Skip to main content
Log in

Pretense: the context of possibilities

  • Published:
Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

In this paper, we deal with the issue of how it is possible for pretending children to engage in exploratory performances and entertain alternative states of affairs. We question the approach according to which pretenders must be capable of counterfactual reasoning. Instead, we follow an alternative action-based framework on cognition and thus pretense, which argues for a much more profound role of the context of play than the questioned Counterfactual Thinking Approach to Pretense (CTAP). First, we motivate this shift in theoretical perspective by critiquing CTAP and providing arguments in favor of the action-based alternative we endorse. Then, we demonstrate that the action-based framework allows for a fruitful analysis of pretense in terms of its context rather than (solely) mind-internal processes. This paper proposes that (1) thematic play-frames enable unusual manipulations with objects and words, and invite dynamic interactions between players who can discover new possibilities for action and communication, as well as that (2) pretense contexts understood generally as opposed to non-pretense contexts have selected features—specifically the adults’ approval of playing with cultural norms, the looseness of constraints, and the lack of particular goals leading to children’s positive feelings—that are genuinely conducive to play explorations. Finally, we discuss other contexts of possibilities, as well as the educational prospects of particular context-to-context transmissions.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. To utilize the well-known example, a frog sitting on the bank of a river can anticipate certain possibilities of interaction with the world: for instance, it can anticipate that tongue flicking will result in a fly being caught and digestive processes ensuing, or that jumping slightly forward will afford swimming in the river and shelter it from a flying predator. These anticipations can be false and the potential falsity can be discovered by the frog: all it takes is for the frog to actually try flicking its tongue or jumping into water; if the world does not support the anticipated interaction, then the organism-internal part of the process will destabilize and thus be falsified. Thus, situation representations and its particular aspects can be argued to have truth value.

  2. By questioning the view that basic pretense is founded on counterfactual thinking that relies on a few specific representational abilities, e.g. on representing falsity as if it were true (see: paragraph 2.1.), we do not want to question simultaneously that pretending involves some forms of representations, such as (noticeably) the situation representations described above. Representations required for counterfactual reasoning are one thing, and representations required for basic pretending are other thing. If we undermine the role of mental representations in pretense in this paper, this should only be understood in the former sense. We acknowledge, though, that some advanced forms of pretense might likely be founded on counterfactual reasoning, and—therefore—by mental representations that are specific to it.

  3. We admit it as highly likely that older pretenders, who are already advanced language users, can be exploring possibilities internally through their counterfactual thoughts. However, such a prospect does not diminish what we want to achieve with this paper, thus to provide an apt alternative account of pretense that accentuates its contextual features. We cannot, after all, not admit it as highly likely that even older pretenders—who are fully capable of reasoning counterfactually—are still interactively influenced by the contextual factors of pretense.

  4. These authors have applied the similar research paradigm (differing only in the stories presented) as the one first proposed by Harris et al., (1996) who introduced to children a story about Carol walking across the clean floor wearing dirty shoes, and then asked them ‘What if Carol had taken her shoes off, would the floor be dirty?‘. Interestingly, Harris et al. have shown that children are able to answer these questions correctly starting from 3 years of age. This confronts us with the problem of inconclusiveness in the empirical data on the development of counterfactual thinking. Still, we have decided to refer to this data as we can spot the general developmental trend indicated by all the referenced studies, which is that 2-year-olds—who can already engage is some basic forms of pretense—have serious problems with reasoning explicitly in a counterfactual manner.

  5. Such postulates are what Lakatos (1970) has famously recognized as the metaphysical “hard core” of a theory or a research program, which can be defended in principle indefinitely. It is always possible to formulate what Lakatos terms an auxiliary hypothesis that claims some issue in measurement or performance that has interfered with the actual results of the study, and thus continue to hold one’s theory unscathed (or make an ad hoc theoretical adjustment).

  6. Lakatos himself did not allow for theoretical arguments about underlying metaphysics; he believed that a research program can only gradually become unproductive and replaced if there is another more fruitful model available–that is, he only allowed for the latter route we mention above. The present paper builds on that latter option, so the issue can be left open, but we wish to direct the reader to the work that argues for the legitimacy of theoretical arguments, e.g. Campbell & Bickhard (1986).

