Skip to main content

Fair Play Theories of Punishment

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
The Palgrave Handbook on the Philosophy of Punishment

Part of the book series: Palgrave Handbooks in the Philosophy of Law ((PHPL))

  • 452 Accesses

Abstract

Fair play theories of punishment locate the permissibility or desirability of legal punishment in its ability to restore relations of fairness between lawbreakers and other members of society. This chapter discusses the chief objection leveled against such views, which is that many crimes do not yield any benefit for the offender and thus do not create unfair advantages of the sort punishment is supposedly to correct. Duus-Otterström argues that, while this objection squarely hits traditional versions of the fair play theory that emphasize benefits deriving from committing crime, it is less persuasive against versions that emphasize losses inflicted by crime or the offender’s lack of entitlement to the benefits of the legal order.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 169.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 219.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 219.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    The fair play theory of political obligation holds that the moral duty of citizens to obey the law stems from the expectation that mutually beneficial compliance be repaid in kind. The theory was set out in systematic form by Hart (1955) and Rawls (1999). Its contemporary defenders include Klosko (2004, 2005) and Dagger (2018). For criticism, see, e.g., Simmons (2001, chs. 1–2) and Wellman (2001).

  2. 2.

    Another prominent early defender of the fair play theory was Jeffrie Murphy (1971, 1973).

  3. 3.

    The main aim of Morris’s (1968) essay is to defend punishment over the “therapy model” as an institution of social control. Morris’s argument is that punishment, unlike the therapy model, respects persons as autonomous agents.

  4. 4.

    A corollary of this is that, if all people were to break a law, then it would not be justified to punish someone for breaking it. This is because breaking the law would not produce an unfair advantage.

  5. 5.

    In the social sciences, however, it is common to argue that “punishment” (here understood as the imposition of a cost) is essential for solving public goods problems since it assures people that they will not be rendered “suckers” by contributing to collective action. For a classical statement of this kind of view, see Runge (1984).

  6. 6.

    There are some doubts about whether fair play retributivism is about desert as much as it is about paying debts (Boonin 2008, 122). I shall not delve into this debate here, but since the fair play theory holds that lawbreakers commit a moral wrong, it has no apparent problem in saying that lawbreakers deserve punishment in a familiar sense of “deserves” (e.g., that it would be impersonally and non-instrumentally good or just to punish them).

  7. 7.

    Moore is alive to the political questions (1997, 739–95).

  8. 8.

    That political legitimacy might be a precondition for justified punishment has been explored with particular clarity in the debate about moral standing. See Duff (2001, 179–96) and Tadros (2009) for influential treatments. For examples of penal theories that do not vest any fundamental importance in political legitimacy, see Thorburn (2012) and Duus-Otterström and Kelly (2019).

  9. 9.

    The no-benefit objection is my way of crystallizing a worry many people have had about the fair play theory (e.g., Burgh 1982; Dolinko 1991; Hampton 1991; Duff 2008). I state it more fully in Duus-Otterström (2017); see also Falls (1987). Note that “benefit” is vague between “being better off than before” and “being better off than otherwise.” I stay neutral between these two uses here. Note also that “benefit” and “better off” can come apart insofar as a person can be rendered better off than others (i.e., gain a relative advantage) despite having gained no absolute benefit. I return to this below when I discuss loss-based versions of the fair play theory. Critics of the fair play theory have generally been unclear about whether their point is that lawbreakers have not benefited in an absolute sense or have not been rendered better off than others.

  10. 10.

    For a discussion of whether we need fair play to account for the wrongness of a crime like tax evasion, see Dagger (2018, 150–55).

  11. 11.

    This objection can also be raised in a moralized way. The objection would then be that it would be inappropriate to locate an offender’s desert in others’ grudging compliance with moral duties (Duff 2008, 279). The non-moralized version of this objection is clearly better, as it is plausible that morally abhorrent crimes would be unfair, in the sense of free riding on a mutually beneficial system of cooperation, if most people were tempted to commit such crimes. For a defense of treating fair play obligations in a non-moralized way, see Simmons (2001, 6–11) and Duus-Otterström (2021).

  12. 12.

