Skip to main content
Log in

The Sense of Agency and the Epistemology of Thinking

  • Original Research
  • Published:
Erkenntnis Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

This paper motivates a constraint on how to explain the “sense of agency” for conscious thinking. It argues that a prominent model fails to satisfy the constraint before sketching an alternative that does. On the alternative, punctate acts of conscious thinking, such as episodes of inner speech, are recognizable as our deeds because they are recognizable as parts of complex cognitive activities, which we know non-observationally in virtue of holding intentions to perform them.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. The literature on the senses of ownership and agency is extensive. For ownership see Martin (1995), the essays collected in Roessler and Eilan (2003), Zahavi (2005), and Musholt (2015). For the sense of agency, in addition to the essays discussed below, see Bayne (2008).

  2. For an opposing view, see Machery (2018), who argues that because inner speech is communication, and so governed by pragmatic norms, it isn’t an instance of thinking.

  3. This is consistent with denying, as I did in the last paragraph, that we can get a grip on the idea of a sense of agency for conscious thinking through reflection on phenomenal contrast cases, as we might for intentional bodily action.

  4. See Saks (2007) for a compelling memoir about schizophrenia and Mellor (1970) for discussion of its symptoms.

  5. That leaves open the question whether we are in fact justified in taking our conscious thinking as our own doing. Perhaps we are under an illusion. I assume we are not, and am inclined to assume that an account of the sense of agency ought to explain our objective justification for taking thinking as our deed. But I won’t pursue that here.

  6. So-named for John Campbell, whose 1998 argued for the thesis and influenced much of the contemporary work that tries to answer the normative question about the sense of agency by a backwards inference from reflection on the inserted thought delusion.

  7. This is a point made familiar by so-called “two-factor” accounts of delusions. See Davies et al. (2001).

  8. This assumes delusions are beliefs, of course. But nothing here hangs on that assumption. See Bortolotti (2009) for discussion.

  9. I remain neutral here on the explanation of the positive content of delusions of thought insertion. Karl Jaspers notoriously claimed that delusions are “ununderstandable” (1913). Much of the literature on delusions has denied this, and aimed to make sense of how delusions arise (what Jaspers calls achieving “genetic understanding” or empathy, ibid. 17) (see Thornton 2007 for discussion.) But one thing that Jaspers might be taken to mean is that the specific positive content of delusions cannot be given an empathetic, rationalizing explanation. (I’m indebted to a conversation with Matt Parrott for this.).

  10. Thanks to an anonymous referee for help clarifying how best to capture the view.

  11. Thanks to an anonymous referee for this.

  12. Furthermore, if you think that we come to know our attitudes by introspecting inner speech (Machery 2018), then it looks like the agency as endorsement model has things backwards.

  13. It is rare, of course, for one’s inner speech to be so elaborate. Fernyhough (2016) points out that inner speech is often compressed, akin to personal notes. But presumably anything one can say in outer speech one can mutter in inner speech. So there is no harm imagining a case like this, even if it is atypical in certain respects.

  14. See McDowell (2011) and Bratman’s rejection of the “simple view” in his 1987.

  15. Other purported counterexamples are obsessive thoughts and mind-wandering. See O’Brien (2013) for a compelling defense of the claim that obsessive thoughts are active phenomena. See Metzinger (2013) for the view that mind-wandering involves a loss of autonomy and Irving (2016) for the view that it is unguided thinking. Finally, see Shepherd (2019) for the claim that mind-wandering is a search for a more rewarding goal guided by the cognitive control system. Although his view is more amenable to the present account, Shepherd notes that in the relevant cases subjects do not report an intention to engage in mind-wandering. One question to consider here is whether we possess practical knowledge of the constituent elements of mind-wandering. One may not intend to wander, but one may have practical knowledge of recalling this or and that, and then imagining something, and so on. One’s action isn’t intentional under the description “mind-wandering”, but its constituent elements are. (See my discussion of O’Shaughnessy on daydreaming for this option.) Unfortunately, I don’t have the space to consider this here. Thanks to an anonymous referee for raising this issue.