  7. Nonetheless, we do not want to rule out the possibility that counterfactual norms could be implemented by pretenders at the action level and would be interpreted or read by others directly from pretense actions, and not by any intellectual means (e.g. children would pretend to pour out the tea from the cup even though they are not aware of the logic of counterfactual conditionals). We avoid juxtaposing notions taken psychologically and logically then, as we are talking about a certain action, a bit like logical thinking (its source) was described by Piaget (1963). (For more discussion between logical versus psychological norms of thinking, see: Gut 2015).

  8. Some authors would claim that to follow the “illusion conservation rule” would be to simultaneously hold two separate representations in mind: the primary representation of what is real and the secondary representation of what is pretended (see: Leslie 1987, 1994; Perner, 1991). We would, however, be willing to offer an alternative explanation of how it is possible to comply with the “illusion conservation rule” without representing things mentally. Namely, specific contextual and interactional factors could be pointed out as ones making the difference between what is pretended and what is not. We have touched on this topic a few paragraphs above.

  9. Enjoyment is often included in the definition of play. For example, in the online Cambridge Dictionary it is stated that “When you play, especially as a child, you spend time doing an enjoyable and/or entertaining activity”. It can also happen, though, that play becomes an unpleasant experience for some children, even turning into one that is frightening or repulsive to them—an activity being occasionally labelled as “evil play” (e.g., Schousboe 2013). Still, even an “evil play”—as we see it after analyzing a few cases of it—seems to be bringing pleasure and excitement to part of the group who engage in this type of activity, only becoming unpleasant for one or few of them. Nevertheless, discussing such “evil” manifestations of play is beyond the scope of this paper, as we want to focus here on the more common non-malicious forms of play.

  10. The inspiration for this claim comes from the interactivist model of emotion, see, e.g. Bickhard (2003).

References

  • Allen, J. W., & Bickhard, M. H. (2013). Stepping off the pendulum: Why only an action-based approach can transcend the nativist–empiricist debate. Cognitive Development, 28(2), 96–133. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.cogdev.2013.01.002

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Amsel, E., & Smalley, J. D. (2000). Beyond really and truly. In P. Mitchell, & K. J. Riggs (Eds.), Children’s reasoning and the mind (pp. 121–147). Hove, UK: Psychology Press

    Google Scholar 

  • Ariel, S., Carel, C. A., & Tyano, S. (1985). Uses of children’s make believe play in family therapy. Journal of Marital and Family Therapy, 11(1), 47–60

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Beck, S. R., & Guthrie, C. (2011). Almost thinking counterfactually: children’s understanding of close counterfactuals. Child Development, 82(4), 1189–1198

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Beck, S. R., & Riggs, K. J. (2013). The development of counterfactual reasoning. In H. Markovits (Ed.), The developmental psychology of reasoning and decision making (pp. 165–181). New York: Psychology Press

    Google Scholar 

  • Bermudez, J. L. (2014). Cognitive Science: An Introduction to the Science of the Mind (2nd ed.). New York: Cambridge University Press

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Bickhard, M. H. (1980). Cognition, convention, and communication. New York N.Y.: Praeger

    Google Scholar 

  • Bickhard, M. H. (1993). Representational content in humans and machines. Journal of Experimental & Theoretical Artificial Intelligence, 5(4), 285–333. https://doi.org/10.1080/09528139308953775

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bickhard, M. H. (1998). Levels of representationality. Journal of Experimental & Theoretical Artificial Intelligence, 10(2), 179–215. https://doi.org/10.1080/095281398146824

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bickhard, M. H. (2000). Motivation and Emotion: An Interactive Process Model. In R. D. Ellis, & N. Newton (Eds.), The Caldron of Consciousness (pp. 161–178). Amsterdam: John Benjamins Publishing Company

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Bickhard, M. H. (2003). An integration of motivation and cognition. In L. Smith, C. Rogers, & P. Tomlinson (Eds.), Monograph series II: Psychological aspects of education -current trends: no.2. Development and motivation: Joint perspectives / edited by Leslie Smith, Colin Rogers and Peter Tomlinson (pp. 41–56). Leicester: The British Psychological Society

