Skip to main content
Log in

Abstract

This paper proposes a semiotic theory of norms—what I term normative semiotics. The paper’s central contention is that social norms are a language. Moreover, it is a language that we instinctively learn to speak. Normative behaviour is a mode of communication, the intelligibility of which allows us to establish cooperative relationships with others. Normative behaviour communicates an actor’s potential as a cooperative partner. Compliance with a norm is an act of communication: compliance signals cooperativeness; noncompliance signals uncooperativeness. An evolutionary model is proposed to explain how this comes about: evolution has generated an instinctual proficiency in working with these signals much like a language—a proficiency that manifests in an emotional context. We see these social rules as possessing a certain ‘rightness’ in normative terms. This adaptive trait is what we call internalization. Internalization enhances the individual’s ability to speak this code. Because these signals communicate who is and who is not a reliable co-operator, sending and receiving cooperation signals is crucial to individual survival. Individuals who internalized the entire process and thus became more adept at speaking the language were at an advantage. Law seeks to shape the language of norms by maintaining the collective standards of society; as such, understanding how and why this normative language emerges is critical to understanding a core function of law.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. I borrow the question from Peyton Young. See Young [42, p. 6].

  2. This idea formed the core underpinning to my doctoral work at King’s College London and is the subject of a book I am currently writing.

  3. For norms that involve negative injunctions, this takes the form of restraining one’s behaviour; for example, refraining from littering and instead carrying the garbage to the nearest trashcan.

  4. See Barthes [4, p. 9]. See also Eco [11, p. 8].

  5. The term “normative semiotics” is appears in some of the semiotic literature; however, the meaning here is markedly distinct from past usages of the term.

  6. See, e.g., Leary [22, p. 129] “Since Darwin … all theories of emotion have assumed that the capacity for emotional experience evolved because it had adaptive value in helping organisms deal with recurrent challenges and opportunities in their physical and social environments.” (footnotes omitted).

  7. See Mahoney et al. [25, p. 2027]. See also, e.g., Ellickson [13, p. 35].

  8. A primary difference is that Posner pins his theory entirely on a rational choice model, choosing to completely ignore internalization. See Posner [31]. As well, I do not think cost is necessary to explain norms; the mere act of compliance is enough to signal cooperation.

  9. Note this definition crucially includes abstract opinions and views, as these have the potential to be communicated to others and so can be understood as a form of behaviour.

  10. I am in good company: Robert Cooter also asserts a norm only exists if it has been internalized. See Cooter [8, pp. 1661–1666].

  11. However, this is not to imply that norms can never also possess a functional character. Often their functional characteristic is their chief feature and only standardize as signals thereafter.

  12. Norms of course take the form of negative as well as positive injunctions, prescribing a course of action or inaction as the case may be.

  13. E.g. phonological, syntactical, lexical, prosodic and paralinguistic subcodes.

  14. The word “economic” here is used in its most sweeping sense: cooperation to ensure survival.

  15. Of course, not all preferences are triggered by signalling; but all normative intuitions are.

  16. See Nucci [28, p. 77], Sripada et al. [36, p. 284].

  17. See. e.g., Asch [1], Sherif [34]. For a broad survey of this literature, see Cialdini et al. [7, pp. 630–634, 642–644].

  18. See Hurley [19], Raafat et al. [32], Berns et al. [5], Klucharev et al. [20], Wild et al. [40], Nummenmaa et al. [29], Guyer et al. [17]. See also Damasio [10, pp. 173–180], Moll [27, p. 806].

  19. Many rational choice theorists in fact employ evolutionary models that presuppose this kind of bounded rationality to explain norm emergence. See, e.g., Axelrod [2], Skyrms [35], Young [41]. See also, e.g., Sunstein [38], Korobkin [21].

  20. Indeed, Frank sees the emotions as the progenitor of moral behaviour rather than rational decisions. See Frank [14, pp. 51–56].

  21. Robert Trivers famously presented a similar idea in his 1971 paper The Evolution of Reciprocal Altruism, though not in terms of signalling. Trivers argued that due to the difficulty involved in computing the complex cost–benefit ratios that underpin long-term reciprocity, human emotions evolved as a regulating mechanism. See Trivers [39].

  22. Herbert Gintis argues that the ability to internalize norms evolves as it enhances individual fitness in situations where social behaviour has become too complex to be evaluated piecemeal through individual rational assessment. See Gintis [15].

  23. I radically diverge from Posner here; he believes that a normative act must be rationally chosen to qualify as a signal.

  24. Two other problems arise when we embrace such a problem but are not dealt with here. First, why would norms that are consistently inefficient, such as samurai ritual suicide, emerge? Second, if internalization is advantageous, why do some actors not do so? The answer to the first is that we are conditioned to internalize a norm’s cooperation signals, not the norm's content. At times these signals can go quite haywire in evolutionary terms as in the case of ritual suicide. The answer to the second is that some players adopt the evolutionary strategy of opportunism, and internalization would impede such a strategy at times.

  25. For example, animals certainly kill, but it is unclear if an animal can commit murder; we do not have the moral language for this, as we do not impose normative meaning on animal behaviour in the way we do for human behaviour.

  26. This provocative contention brings up some important questions. For one, why does normativity differ in intensity? That is, why is it more wrong to murder someone than to push them out of your way? The answer is that acts will vary in terms of their normative intensity commensurate with how powerfully they signal non-cooperation. An actor who pushes someone may still have some cooperative potential; the murderer does not. Another question is why do cultures exhibit quite a bit of normative consistency? The answer to this is that many acts are natural candidates to standardize as cooperation signals in that they naturally signal non-cooperation, e.g. murder, theft, or cannibalism.

  27. Early traces are arguably found in David Hume questioning how an ‘ought’ could be extracted from an “is.” See Hume [18, p. 469]. For a more contemporary and comprehensive account of moral scepticism see Mackie [24]. The branch of analytic philosophy known as meta-ethics addresses this idea extensively. The reader is referred to this fascinating (and relatively active) area of philosophy, specifically non-cognitivist approaches such as emotivism (which holds that moral propositions are merely expressions of emotion).

References

  1. Asch, S.E. 1955. Opinions and social pressure. Scientific American 193: 31–37.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  2. Axelrod, R. 1997. The complexity of cooperation: Agent-based models of competition and collaboration. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  3. Baird, D., et al. 1994. Game theory and the law. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  4. Barthes, R. 1967. Système de la mode. New York: French & European Pubns.

    Google Scholar 

  5. Berns, G.S., et al. 2005. Neurobiological correlates of social conformity and independence during mental rotation. Biological Psychiatry 58: 245–253.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  6. Chandler, D. 2007. Semiotics: The basics. New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  7. Cialdini, R.B. et al. Social Influence: Social Norms, Conformity, and Compliance. In The handbook of social psychology, ed. D.T. Gilbert, et al., 151, New York: McGraw-Hill.

  8. Cooter, R. 1996. Decentralized law for a complex economy: The structural approach to adjudicating the new law merchant. University of Pennsylvania Law Review 144: 1643–1696.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  9. Cooter, R. 1998. Law from order: Economic development and the jurisprudence of social norms. John M. Olin Working Papers in Law.

  10. Damasio, A. 1994. Descartes’ error: Emotion, reason, and the human brain. New York: Harper Perennial.

    Google Scholar 

  11. Eco, U. 1978. A theory of semiotics. Bloomington: Indiana University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  12. Ellickson, R. 1998. Law and economics discovers social norms. Journal of Legal Studies 27: 537–552.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  13. Ellickson, R. 2001. The evolution of social norms: A perspective from the legal academy. In Social Norms ed. M. Hechter et al., 35–75. New York: Russell Sage Foundation.