    Dagger offers two reasons why different crimes can be differently unfair even though one embraces the general compliance response. First, crimes can leave victims unequally able to participate in social cooperation. As he writes,

    the tax evader takes unfair advantage of many people, but her offense typically does not make it difficult for them to continue doing their part in the cooperative practice. With the rapist, the murderer, and the batterer, however, the offender has done something that makes it difficult or even impossible for his victim to contribute further to the ongoing cooperative endeavour. (2018, 192)

    Second, the need to preserve social cooperation requires tracking the members’ opinions about which crimes are worse than others (194). Dagger is here arguably guilty of equivocating between the unfairness of a crime and the extent to which the crime is a threat to a society guided by the principle of fair play, but even if we let this slide, the reasons he offers raise questions. For example, it seems strained to say that murdering someone is an especially flagrant violation of fair play because it means that the victim cannot contribute at all to social cooperation moving forward. I generally doubt that our intuitive sense of criminal seriousness will track how unable people would be to participate in reciprocal exchanges. As for the idea that social cooperation requires empirical legitimacy to sustain it, this is no doubt true, but this is an indirect and contingent way of connecting fair-play considerations and sentencing.

  13. 13.

    For loss-based versions of the fair play theory, see McDermott (2001) and Duus-Otterström (2017).

  14. 14.

    “Leveling down” refers to the idea of making an outcome or distribution equal merely by reducing the position of the better off. For a valuable discussion, see Temkin (2003).

  15. 15.

    This is the same as saying that acts can wrong us even though they do not harm us (and may even benefit us). For a defense, see, e.g., McDermott (2001, 412), Kumar (2003), and Slavny and Parr (2015).

  16. 16.

    McDermott (2001) arguably goes too far, though, since he comes perilously close to saying that material goods (being “categorically” different from the moral good of respectful treatment) can never correct the distinctive loss inflicted by crime. This would be too strong considering that fines can be punishments even though they go after the perpetrator’s money. However, this does not change the crucial point that compensation via rights-respecting treatment is often impossible, for if the distinctive loss of crime is that one is not treated as a person, then it seems that the only way this loss could be compensated would be for the victim to be treated as more than a person for a period. But the idea of treating someone as more than a person, if it is even desirable, is incoherent insofar as our rights are satiable. For example, once a person’s right to bodily integrity is respected, no more bodily integrity can be gained; there is no “extra” bodily integrity to dole out.

  17. 17.

    Westen (2016) also claims that this is the point Morris had in mind, although Westen admits that Morris stated his view so vaguely that the door was opened to other interpretations.

  18. 18.

    Thomas Hobbes famously argued that life in the state of nature (a pre-societal condition without overarching political authorities) would be plagued by war and be “solitary, poor, nasty, brutish, and short” (1996, 89).

  19. 19.

    For discussion of these issues, see Shelby (2016) and Duus-Otterström (2021).

  20. 20.

    I am grateful for written feedback from Peter Chau, William Bülow, Peter Westen, and Zachary Hoskins.

References

  • Anderson, Jami L. 1997. “Reciprocity as a Justification for Retributivism.” Criminal Justice Ethics 16, no. 1: 13–25.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bauer, Paul, and Andrei Poama. 2020. “Does Suffering Suffice? An Experimental Assessment of Desert Retributivism.” PLOS ONE 15, no. 4 (April 20): e0230304.

    Google Scholar 

  • Boonin, David. 2008. The Problem of Punishment. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Burgh, Richard W. 1982. “Do the Guilty Deserve Punishment?” Journal of Philosophy 79, no. 4 (April): 193–210.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chau, Peter. 2017. “Loss-Based Retributive Justifications of Punishment.” Oxford Journal of Legal Studies 37, no. 3 (Autumn): 618–35.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chiao, Vincent. 2022. “Proportionality and Its Discontents.” Law and Philosophy 41, nos. 2–3 (June): 193–217.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dagger, Richard. 2018. Playing Fair: Political Obligation and the Problems of Punishment. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Davis, Michael. 1983. “How to Make the Punishment Fit the Crime.” Ethics 93, no. 4 (July): 726–52.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1993. “Criminal Desert and Unfair Advantage: What’s the Connection?” Law and Philosophy 12, no. 2 (May): 133–56.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dolinko, David. 1991. “Some Thoughts about Retributivism.” Ethics 101, no. 3 (April): 537–59.

    Google Scholar 

  • Duff, R. A. 2001. Punishment, Communication, and Community. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2008. “The Incompleteness of ‘Punishment as Fair Play’: A Response to Dagger.” Res Publica 14, no. 4 (December): 277–81.

    Google Scholar 

  • Duus-Otterström, Göran. 2017. “Fairness-Based Retributivism Reconsidered.” Criminal Law and Philosophy 11, no. 3 (September): 481–98.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2021. “Fair-Play Obligations and Distributive Injustice.” European Journal of Political Theory 20, no. 2 (April): 167–86.

    Google Scholar 

  • Duus-Otterström, Göran, and Erin I. Kelly. 2019. “Injustice and the Right to Punish.” Philosophy Compass 14, no. 2 (February): e12565.

    Google Scholar 

  • Falls, M. Margaret. 1987. “Retribution, Reciprocity, and Respect for Persons.” Law and Philosophy 6, no. 1 (April): 25–51.

