Skip to main content
Log in

Money for Blood and Markets for Blood

  • Published:
HEC Forum Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Ontario’s Bill 178 proposing a Voluntary Blood Donations Act declares the offer or acceptance of payment for the donation of blood a legal offence and makes it subject to penalty. The bill reinvigorates a fundamental debate about the ethical problems associated with the payment of money for blood. Scarcity of blood donors is a recurring problem in most health systems, and monetary remuneration of the willingness to donate blood is regularly discussed—and sometimes practiced—as a means to overcome scarcity in blood. However, making blood an object of economic exchange has long aroused ethical concerns that often refer to the specific meaning of blood. From the perspective of a modern understanding of money as a metric of economic value, the exchange of money for blood—shed or given—is seen as ethically troubling, because it appears to imply a commensurability of the value of human life and economic wealth. In this paper, we begin with a general taxonomy of the types of arguments that speak in favour or against compensating donors for giving blood. We then describe the context in which the discussion about payment for blood arises, and of the specific aims and concerns that are brought forward in this context. This is used to reconstruct the normative background that supports the rejection of payment for blood as it is envisaged in Bill 178 and the aims of the proposal. We then argue that while a payment indeed changes the nature of a blood donation in an ethically considerable way, we do not believe that decisive arguments against the monetary remuneration of blood donations can be substantiated, at least not independently of assuming specific societal circumstances. Thus it may be possible to establish a stable and safe blood supply through just gratification while at the same time taking strong provisions against social disconnection, injustice, exploitation or heteronomy.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. A moral argument for the separation of different social spheres can be found in Walzer (1983, esp. chs. 3 & 4).

  2. For recent accounts see Satz (2010, esp ch. 4) and Sandel (2012, esp pp. 110–113; 122–127).

  3. See e.g., Buyx (2009, pp. 330–332). For a similar distinction in the context of organ donations see Quante (2008, p. 62).

  4. Whenever we speak of individuals who are dependent on receiving blood, we mean to include not only those who are in need of whole blood transfusions, but also those who depend on specific components of blood for therapy or the provision of pharmaceuticals. For a discussion of the general effects of the introduction of payment for blood donations on their safety and quantity see Rodriguez del Pozo (1994) and Fernández-Montoya (1997).

  5. A person’s decision to give blood under economic pressure may be her own decision in the sense of the presence of a conscious intention to give blood. However, in a more demanding sense the person may be unable to identify with her decision, if she considers the motive of her action to give blood to be alien to her evaluative self-image.

  6. We will not go into the discussion whether the harmful effects on society can in turn be translated into effects on the individual members of society. The central point here is that there may be a party—be it a collective or individual persons—besides the donors and recipients of blood that appears in the relevant ethical considerations.

  7. One classic instance of this critique of a conversion of ends into means can be found in Marx’s analysis in the Comments on James Mill. See Quante (2011).

  8. This distinction is obviously not to be identified with the distinction between categorical and contributory objections to paid blood donations. For, an intrinsic quality of an action may make it more or less commendable as a mere contributory reason. That an action is an instance of lying may make it intrinsically disfavourable, but may not be decisive reason against it, once it is granted that there are competing considerations—that it saves another person's life—to be taken into account.

  9. See Strauss (2001).

  10. It may be doubted that there are extrinsic categorical considerations. For this case one might think of consequences that are contingently linked to an action, and that render the conclusion unavoidable that the action is impermissible.

  11. For simplicity's sake we only look at allogeneic donations, i.e., donations given to a blood bank, without having a specific recipient (e.g., the donor herself or a relative of hers) in mind.

  12. Bill 178 (2014, 3.1.). Sentence 3.2. states the corresponding prohibition to accept payment for the donors.

  13. WHO (2010, pp. 19–20).

  14. WHO (2010) presupposes that „[paid] donors are vulnerable to exploitation and commercialization of the human body as they usually come from the poorer sectors of society and become paid blood donors due to economic difficulties.“ While this is probably true under many social circumstances, it would have to be shown that these circumstances actually apply in the case of the Canadian bill.

  15. See Titmuss (1997, esp. ch. 8). Regarding the debate following the first edition of Titmuss's contribution see Arrow (1972), Singer (1973) and Archard (2002).

  16. For this distinction see Archard (2002, pp. 93–94).

  17. Bill 178 (2014, 1.3.).

  18. Bill 178 (2014, 1.1.).

  19. WHO (2010, p. 3) brings forward a similar argument that depends on the further recognition that “voluntary non-remunerated blood donors are the foundation of a safe, sustainable blood supply.”

  20. See Daniels (2008, pp. 110–111) and Sen (2004).

  21. Bill 178 (2014, 3.3).

References

  • Archard, D. (2002). Selling yourself: Titmuss’s argument against a market in blood. The Journal of Ethics, 6, 87–103.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Arrow, K. (1972). Gifts and exchanges. Philosophy & Public Affairs, 4, 343–362.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bill 178, 2nd Session, 40th Legislature, Ontario 63 Elizabeth II. (2014). An act to ensure that Blood and Blood Constituents are Donated Freely/Voluntary Blood Donations Act. Retrieved from http://www.ontla.on.ca/bills/bills-files/40_Parliament/Session2/b178.pdf. Accessed 21 Nov 2014.

  • Buyx, A. (2009). Blood donation, payment, and non-cash incentives: Classical questions drawing renewed interest. Transfusion Medicine and Hemotherapy, 36, 329–339.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Daniels, N. (2008). Just health. Meeting health needs fairly: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fernández-Montoya, A. (1997). Altruism and payment in blood donation. Transfusion Science, 18, 379–386.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Quante, M. (2008). My body, my ware-house? Acta Universtitatis Lodziensis. Folia Philosophica, 21, 59–74.

    Google Scholar 

  • Quante, M. (2011). Recognition as the social grammar of species being in Marx. In H. Ikaheimo & A. Laitinen (Eds.), Recognition and social ontology (pp. 239–268). Leiden: Brill.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Rodriguez del Pozo, P. (1994). Paying donors and the ethics of blood supply. Journal of Medical Ethics, 20, 31–35.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sandel, M. (2012). What money can’t buy: The moral limits of markets. London: Allen Lane (Penguin).

    Google Scholar 

  • Satz, D. (2010). Why some things should not be for sale: The moral limits of markets. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Sen, A. (2004). Why health equity? In S. Anand, F. Peter, & A. Sen (Eds.), Public health, ethics, and equity (pp. 21–34). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Singer, P. (1973). Altruism and commerce: A defense of Titmuss against Arrow. Philosophy & Public Affairs, 2, 312–320.

    Google Scholar 

  • Strauss, R. (2001). Blood donations, safety, and incentives. Transfusion, 41, 165–167.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Titmuss, R. (1997). The gift relationship. From human blood to social policy. New York: New Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Walzer, M. (1983). Spheres of justice. New York: Basic Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • WHO. (2010). Towards 100 % voluntary blood donation. A global framework for action. Retrieved from http://www.who.int/bloodsafety/publications/9789241599696_eng.pdf?ua=1. Accessed 21 Nov 2014.

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Simon Derpmann.

Additional information

We would like to thank the two anonymous reviewers for their comments and critiques of the first submitted version of this paper.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Derpmann, S., Quante, M. Money for Blood and Markets for Blood. HEC Forum 27, 331–345 (2015). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10730-014-9259-z

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10730-014-9259-z

Keywords

Navigation