Skip to main content
Log in

Dynamic Logic of Legal Competences

  • Published:
Journal of Logic, Language and Information Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

We propose a new formalization of legal competences, and in particular for the Hohfeldian categories of power and immunity, through a deontic reinterpretation of dynamic epistemic logic. We argue that this logic explicitly captures the norm-changing character of legal competences while providing a sophisticated reduction of the latter to static normative positions. The logic is completely axiomatizable, and we apply it to a concrete case in German contract law to illustrate that it can capture the distinction between legal ability and legal permissibility.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Fig. 1
Fig. 2
Fig. 3
Fig. 4
Fig. 5
Fig. 6
Fig. 7

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. What we call here static and dynamic rights have been labelled in various ways in the formal literature. Kanger called static rights the “type of the states of affairs” and dynamic ones the “type of influence” (Kanger 1972). Makinson instead used the “deontic family” and the “legally capacitative family” for static and dynamic rights, respectively (Makinson 1986). Bentham, von Wright and Hart on the other hand used “legal validity” and “norm-creating action” (Lindahl 1977), while (Lindahl 1977) called it “the range of action.”

  2. The terminology used by Hohfeld might not fully reflect how terms like “power”, “immunity” or “liability” have been used in all the English-speaking literature. The work following (Kanger 1972) has, however, in important parts used that terminology. In other to situate our contribution better in that tradition, we use it here as well. We thank one of the anonymous reviewers of the JLLI for pointing us to the importance of making this caveat.

  3. The results presented in this paper build on and extend the work reported in (Dong and Roy 2017). The present paper uses a more general condition for static conditional obligations, presents an improved version of the definitions of power and immunity, and a more in-depth conceptual discussion of the key points.

  4. There have been a number of different proposals for defining “seeing to it that”. One popular family of approaches uses either one (Chellas 1980) or a pair of unary modalities  (Kanger 1972; Lindahl 1977; Makinson 1986). All of them satisfy the T axiom as well as the E rule for substitution of logical equivalence. More recent approaches, as for instance the so-called “Chellas STIT”, use a normal, S5 modality (Chellas 1992; Horty 2000).

  5. The complexity of the formula below is due to the fact that there might not be states that are maximal according to the relation \(\ge _{i \rightarrow j}\), i.e. states that have no other states strictly above them. When such states are guaranteed to exist, for instance finite models, this definition reduces to the more familiar definition in terms of truth in all maximal states.

  6. Our definition of the update rule is slightly different from the standard one, used for instance Baltag and Smets (2008); van Benthem et al. (2014). Here two pairs (wa) and \((w', a')\) are connected in the updated model as soon as \(a >^{{\mathcal {A}}_i}_{j \rightarrow k} a'\) or the other way around. This is so irrespective of whether w and \(w'\) were initially connected by \(\le _{j \rightarrow k}\). We made this modeling choice because it allowed us to capture more naturally some of the examples that we present here.

  7. The semantics of conditional obligation that we use also yields, after the update, that at \((w_1, a_1)\) the city has an unconditional claim against Ivy to park and not display a permit. This counter-intuitive prediction is a consequence of the fact that this semantics validates \(O_{i \rightarrow c}(\varphi /\varphi )\), for any \(\varphi \). This means that, when the current state can only see itself according to the relation \(\le ^{{\mathcal {A}}_{John}}_{i \rightarrow c}\), we obtain that \(O_{i \rightarrow c}\varphi \) whenever \(\varphi \) is true. This is an issue that is shared by most preferential accounts of conditional obligation (Zvolenszky 2002), and that also affects some approaches based on default logic (Fuhrmann 2017). Addressing this thoroughly would require using a completely different approach to static conditional obligations, which would go beyond the scope of this paper. Note, however, that this is a defect that only affects the static conditional obligations. One could also interpret ”given \(\varphi \), \(\psi \)” dynamically, for instance using in terms of public announcements of the form \([\varphi !]\psi \), which are a special cases of the updates that we define here (Baltag and Smets 2008). It is well known that \([\varphi !]\varphi \) is not a valid formula (van Ditmarsch et al. 2007).