    Google Scholar 

  • Bickhard, M. H. (2009). The interactivist model. Synthese, 166(3), 547–591. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-008-9375-x

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bickhard, M. H. (2015). The Social-Interactive Ontology of Language. Ecological Psychology, 27(3), 265–277. https://doi.org/10.1080/10407413.2015.1068656

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bickhard, M. H., & Richie, D. M. (1983). On the nature of representation: A case study of James Gibson’s theory of perception / Mark H. Bickhard, D. Michael Richie with Robert Hughes, James Dannemiller. New York, NY, USA: Praeger. https://doi.org/10.1057/9781137400437.0005

  • Bickhard, M. H., & Terveen, L. (1995). Foundational issues in artificial intelligence and cognitive science: Impasse and solution. Advances in psychology: Vol. 109. Amsterdam, New York: Elsevier

    Google Scholar 

  • Bretherton, I. (1989). Pretense: The form and function of make-believe play. Developmental Review, 9(4), 383–401

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brooks, R. A. (1991). Intelligence without representation. Artificial Intelligence, 47(1–3), 139–159. https://doi.org/10.1016/0004-3702(91)90053-M

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bruner, J. S. (1990). Acts of meaning. The Jerusalem-Harvard lectures. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press

    Google Scholar 

  • Bruineberg, J., & Rietveld, E. (2014). Self-organization, free energy minimization, and optimal grip on a field of affordances. Frontiers in Human Neuroscience, 8, 599. https://doi.org/10.3389/fnhum.2014.00599

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Campbell, R. L., & Bickhard, M. H. (1986). Knowing levels and developmental stages. Contributions to human development: Vol. 16. Basel: S. Karger

  • Carlson, S. M., Taylor, M., & Levin, G. R. (1998). The Influence of Culture on Pretend Play: The Case of Mennonite Children. Merrill-Palmer Quarterly, 44(4), 538–565

    Google Scholar 

  • Carpendale, J. I. M., & Lewis, C. (2006). How children develop social understanding. Understanding children’s worlds. Malden, Mass., Oxford: Blackwell Publishers

    Google Scholar 

  • Chomsky, N. (1965). Aspects of the theory of syntax (25. print). Special technical report of the Research Laboratory of Electronics of the Massachusetts Institute of Technology: Vol. 11. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press

  • Chylińska, M., & Gut, A. (2020). Pretend play as a creative action: On the exploratory and evaluative features of children’s pretense. Theory & Psychology, 30(4), 548–566

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Costall, A. (2012). Canonical affordances in context. AVANT. Trends in Interdisciplinary Studies, 3(2), 85–93

    Google Scholar 

  • Costall, A. (1995). Socializing affordances. Theory & Psychology, 5(4), 467–481

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • De Jaegher, H., & Di Paolo, E. A. (2007). Participatory sense-making. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 6(4), 485–507. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11097-007-9076-9

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Di Paolo, E. A., Cuffari, E. C., & de Jaegher, H. (2018). Linguistic bodies: The continuity between life and language. Cambridge MA: The MIT Press

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Di Paolo, E. A., & De Jaegher, H. (2008). Making sense in participation: An enactive approach to social cognition. In F. Morganti, A. Carassa, & G. Riva (Eds.), Emerging communication, 1566–7677: v. 10. Enacting intersubjectivity: A cognitive and social perspective on the study of interactions / edited by Francesca Morganti, Antonella Carassa and Giuseppe Riva. Amsterdam, Oxford: IOS Press

    Google Scholar 

  • Erdin, H. O., & Bickhard, M. H. (2018). Representing is something that we do, not a structure that we “use”: Reply to Gładziejewski. New Ideas in Psychology, 49, 27–37. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.newideapsych.2018.02.001

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fein, G. G. (1989). Mind, Meaning, and Affect: Proposals for a Theory of Pretense. Developmental Review, 9(4), 345–363

