brown, M.: Generalized quantifiers and the square of opposition. Notre Dame J. Formal Logic 25, 303–322 (1984)

    Article  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  5. Cavaliere, F.: Fuzzy syllogisms, numerical square, triangles of contraries, inter-bivalence. In: Béziau, J.Y., Jacquette, D. (eds.) Around and Beyond the Square of Opposition, pp. 241–260. Springer, Heidelberg (2012)

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  6. Chatti, S., Schang, F.: The cube, the square and the problem of existential import. Hist. Philos. Logic 32, 101–132 (2013)

    Article  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  7. Chow, K.F.: General patterns of opposition squares and 2n-gons. In: Béziau, J.Y., Jacquette, D. (eds.) Around and Beyond the Square, pp. 263–275. Springer, Heidelberg (2012)

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  8. Correia, M.: Boethius on the square of opposition. In: Béziau, J.Y., Jacquette, D. (eds.) Around and Beyond the Square of Opposition, pp. 41–52. Springer, Heidelberg (2012)

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  9. Coxeter, H.S.M.: Regular Polytopes. Dover Publications, Mineola (1973)

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  10. Demey, L.: Algebraic aspects of duality diagrams. In: Cox, P., Plimmer, B., Rodgers, P. (eds.) Diagrams 2012. LNCS, vol. 7352, pp. 300–302. Springer, Heidelberg (2012)

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  11. Demey, L.: Structures of oppositions for public announcement logic. In: Béziau, J.Y., Jacquette, D. (eds.) Around and Beyond the Square of Opposition, pp. 313–339. Springer, Heidelberg (2012)

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  12. Demey, L.: Interactively illustrating the context-sensitivity of Aristotelian diagrams. In: Christiansen, H., Stojanovic, I., Papadopoulos, G. (eds.) CONTEXT 2015. LNCS, vol. 9405, pp. 331–345. Springer, Heidelberg (2015)

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  13. Demey, L., Smessaert, H.: The relationship between Aristotelian and Hasse diagrams. In: Dwyer, T., Purchase, H., Delaney, A. (eds.) Diagrams 2014. LNCS, vol. 8578, pp. 213–227. Springer, Heidelberg (2014)

    Google Scholar 

  14. Demey, L., Smessaert, H.: Combinatorial bitstring semantics for arbitrary logical fragments (2015, submitted)

    Google Scholar 

  15. Demey, L., Smessaert, H.: Metalogical decorations of logical diagrams. Log. Univers. 10, 233–292 (2016)

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  16. Demey, L., Smessaert, H.: Shape heuristics in Aristotelian diagrams. In: Kutz, O., Borgo, S., Bhatt, M. (eds.) Shapes 3.0 Proceedings. CEUR-WS (forthcoming)

    Google Scholar 

  17. Dubois, D., Prade, H.: From Blanché’s hexagonal organization of concepts to formal concept analysis and possibility theory. Log. Univers. 6, 149–169 (2012)

    Article  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  18. Gurr, C.: Effective diagrammatic communication: syntactic, semantic and pragmatic issues. J. Vis. Lang. Comput. 10, 317–342 (1999)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  19. Horn, L.R.: A Natural History of Negation. University of Chicago Press, Chicago (1989)

    Google Scholar 

  20. Jacquette, D.: Thinking outside the square of opposition box. In: Béziau, J.Y., Jacquette, D. (eds.) Around and Beyond the Square, pp. 73–92. Springer, Heidelberg (2012)

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  21. Joerden, J.: Logik im Recht. Springer, Heidelberg (2010)

    Book  Google Scholar 

  22. Kraszewski, Z.: Logika stosunków zakresowych [Logic of extensional relations]. Stud. Logica. 4, 63–116 (1956)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  23. Larkin, J., Simon, H.: Why a diagram is (sometimes) worth ten thousand words. Cogn. Sci. 11, 65–99 (1987)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  24. McNamara, P.: Deontic logic. In: Zalta, E.N. (ed.) Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. CSLI (2010)

    Google Scholar 

  25. Moretti, A.: The geometry of standard deontic logic. Log. Univers. 3, 19–57 (2009)

    Article  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  26. Parsons, T.: The traditional square of opposition. In: Zalta, E.N. (ed.) Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. CSLI (2006)

    Google Scholar 

  27. Rodgers, P.: A survey of Euler diagrams. J. Vis. Lang. Comput. 25, 134–155 (2014)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  28. Rotman, J.J.: An Introduction to the Theory of Groups, 4th edn. Springer, New York (1995)

    Book  MATH  Google Scholar 

  29. Seuren, P., Jaspers, D.: Logico-cognitive structure in the lexicon. Language 90, 607–643 (2014)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  30. Smessaert, H.: On the 3D visualisation of logical relations. Log. Univers. 3, 303–332 (2009)

    Article  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  31. Smessaert, H.: Boolean differences between two hexagonal extensions of the logical square of oppositions. In: Cox, P., Plimmer, B., Rodgers, P. (eds.) Diagrams 2012. LNCS, vol. 7352, pp. 193–199. Springer, Heidelberg (2012)

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  32. Smessaert, H., Demey, L.: Logical and geometrical complementarities between Aristotelian diagrams. In: Dwyer, T., Purchase, H., Delaney, A. (eds.) Diagrams 2014. LNCS, vol. 8578, pp. 246–260. Springer, Heidelberg (2014)

    Google Scholar 

  33. Smessaert, H., Demey, L.: Logical geometries and information in the square of opposition. J. Logic Lang. Inform. 23, 527–565 (2014)

    Article  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  34. Smessaert, H., Demey, L.: The unreasonable effectiveness of bitstrings in logical geometry. In: Béziau, J.Y. (ed.) Proceedings of Square (2014, forthcoming)

    Google Scholar 

  35. Smessaert, H., Demey, L.: Visualising the Boolean algebra \(\mathbb{B}_4\) in 3D. In: Jamnik, M., Uesaka, Y., Elzer Schwartz, S. (eds.) Diagrams 2016. LNCS, vol. 9781, pp. 289–292. Springer, Heidelberg (2016)

    Google Scholar 

  36. Tversky, B.: Prolegomenon to scientific visualizations. In: Gilbert, J.K. (ed.) Visualization in Science Education, pp. 29–42. Springer, Heidelberg (2005)

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  37. Tversky, B.: Visualizing thought. Top. Cogn. Sci. 3, 499–535 (2011)

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

We would like to thank Dany Jaspers and Margaux Smets for their valuable feedback on an earlier version of this paper. The first author holds a Postdoctoral Fellowship of the Research Foundation–Flanders (FWO).

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Lorenz Demey .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2016 Springer International Publishing Switzerland

About this paper

Cite this paper

Demey, L., Smessaert, H. (2016). The Interaction Between Logic and Geometry in Aristotelian Diagrams. In: Jamnik, M., Uesaka, Y., Elzer Schwartz, S. (eds) Diagrammatic Representation and Inference. Diagrams 2016. Lecture Notes in Computer Science(), vol 9781. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-42333-3_6

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-42333-3_6

  • Published:

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Cham

  • Print ISBN: 978-3-319-42332-6

  • Online ISBN: 978-3-319-42333-3

  • eBook Packages: Computer ScienceComputer Science (R0)

Publish with us

Policies and ethics