  8. This view of legal powers as potential to change or ”flip”, so to speak, the truth value of certain legal facts is also used by van Eijck and Ju (2016). Note, however, that in that paper they restrict to the case where the agents have control over atomic propositions, while where the legal powers extend to any right \(T(j,k,\psi /\varphi )\).

  9. These axioms are by and large standard, c.f. again (Baltag and Smets 2008; van Benthem et al. 2014). The only difference comes from our slightly non-standard clause in the lexicographic update rule, which results in the use of the universal modality in the first group of conjuncts in the second equivalence from below. See again footnote 6 on page 11 for details.

  10. Our emphasis. Freely tranlated from “Nichteinhaltung von Beschränkungen aus dem der Vertretungsmacht zugrunde liegenden Rechtsverhältnis bei Vornahme eines Rechtsgeschäfts in Stellvertretung durch den Vertreter. Da die Vertretungsmacht von dem zugrunde liegenden Rechtsverhältnis abstrakt ist, führen solche Beschränkungen nicht zu einer Einschränkung der Vertretungsmacht, so dass sich auch eine unter Missbrauch der Vertretungsmacht abgegebene Erklärung grundsätzlich im Rahmen der Vertretungsmacht hält.” Source http://rechtslexikon.net/d/missbrauch-der-vertretungsmacht/missbrauch-der-vertretungsmacht.htm.

  11. The German Civil Code of course explicitly voids this provision if there was proven collusion between buyer and seller, or when the seller should have known the terms of the agent’s contract.

References

  • Baltag, A., & Smets, S. (2008). A qualitative theory of dynamic interactive belief revision. Logic and the foundations of game and decision theory (LOFT), 7(3), 9–58.

    Google Scholar 

  • Boutilier, C. (1994). Toward a logic for qualitative decision theory. In Principles of Knowledge Representation and Reasoning: Proceedings of the Fourth International Conference (KR’94), pp 75–86.

  • Burgess, J. P. (1981). Quick completeness proofs for some logics of conditionals. Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic, 22(1), 76–84.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chellas, B. F. (1980). Modal logic: an introduction (Vol. 316). Cambridge Univ Press.

  • Chellas, B. F. (1992). Time and modality in the logic of agency. Studia Logica, 51(3–4), 485–517.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dong, H. (2017). Permission in non-monotonic normative reasoning. Universität Bayreuth. PhD thesis.

  • Dong, H., & Roy, O. (2017). Dynamic logic of power and immunity. International Workshop on Logic (pp. 123–136). Rationality and Interaction: Springer.

  • Fuhrmann, A. (2017). Deontic modals: Why abandon the default approach. Erkenntnis, 82(6), 1351–1365.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Goldman, A. I. (1970). A theory of human action. Princeton University Press.

  • Governatori, G., Rotolo, A., & Sartor, G. (2005). Temporalised normative positions in defeasible logic (pp. 25–34). ACM.

  • Grossi, D., Meyer, J. J. C., & Dignum, F. (2006). Classificatory aspects of counts-as: An analysis in modal logic. Journal of Logic and Computation, 16(5), 613–643.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hansson, B. (1969). An analysis of some deontic logics. Nous, 3(4), 373–398.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Harel, D., Kozen, D., & Tiuryn, J. (2000). Dynamic logic. MIT press.

  • Herrestad, H., & Krogh, C. (1995). Obligations directed from bearers to counterparties (pp. 210–218). ACM Press.

  • Herzig, A., Lorini, E., & Troquard, N. (2011). A dynamic logic of institutional actions. In P. Torroni, T. Ågotnes, G. Boella, & L. van der Torre (Eds.), Leite J (pp. 295–311). Springer: International Workshop on Computational Logic in Multi-Agent Systems.

  • Hohfeld, W. N. (1913). Some fundamental legal conceptions as applied in judicial reasoning. The Yale Law Journal, 23(1), 16–59.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Horty, J. F. (2000). Agency and deontic logic. Oxford University Press.

  • Jones, A. J., & Sergot, M. (1996). A formal characterisation of institutionalised power. Logic Journal of IGPL, 4(3), 427–443.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kanger, S. (1970). New foundations for ethical theory. Deontic logic: Introductory and systematic readings (pp. 36–58). Springer.