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Freud, A. (1965). Normality and Pathology in Childhood: Assessment of Development. New York: International Universities Press

    Google Scholar 

  • Fredrickson, B. L. (2004). The broaden-and-build theory of positive emotions. Philosophical transactions of the Royal Society of London. Series B, Biological sciences, 359(1449), 1367–1378

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fredrickson, B. L., & Branigan, C. (2005). Positive emotions broaden the scope of attention and thought-action repertoires. Cognition & Emotion, 19(3), 313–332

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gallagher, S., & Varga, S. (2014). Social constraints on the direct perception of emotions and intentions. Topoi, 33(1), 185–199

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Garvey, C., & Kramer, L. T. (1989). The language of social pretend play. Developmental Review, 9(4), 364–382

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gaskins, S. (1999). Children’s daily lives in a Mayan village: A case study of culturally constructed roles and activities. In A. Göncü (Ed.), Children’s engagement in the world (pp. 25–61). Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press

    Google Scholar 

  • Gee, J., (née Gerhardt, & Savasir, I. (1985). On the use of WILL and GONNA: Towards a description of activity-types for child language. Discourse Processes, 8, 143–175

  • Giffin, H. (1984). The coordination of meaning in the creation of a shared make-believe reality. In I. Bretherton (Ed.), Symbolic play: The development of social understanding (pp. 73–100). New York: Academic Press

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Ginsburg, G. P. (1980). Epilogue: A conception of situated action. In M. Brenner (Ed.), The structure of action (pp. 313–350). Oxford, England: Blackwell

    Google Scholar 

  • Göncü, A. (1993). Development of Intersubjectivity in Social Pretend Play. Human Development, 36(4), 185–198

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Göncü, A. (1989). Models and Features of Pretense. Developmental Review, 9(4), 341–344

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gopnik, A. (2009). The philosophical baby: What children’s minds tell us about truth, love, and the meaning of life. New York, NY: Farrar, Straus, and Giroux

    Google Scholar 

  • Gut, A. (2015). Overcoming Logical Psychologism. Polish Journal of Philosophy, 9(1), 7–32

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gut, A. (2005). Gottlob Frege i problemy współczesnej filozofii (Gottlob Frege and the problems of contemporary philosophy). Lublin: Wydawnictwo KUL

    Google Scholar 

  • Gut, A., & Mirski, R. (2016). In Search of a Theory: The Interpretative Challenge of Empirical Findings on Cultural Variance in Mindreading. Studies in Logic, Grammar and Rhetoric, 48(61), 201–230

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Haight, W., & Miller, P. J. (1992). Pretending at home: Early development in a sociocultural context. Albany: State University of New York Press

    Google Scholar 

  • Harris, P. L. (2000). The work of the imagination. Oxford: Blackwell Publishing

    Google Scholar 

  • Harris, P. L., German, T. P., & Mills, P. (1996). Children’s use of counterfactual-thinking in causal reasoning. Cognition, 61(3), 233–259

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Heimann, K. S., & Roepstorff, A. (2018). How Playfulness Motivates – Putative Looping Effects of Autonomy and Surprise Revealed by Micro-Phenomenological, Investigations. Frontiers in Psychology, 9, 1704

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hutto, D. D. (2015). Basic social cognition without mindreading: Minding minds without attributing contents. Synthese, 194(3), 827–846. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-015-0831-0

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hutto, D. D., & Myin, E. (2013). Radicalizing enactivism: Basic minds without content / Daniel D. Hutto and Erik Myin. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press

    Google Scholar 

  • Hutto, D. D., & Myin, E. (2017). Evolving enactivism: Basic minds meet content. Cambridge Massachusetts: MIT Press

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Karniol, R. (2016). A language-based, three-stage, social- interactional model of social pretend play: Acquiring pretend as an epistemic operator, pretending that, and pretending with (the P–PT–PW model). Developmental Review, 41, 1–37

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lakatos, I. (1970). Falsification and the Methodology of Scientific Research Programmes. In I. Lakatos, & A. Musgrave (Eds.), Criticism and the Growth of Knowledge (pp. 91–196). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Leslie, A. M. (1987). Pretense and Representation: The Origins of “Theory of Mind. Psychological Review, 94(4), 412–426