    Google Scholar 

  • Finnis, John. 1980. Natural Law and Natural Rights. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Flanders, Chad. 2017. “Punishment, Liberalism, and Public Reason.” Criminal Justice Ethics 36, no. 1: 61–77.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Goodin, Robert E. 1989. “Theories of Compensation.” Oxford Journal of Legal Studies 9, no. 1 (Spring): 56–75.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hampton, Jean. 1991. “Correction Harms versus Righting Wrongs: The Goal of Retribution.” UCLA Law Review 39, no. 6 (August): 1659–702.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hart, H. L. A. 1955. “Are There Any Natural Rights?” Philosophical Review 64, no. 2 (April): 175–91.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2008. Punishment and Responsibility: Essays in the Philosophy of Law. 2nd ed. Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Hobbes, Thomas. 1996. Leviathan. Edited by Richard Tuck. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hoskins, Zachary. 2011. “Fair Play, Political Obligation, and Punishment.” Criminal Law and Philosophy 5, no. 1 (January): 53–71.

    Google Scholar 

  • Husak, Douglas. 2008. Overcriminalization: The Limits of the Criminal Law. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Klosko, George. 2004. The Principle of Fairness and Political Obligation. Lanham, MD: Rowman & Littlefield.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2005. Political Obligations. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Kramer, Matthew. 2013. “Retributivism in the Spirit of Finnis.” In Reason, Morality, and Law: The Philosophy of John Finnis, edited by John Keown and Robert P. George, 167–85. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Kumar, Rahul. 2003. “Who Can Be Wronged?” Philosophy & Public Affairs 31, no. 2 (April): 99–118.

    Google Scholar 

  • McDermott, Daniel. 2001. “The Permissibility of Punishment.” Law and Philosophy 20, no. 4 (July): 403–32.

    Google Scholar 

  • Moore, Michael S. 1997. Placing Blame: A General Theory of the Criminal Law. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Morris, Herbert. 1968. “Persons and Punishment.” Monist 52, no. 4 (October): 475–501.

    Google Scholar 

  • Murphy, Jeffrie G. 1971. “Three Mistakes about Retributivism.” Analysis 31, no. 5 (April): 166–69.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1973. “Marxism and Retribution.” Philosophy & Public Affairs 2, no. 3 (Spring): 217–43.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rawls, John. 1999. “Legal Obligation and the Duty of Fair Play.” In John Rawls: Collected Papers, edited by Samuel Freeman, 117–29. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Runge, Carlisle Ford. 1984. “Institutions and the Free Rider: The Assurance Problem in Collective Action.” Journal of Politics 46, no. 1 (February): 154–81.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shelby, Tommie. 2016. Dark Ghettos: Injustice, Dissent, and Reform. Cambridge, MA: Belknap.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Sher, George. 1987. Desert. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Simmons, A. John. 2001. Justification and Legitimacy: Essays on Rights and Obligations. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Slavny, Adam, and Tom Parr. 2015. “Harmless Discrimination.” Legal Theory 21, no. 2 (June): 100–114.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tadros, Victor. 2009. “Poverty and Criminal Responsibility.” Journal of Value Inquiry 43, no. 3 (September): 391–413.

    Google Scholar 

  • Temkin, Larry S. 2003. “Equality, Priority or What?” Economics and Philosophy 19, no. 1 (April): 61–87.

    Google Scholar 

  • Thorburn, Malcolm. 2012. “Proportionate Sentencing and the Rule of Law.” In Principles and Values in Criminal Law and Criminal Justice: Essays in Honour of Andrew Ashworth, edited by Lucia Zedner and Julian V. Roberts, 269–84. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Tonry, Michael. 2020. “Is Proportionality in Punishment Possible, and Achievable?” In Of One-Eyed and Toothless Miscreants. Making the Punishment Fit the Crime, edited by Michael Tonry, 1–29. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wellman, Christopher Heath. 2001. “Toward a Liberal Theory of Political Obligation.” Ethics 111, no. 4 (July): 735–59.

    Google Scholar 

  • Westen, Peter. 2016. “Retributive Desert as Fair Play.” In Legal, Moral, and Metaphysical Truths: The Philosophy of Michael S. Moore, edited by Kimberly Kessler Ferzan and Stephen J. Morse, 63–78. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Göran Duus-Otterström .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2023 The Author(s), under exclusive license to Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Duus-Otterström, G. (2023). Fair Play Theories of Punishment. In: Altman, M.C. (eds) The Palgrave Handbook on the Philosophy of Punishment. Palgrave Handbooks in the Philosophy of Law. Palgrave Macmillan, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-031-11874-6_13

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics