Skip to main content
Log in

Another perspective on Borda’s paradox

  • Published:
Theory and Decision Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

This paper presents the conditions required for a profile in order to never exhibit either the strong or the strict Borda paradoxes under all weighted scoring rules in three-candidate elections. The main particularity of our paper is that all the conclusions are deduced from the differences of votes between candidates in pairwise majority elections. This way allows us to answer new questions and provide an organized knowledge of the conditions under which a given profile never shows one or the other of the two paradoxes.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Fig. 1
Fig. 2

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. A rigorous definition of this notion is given in Sect. 2.1.

  2. Saari and McIntee (2013) use the notation P(XY). Instead, we use the notation XY since it allows us to reduce the length of our results.

  3. For a detailed description of Saari’s voting geometry, the reader is referred to Saari (1989, 1995, 2010) and Nurmi (2002).

  4. Notice that these results are found under the standard assumption that \(AB > 0\) and \(BC > 0\). This is established without loss of generality.

  5. Remember that if the strongly non-cyclic condition is not satisfied this does not necessarily define a cycle. Although we use the name “cyclic” for this essential profile to be consistent with Saari and McIntee (2013), we need to consider \(AC>0\), in our framework of Borda’s paradox, in order for C to be a Condorcet loser.

  6. For instance, the preference \(A\succ B\succ C\) type has a reverse given by \(C\succ B\succ A\). It is clear that removing the same number of voters with reversal pairs does not change XY values.

  7. This is not true with more than three candidates.

  8. It is equivalent to remove 5 voters of each of both \(A\succ B\succ C\) and \(C\succ B\succ A\) preference types.

  9. Notice that n and all XY values have the same parity. This is true because, for each pair of candidates X and Y we have \(n = \{X\text {'s vote} + Y\text {'s vote}\}\), which leads to \(\{X\text {'s vote}\} = \frac{1}{2}(n + XY)\) since \(XY=\{X\text {'s vote} - Y\text {'}\text{ s } \text{ vote }\}\). In order for \(\{X\text {'s vote}\}\) to be an integer value, it follows that n and all XY values either are odd integers, or are all even integers. In other words, \(\alpha +\beta +\gamma \) is always an integer value and, even more, it has the same parity as n and all XY values.

  10. Notice that for all U in \(\mathbb {Z}\), we have \(\lfloor U \rfloor = U - F(U)\) such that \(\lfloor U \rfloor \) stands for the greatest integer less than or equal to U. Notice that F(U) is defined in the same way for positive and negative numbers. However, it is important to precise that for instance \(\lfloor -1.3 \rfloor = -2 \) leading to \(F(-1.3)=0.7\) and \(\lfloor 1.3 \rfloor = 1 \) leading to \(F(1.3)=0.3\).

  11. Notice that in this case \(U=\dfrac{AC-AB}{2}\) and \(F(U)=0\) since AB and AC have the same parity (see the discussion in Footnote 9). The same remark can be used for some other parts of our corollaries.

  12. Let us explain more precisely the latter case. First, the condition \((1-s)(AC-AB)+2sBC\ge 0\) in 1-c of Theorem 1 leads to \(s\ge \dfrac{1}{3}\). In addition, the value of F(U) in the condition \((1-s)AC+sBC \ge \dfrac{1-2s}{3}(n-2+2 F(U))\) does not matter. Indeed, we know that \(0 \le F(U)\lesssim 1\). In addition, if \(F(U)=0\), the condition \((1-s)AC+sBC \ge \dfrac{1-2s}{3}(n-2+2 F(U))\) becomes \(s\ge \dfrac{1}{8}\). Moreover, if \(F(U)\simeq 1\), the condition \((1-s)AC+sBC \ge \dfrac{1-2s}{3}(n-2+2 F(U))\) becomes \(s\gtrsim \dfrac{1}{5}\). Both \(s\ge \dfrac{1}{8}\) and \(s\gtrsim \dfrac{1}{5}\) are relaxed in comparison with the first requirement given by \(s\ge \dfrac{1}{3}\).

References

  • de Borda, J. C. (1781). Mémoire sur les élections au srutin. Paris: Histoire de l’Académie Royale des Sciences.

    Google Scholar 

  • de Condorcet, M. (1785). Éssai sur l’application de l’analyse à la probabilité des décisions rendues à la pluralité des voix. Paris: Imprimerie Royale.

    Google Scholar 

  • Daunou, P. C. F. (1803). A paper on elections by ballot. In F. Sommerlad & I. McLean (Eds.), The political theory of Condorcet II (pp. 235–279). Oxford: University of Oxford Working Paper.

    Google Scholar 

  • Diss, M., & Gehrlein, W. V. (2012). Borda’s paradox with weighted scoring rules. Social Choice and Welfare, 38, 121–136.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fishburn, P. C., & Gehrlein, W. V. (1976). Borda’s rule, positional voting, and Condorcet’s simple majority principle. Public Choice, 28, 79–88.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gärdenfors, P. (1973). Positionalist voting functions. Theory and Decision, 4, 1–24.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gehrlein, W. V., & Lepelley, D. (2010a). Voting paradoxes and group coherence: The Condorcet efficiency of voting rules. Berlin: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gehrlein, W. V., & Lepelley, D. (2010b). On the probability of observing Borda’s paradox. Social Choice and Welfare, 35, 1–23.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gehrlein, W. V., & Lepelley, D. (2016). Refining measures of group mutual coherence. Quality and Quantity, 50(4), 1845–1870.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kamwa, E., & Valognes, F. (2017). Scoring rules and preference restrictions: The strong Borda paradox revisited. Revue d’Economie Politique, 127(3), 375–395.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nurmi, H. (2002). Voting procedures under uncertainty. New York: Springer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Saari, D. G. (1989). A dictionary for voting paradoxes. Journal of Economic Theory, 48, 443–475.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Saari, D. G. (1995). Basic geometry of voting. New York: Springer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Saari, D. G. (1999). Explaining all three-alternative voting outcomes. Journal of Economic Theory, 87, 313–355.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Saari, D. G. (2008). Disposing dictators, demystifying voting paradoxes. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Saari, D. G. (2010). Geometry of voting. In K. Arrow, A. Sen, & K. Suzumura (Eds.), Handbook of social choice and welfare (pp. 897–946). San Diego: Elsevier.

    Google Scholar 

  • Saari, D. G., & McIntee, T. J. (2013). Connecting pairwise and positional election outcomes. Mathematical Social Sciences, 66, 140–151.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Smith, J. H. (1973). Aggregation of preferences with variable electorate. Econometrica, 41, 1027–1041.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Mostapha Diss.

Additional information

The authors thank two anonymous reviewers of Theory and Decision for their helpful feedback on an earlier version of this paper. We further thank Nicolas Barbaroux, Richard Baron, Rachid Chemsi, Rachid Dali, and Florent Pirot for their help in proofreading the paper. The first author gratefully acknowledges financial support by the National Agency for Research (ANR)—research program “Dynamic Matching and Interactions: Theory and Experiments” (DynaMITE) ANR-BLANC.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Diss, M., Tlidi, A. Another perspective on Borda’s paradox. Theory Decis 84, 99–121 (2018). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11238-017-9649-1

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11238-017-9649-1

Keywords

Navigation