  • Kanger, S. (1972). Law and logic. Theoria, 38(3), 105–132.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kanger, S., & Kanger, H. (1966). Rights and parliamentarism. Theoria, 32(2), 85–115.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lindahl, L. (1977). Position and change: A study in law and logic. Springer Science & Business Media.

  • Lorini, E., & Longin, D. (2008). A logical account of institutions: From acceptances to norms via legislators. In: Brewka, G., Lang, J. (eds) Proceedings of the 11th International Conference on Principles of Knowledge Representation and Reasoning, AAAI Press (pp. 38–48).

  • Makinson, D. (1986). On the formal representation of rights relations. Journal of Philosophical Logic, 15(4), 403–425.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Markovich R (2016) Agents, roles and rights. a formal analysis on Hohfeldian conceptions. In: Belkemishev, L., Demri, S., & Máté, A. (eds) Advances in Modal Logic.

  • Markovich, R. (2020). Understanding Hohfeld and formalizing legal rights: The Hohfeldian conceptions and their conditional consequences. Studia Logica, 108(1), 129–158.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Meyer, J. J. C. (1988). A different approach to deontic logic: Deontic logic viewed as a variant of dynamic logic. Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic, 29(1), 109–136.

    Google Scholar 

  • Parent, X. (2014). Maximality vs. optimality in dyadic deontic logic. Journal of Philosophical Logic, 43(6), 1101–1128.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sartor, G. (2005). Legal reasoning. Springer.

  • Sergot, M. (2013). Normative positions. In D. Gabbay, J. Horty, X. Parent, R. van der Meyden, & L. van der Torre (Eds.), Handbook of deontic logic and normative systems. (Vol. 1). College Publication.

  • Sergot, M. (2001). A computational theory of normative positions. ACM Transactions on Computational Logic (TOCL), 2(4), 581–622.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • van Benthem, J. (2011). Logical dynamics of information and interaction. Cambridge University Press.

  • van Benthem, J., Grossi, D., & Liu, F. (2010). Deontics = Betterness + Priority. In G. S. Guido Governatori (Ed.), Deontic Logic in Computer Science: 10th International Conference, DEON 2010 (pp. 50–65). Springer.

  • van Benthem, J., van Otterloo, S., & Roy, O. (2006). Preference logic, conditionals, and solution concepts in games. In S. Lindström & R. Śliwiński (Eds.), Lagerlund H (pp. 61–76). Modality Matters: Twenty-Five Essays in Honour of Krister Segerberg, University of Uppsala.

  • van Benthem, J., Grossi, D., & Liu, F. (2014). Priority structures in deontic logic. Theoria, 80(2), 116–152.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • van Ditmarsch, H., & Kooi, B. (2008). Semantic results for ontic and epistemic change. In: Bonanno, G., Wooldridge, M., van der Hoek, W. (eds) Proceedings of Conference on Logic and the Foundations of Game and Decision Theory, Amsterdam University Press (pp 87–117).

  • van Ditmarsch, H., van der Hoek, W., & Kooi, B. (2007). Dynamic epistemic logic (Vol. 337). Springer Science & Business Media.

  • van Eijck, J., & Ju, F. (2016). Modelling legal relations. In: Bonanno, G., van der Hoek, W., & Perea, A. (eds) Proceedings of Conference on Logic and the Foundations of Game and Decision Theory.

  • von Wright, G. H. (1963). Norm and action—A logical enquiry. Routledge.

  • Zvolenszky, Z. (2002). Is a possible-worlds semantics of modality possible? A problem for Kratzer’s semantics. In: Jackson, B. (ed.) Proceedings of the 12th Semantics and Linguistic Theory Conference (pp 339–358).

Download references

Acknowledgements

The authors would like to thank Alessandra Marra, Paul McNamara, Piotr Kulicki, and the anonymous reviewers for their valuable remarks and comments.

Funding

Huimin Dong is supported by the National Social Science Fund of China (No. 20CZX051, No. 17ZDA026) and the National Science Centre of Poland (No. UMO-2017/26/M/HS1/01092). Both authors are supported by the PIOTR research project (No. RO 4548/4-1).

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Huimin Dong.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Dong, H., Roy, O. Dynamic Logic of Legal Competences. J of Log Lang and Inf 30, 701–724 (2021). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10849-021-09340-z

Download citation

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10849-021-09340-z

Keywords

Navigation