  16. Or, as Brian O’Shaughnessy puts it: “…the main processive constituents of the stream of consciousness of the conscious are intentionally active phenomena” (2000, 200).

  17. You might think such cases of “idle active drift” are not subject to Anscombe’s special sense of the question “why?” where an answer gives the agent’s reasons (1957). That’s because it isn’t clear that such actions are performed for reasons at all, at least normative practical reasons. Again, O’Shaughnessy is on to something when he writes that: “just why these rather than those intentions arose as the process advanced is a matter upon which one may lack authority and insight” (2000, 219). However, if answering the question why involves citing the activity of which a particular stretch of thinking formed is a part, then it would seem that this question can be answered even in cases of daydreaming. (See Thompson 2007 on such “naïve” action explanation.).

  18. Thanks to an anonymous referee for raising this issue.

References

  • Anscombe, G. E. M. (1957). Intention. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bayne, T. (2008). The phenomenology of agency. Philosophy Compass, 3(1), 182–202.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bermudez, J. L. (2011). Bodily awareness and self-consciousness. In S. Gallagher (Ed.), Oxford handbook of the self (pp. 157–179). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bermudez, J. L. (2019). Bodily ownership, psychological ownership, and psychopathology. Review of Philosophy and Psychology, 10(2), 263–280.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bortolotti, L. (2009). Delusions and other irrational beliefs. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Campbell, J. (1999). Schizophrenia, the space of reasons, and thinking as a motor process. The Monist, 82(4), 609–625.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Davidson, D. (1980). Essays on actions and events. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Davies, M., Coltheart, M., Langdon, R., & Breen, N. (2001). Monothematic delusions: Towards a two-factor account. Philosophy, Psychiatry, and Psychology, 8(2/3), 133–158.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Doyle, C. (2018). Agency and observation in knowledge of one’s own thinking. European Journal of Philosophy, 27(1), 148–161.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fernandez, J. (2010). Thought insertion and self-knowledge. Mind Language, 25(1), 66–88.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fernandez, J. (2013). Transparent minds. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Fernyhough, C. (2016). The voices within: The history and science of how we talk to ourselves. London: Basic Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Frankfurt, H. (1971). Freedom of the will and the concept of a person. Journal of Philosophy, 68(1), 5–20.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Frith, C. D. (1992). The cognitive neuropsychology of schizophrenia. Hove: Erlbaum (UK) Taylor & Francis.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gauker, C. (2018). Inner speech as the internalization of outer speech. In P. Langland-Hassan & A. Vicente (Eds.), Inner speech: New voices (pp. 53–77). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gibbons, J. (2010). Seeing what you’re doing. Oxford Studies in Epistemology, 3, 63–85.

    Google Scholar 

  • Graham, G., & Stephens, L. (2000). When self-consciousness breaks. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hoerl, C. (2001). On thought insertion. Philosophy, Psychiatry and Psychology, 8(2/3), 189–200.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hulburt, R. T., Heavey, C., & Kelsey, J. (2013). Toward a phenomenology of inner speaking. Consciousness and Cognition, 22, 1477–1494.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hurlburt, R. T., & Akhter, S. A. (2006). The descriptive experience sampling method. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 5, 271–301.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hulburt, R., & Heavy, C. (2018). Inner speech as pristine inner experience. In P. Langland-Hassan & A. Vicente (Eds.), Inner speech: New voices. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Irving, Z. (2016). Mind-wandering is unguided attention: Accounting for the ‘purposefu’ wanderer. Philosophical Studies, 173, 547–571.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jaspers, K. ([1913] 1997). General psychopathology. trans. J. Hoenig & M.W. Hamilton. Baltimore, MD: Johns Hopkins University Press.