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Leslie, A. M. (1994). Pretending and believing: issues in the theory of ToMM. Cognition, 50(1–3), 211–238

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. (1973). Counterfactuals. Oxford: Blackwell Publishing

    Google Scholar 

  • Lieberman, J. N. (1977). Playfulness: Its relationship to imagination and creativity. New York: Academic Press

    Google Scholar 

  • Lillard, A. (2001). Pretend play as twin earth: A social-cognitive analysis. Developmental Review, 21(4), 495–531

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Manstead, A. S. R., & Fischer, A. (2000). Social Appraisal: The Social World As Object and Influence on Appraisal Processes. In K. R. Scherer, A. Schorr, & T. Johnstone (Eds.), Appraisal processes in emotion. Theory, methods, research (pp. 221–233). New York: Oxford University Press

    Google Scholar 

  • McCune-Nicolich, L. (1981). Toward symbolic functioning: Structure of early pretend games and potential parallels with language. Child Development, 52(3), 785–797

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mirski, R., & Bickhard, M. H. (2021). Conventional minds: An interactivist perspective on social cognition and its enculturation. New Ideas in Psychology, 62, 100856. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.newideapsych.2021.100856

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mirski, R., & Gut, A. (2018). Action-based versus cognitivist perspectives on socio-cognitive development: culture, language and social experience within the two paradigms. Synthese, 28(2), 96. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-018-01976-y

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Moors, A. (2020). Appraisal theory of emotion. In V. Zeigler-Hill, & T. K. Shackelford (Eds.), Encyclopedia of personality and individual differences (pp. 232–240). Springer International Publishing

  • Müller, U., Miller, M. R., Michalczyk, K., & Karapinka, A. (2007). False belief under- standing: The influence of person, grammatical mood, counterfactual reasoning, and working memory. British Journal of Developmental Psychology, 25(4), 615–632

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nichols, S., & Stich, S. (2000). A cognitive theory of pretense. Cognition, 74(2), 115–147

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nelson, K. (1986). Event knowledge: Structure and function in development. Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum

    Google Scholar 

  • Nelson, K. (2007). Young minds in social worlds: Experience, meaning, and memory / Katherine Nelson. Cambridge, Mass., London: Harvard University Press

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Nelson, K., Plesa, D., & Henseler, S. (1998). Children’s Theory of Mind: An Experiential Interpretation. Human Development, 41(1), 7–29. https://doi.org/10.1159/000022565

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Parrott, W. G., & Gleitman, H. (1989). Infants’ expectations in play: The joy of peek-a-boo. Cognition and Emotion, 3(4), 291–311

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Piaget, J. (1962). Play, Dreams and Imitation. New York: The Norton Library

    Google Scholar 

  • Piaget, J. (1963). The origins of intelligence in children. New York: W.W. Norton & Company

    Google Scholar 

  • Perner, J. (1991). Understanding the Representational Mind. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press

    Google Scholar 

  • Rafetseder, E., & Perner, J. (2012). When the alternative would have been better: Counterfactual reasoning and the emergence of regret. Cognition and Emotion, 26(5), 800–819

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rączaszek-Leonardi, J., Nomikou, I., Rohlfing, K. J., & Deacon, T. W. (2018). Language Development From an Ecological Perspective: Ecologically Valid Ways to Abstract Symbols. Ecological Psychology, 30(1), 39–73. https://doi.org/10.1080/10407413.2017.1410387

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Riggs, K. J., Peterson, D. M., Robinson, E. J., & Mitchell, P. (1998). Are errors in false belief tasks symptomatic of a broader difficulty with counterfactuality? Cognitive Development, 13(1), 73–90

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rucińska, Z. (2019). Social and Enactive Perspectives on Pretending. AVANT. Trends in Interdisciplinary Studies, 10(3), https://doi.org/10.26913/avant.2019.03.15

  • Rucińska, Z. (2017). The role of affordances in pretend play. In C. Durt, T. Fuchs, & C. Tewes (Eds.), Embodiment, enaction, and culture: Investigating the constitution of the shared world (pp. 257–278). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press