  14. Frank, R. 1988. Passions within reason: The strategic role of the emotions. New York: W.W. Norton & Company.

    Google Scholar 

  15. Gintis, H. 2003. The hitchhiker’s guide to altruism: Gene-culture coevolution, and the internalization of norms. Journal of Theoretical Biology 220: 407–418.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  16. Goodman, R. 2001. Beyond the enforcement principle: Sodomy laws, social norms, and social panoptics. California Law Review 89: 643–740.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  17. Guyer, A.E., et al. 2009. Probing the neural correlates of anticipated peer evaluation in adolescence. Child Development 80: 1000–1015.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  18. Hume, D. 1740. A treatise on human nature book 3. Oxford: Oxford University Press. 1978.

  19. Hurley, S.L., et al. 2005. Perspectives on imitation: From neuroscience to social science. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  20. Klucharev, V., et al. 2009. Reinforcement learning signal predicts social conformity. Neuron 61: 140–151.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  21. Korobkin, R., et al. 2000. Law and behavioral science: Removing the rationality assumption from law and economics. California Law Review 88: 1051–1144.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  22. Leary, M.R. Digging deeper: The fundamental nature of “self-conscious” emotions. Psychological Inquiry 15: 129–131.

  23. Lessig, L. 1995. The regulation of social meaning. The University of Chicago Law Review 62: 943–1045.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  24. Mackie, J.L. 1990. Ethics: Inventing right and wrong. London: Penguin.

    Google Scholar 

  25. Mahoney, P., et al. 2001. Competing norms and social evolution: Is the fittest norm efficient? University of Pennsylvania Law Review 149: 2027–2062.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  26. Mcadams, R. 1997. The origin, development, and regulation of norms. Michigan Law Review 96: 338–433.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  27. Moll, J., et al. 2005. The neural basis of human moral cognition. Nature Reviews 6: 806.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  28. Nucci, L. 2005. Moral development and character formation. In Value education and education for human rights, ed. V.C. Pandey, 66–120. Delhi: Gyan Publishing House.

    Google Scholar 

  29. Nummenmaa, L., et al. 2008. Is emotional contagion special? An fMRI study on neural systems for affective and cognitive empathy. Neuroimage 43: 571–580.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  30. Ostrom, E. 2000. Collective action and the evolution of social norms. Journal of Economic Perspectives 14: 137–158.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  31. Posner, E. 2000. Law and social norms. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  32. Raafat, R.M., et al. 2009. Herding in humans. Trends in Cognitive Sciences 13: 420–428.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  33. Scott, R.E. 2000. The limits of behavioral theories of law and social norms. Virginia Law Review 86: 1603–1647.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  34. Sherif, M. 1937. An experimental approach to the study of attitudes. Sociometry 1: 90–98.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  35. Skyrms, B. 1996. Evolution of the social contract. New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  36. Sripada, C., et al. 2006. A framework for the psychology of norms. In The innate mind: Culture and cognition, ed. P. Carruthers, et al., 280–301. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  37. Sunstein, C. 1996. Social norms and social roles. Columbia Law Review 96: 903–968.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  38. Sunstein, C. 2000. Behavioral law and economics. New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  39. Trivers, R.L. 1971. The evolution of reciprocal altruism. Quarterly Review of Biology 46: 35–57.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  40. Wild, B., et al. 2001. Are emotions contagious? Evoked emotions while viewing emotionally expressive faces: Quality, quantity, time course and gender differences. Psychiatry Researcher 102: 109–124.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  41. Young, H. 1998. Individual strategy and social structure: An evolutionary theory of institutions. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  42. Young, H. 2007. Social norms. University of Oxford Department of Economics Discussion Paper Series No. 307, 6.

Download references

Acknowledgments

I want to thank Prof. Eric Posner at the University of Chicago for his helpful comments and suggestions and Dr. Andreas Dimopoulos (PhD, Cantab.) at Brunel University in London for taking the time to help proofread this draft. Of course, any errors are entirely my own.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Bryan H. Druzin.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Druzin, B.H. Eating Peas with One’s Fingers: A Semiotic Approach to Law and Social Norms. Int J Semiot Law 26, 257–274 (2013). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11196-012-9271-z

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11196-012-9271-z

Keywords

Navigation