  • Langland-Hassan, P. (2018). From inner speech to essence: The auditory nature of inner speech. In P. Langland-Hassan & A. Vicente (Eds.), Inner speech: New voices ((pp. 78–104)). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Leite, A. (2018). Changing one’s mind: Self-conscious belief and rational endorsement. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 97(1), 150–171.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Machery, E. (2018). Know thyself: Beliefs vs desires in inner speech. In P. Langland-Hassan & A. Vicente (Eds.), Inner speech: New voices (pp. 261–275). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Martin, M. G. F. (1995). Bodily awareness: A sense of ownership. In J. L. Bermúdez, A. Marcel, & N. Eilan (Eds.), The body and the self (pp. 267–289). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • McDowell, J. (2011). Some remarks on intention in action. The Amherst Lecture in Philosophy, 6, 1–18.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mellor, C. H. (1970). First rank symptoms of schizophrenia. British Journal of Psychiatry, 117(536), 15–23.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Metzinger, T. (2013). The myth of cognitive agency: Subpersonal thinking as a cyclically recurring loss of mental autonomy. Frontiers in Psychology. https://doi.org/10.3389/fpsyg.2013.00931.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Moran, R. (2001). Authority and estrangement. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Moran, R. 2004. Anscombe on ‘practical knowledge’. In Agency and Action, Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement 55: 43–68. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

  • Musholt, K. (2015). Thinking about oneself: From nonconceptual content to the concept of a self. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Nichols, S., & Stich, S. (2001). Mind-reading. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • O’Shaughnessy, B. (2000). Consciousness and the world. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • O’Brien, L. (2007). Self-knowing agents. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • O’Brien, L. (2013). Obsessive thoughts and inner voices. Philosophical Issues, 23, 93–108.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Peacocke, C. (1999). Being known. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Pickard, H. (2010). Schizophrenia and the epistemology of self-knowledge. European Journal of Analytic Philosophy, 6(1), 55–74.

    Google Scholar 

  • Proust, J. (2009). Is there a sense of agency for thought? In L. O’Brien & M. Soteriou (Eds.), Mental actions (pp. 253–279). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Roessler, J. (2013). Thought insertion, self-awareness, and rationality. In K. Fulford, et al. (Eds.), Oxford handbook of philosophy and psychiatry (pp. 658–672). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Roessler, J., & Eilan, N. (Eds.). (2003). Agency and self-awareness: Issues in philosophy and psychology (pp. 383–405). Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ryle, G. (1949). The concept of mind. London: Hutchinson.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ryle, G. (2009). Collected essays 1929–1968. London: Routledge.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Saks, E. (2007). The centre cannot hold: A memoir of my schizophrenia. London: Virago.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schear, J. (2009). Experience and self-consciousness. Philosophical Studies, 144, 95–105.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schwenkler, J. (2011). Perception and practical knowledge. Philosophical Explorations, 14(2), 137–152.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Setiya, K. (2007). Reasons without rationalism. Princeton University Press.

  • Shepherd, J. (2019). Why does the mind wander? Neuroscience of Consciousness, 1, 1–9. https://doi.org/10.1093/nc/niz014.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Soteriou, M. (2013). The mind’s construction. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Thompson, M. (2007). Life and action. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Thornton, T. (2007). Essential philosophy of psychiatry. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Velleman, J. D. (1989). Practical reflection. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wilkinson, S., & Ferynhough, C. (2018). When inner speech misleads. In P. Langland-Hassan & A. Vicente (Eds.), Inner speech: New voices (pp. 244–260). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zahavi, Dan. (2005). Subjectivity and selfhood: Investigating the first-person perspective. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Zahavi, D., & Kriegel, U. (2015). For-me-ness: What it is and what it is not. In D. Dahlstrom, A. Elpidorou, & W. Hopp (Eds.), Philosophy of mind and phenomenology (pp. 36–53). Abingdon: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

Thanks to Anita Avramides, Christian Coseru, an audience at St Hilda’s College, Oxford, and two anonymous referees for helpful feedback on this paper.

Funding

This article was supported by the project “International mobilities for research activities of the University of Hradec Králové”, CZ.02.2.69/0.0/0.0/16_027/0008487.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Casey Doyle.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Doyle, C. The Sense of Agency and the Epistemology of Thinking. Erkenn 87, 2589–2608 (2022). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10670-020-00317-1

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10670-020-00317-1

Navigation