    Google Scholar 

  • Rucińska, Z. (2016). What Guides Pretence? Toward the Interactive and the Narrative Approaches. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 15(1), 117–133

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Russ, S. W. (2014). Pretend play in childhood: Foundation of adult creativity. Washington, DC: American Psychological Association

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Scherer, K. R., Schorr, A., & Johnstone, T. (2001). Appraisal Processes in Emotion: Theory, Methods, Research. Oxford: Oxford University Press

    Google Scholar 

  • Schousboe, I. (2013). The Structure of Fantasy Play and Its Implications for Good and Evil Games. In I. Schousboe, & D. Winther-Lindqvist (Eds.), Children’s play and development: Cultural-historical perspectives (pp. 13–27). Dordrecht, The Netherlands: Springer

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Singer, D. G., & Singer, J. L. (1990). The house of make-believe: Children’s play and the developing imagination. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Szokolszky, A. (2006). Pretend object play—Symbolic or functional?. In A. Costall, & O. Dreier (Eds.), Doing things with things: The design and use of everyday objects (pp. 67–85). Aldershot, England: Ashgate Publishing

    Google Scholar 

  • Szokolszky, A., & Read, C. (2021). Pretend play with objects: an ecological approach. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11097-021-09755-w

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Thelen, E., & Smith, L. B. (2002/1996). A dynamic systems approach to the development of cognition and action (5. print). A Bradford book. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press

  • Tomasello, M. (2002). Things Are What They Do: Katherine Nelson’s Functional Approach to Language and Cognition. Journal of Cognition and Development, 3(1), 5–19. https://doi.org/10.1207/S15327647JCD0301_2

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Van Gelder, T. (1998). The dynamical hypothesis in cognitive science.Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 21(5), 615 – 28; discussion 629 – 65.

  • Vygotsky, L. S. (1981). The Genesis of Higher Mental Functions. In J. V. Wertsch (Ed.), The Concept of Activity in Soviet Psychology. Armonk, NY: M. E. Sharpe

    Google Scholar 

  • Vygotsky, L. S. (1978). Mind in Society: The Development of Higher Psychological Processes. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press

    Google Scholar 

  • Weisberg, D. S. (2015). Pretend play. WIREs Cognitive Science, 6(3), 249–261

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Weisberg, D. S., & Gopnik, A. (2016). Which counterfactuals matter? A response to Beck. Cognitive Science, 40(1), 257–259

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Weisberg, D. S., & Gopnik, A. (2013). Pretense, counterfactuals, and Bayesian causal models: Why what is not real really matters. Cognitive Science, 37(7), 1368–1381

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Westra, E., & Carruthers, P. (2017). Pragmatic development explains the Theory-of-Mind Scale. Cognition, 158, 165–176. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.cognition.2016.10.021

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wittgenstein, L. (1953). Philosophical investigations. New York: Macmillan

    Google Scholar 

  • Woodward, J. (2011). Psychological studies of causual and counterfactual reasoning. In C. Hoerl, T. McCormack, & S. R. Beck (Eds.), Understanding caunterfactuals, understanding causation: Issues in psychology and philosophy (pp. 16–53). Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

We are sincerely grateful to Zuzanna Rucińska, Martin Weichold, Robert Mirski and three anonymous reviewers for their very helpful guidelines and comments on earlier versions of this paper.

Funding

“The project is funded by the Minister of Science and Higher Education within the program under the name “Regional Initiative of Excellence” in 2019–2022, project number: 028/RID/2018/19, the amount of funding: 11 742 500 PLN”.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Monika Dunin-Kozicka.

Ethics declarations

Conflict of interest

The authors have no conflicts of interest to declare. All authors have seen and agree with the contents of the manuscript and there is no financial interest to report. We certify that the submission is original work and is not under review at any other publication.

Additional information

Publisher’s note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Dunin-Kozicka, M., Gut, A. Pretense: the context of possibilities. Phenom Cogn Sci 21, 1107–1130 (2022). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11097-022-09816-8

Download citation

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11097-022-09816-8

Keywords

Navigation