Skip to main content
Log in

How chemistry shifts horizons: element, substance, and the essential

  • Published:
Foundations of Chemistry Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

In 1931 eminent chemist Fritz Paneth maintained that the modern notion of “element” is closely related to (and as “metaphysical” as) the concept of element used by the ancients (e.g., Aristotle). On that basis, the element chlorine (properly so-called) is not the elementary substance dichlorine, but rather chlorine as it is in carbon tetrachloride. The fact that pure chemicals are called “substances” in English (and closely related words are so used in other European languages) derives from philosophical compromises made by grammarians in the late Roman Empire (particularly Priscian [fl. ~520 CE]). When the main features of the constitution of isotopes became clear in the first half of the twentieth century, the formal (IUPAC) definition of a “chemical element” was changed. The features that are “essential” to being an element had previously been “transcendental” (“beyond the sphere of consciousness”) but, by the mid-twentieth century the defining characteristics of elements, as such, had come to be understood in detail. This amounts to a shift in a “horizon of invisibility” brought about by progress in chemistry and related sciences. Similarly, chemical insight is relevant to currently-open philosophical problems, such as the status of “the bundle theory” of the coherence of properties in concrete individuals.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. English translations of Aristotle are taken from Barnes 1984. The original Greek text of Metaphysics was consulted in Page et al. (1933/1935).

  2. The linguistic peculiarity (polysemy) that Paneth pointed out for chemists’ use of the word “element” is not an isolated case. Chemists have a general tendency to use one and the same word to designate two related but different types of items: on the one hand, an independently existing material “stuff”—and, on the other hand, something that is a part of another thing and does not have its own independent existence (for examples, please see Earley 2006).

  3. Post anglicized his family name on relocating to England.

  4. At King’s College of The University of London, H. R. Post was the mentor of the Ph.D. thesis of Eric Scerri, editor of this journal.

  5. Buchler (2004) pointed out that the German term Stoff does not carry the same philosophic freight as the English word “substance” does.

  6. I defer to others who may know whether or not such usage is widespread.

  7. Buckminsterfullerene consists of quasi-spherical C60 molecules. Graphite consists of planar sheets of carbon centers arranged in a “chicken-wire” pattern.

  8. Baruch (Benedict) Spinoza (1632–1677) took this requirement especially seriously. He concluded that—since all things are more or less connected to each other—there can be no more than one substance, properly speaking.

  9. The categories are: substance, quantity, qualification, where, when, being-in-a-position, having, doing, being affected (Categories, Ib 25).

  10. Aristotle occasionally also used the word ousia, as well as the words hypostasis (“what stands under”) and hypokeimenon (“what lies beneath”—translated as “substratum” in the quotation from Metaphysics VII (Z) given in the text) to designate “the objective reality” (as opposed to “the outer form”) of a thing—“the substance” as contrasted with “a substance.”

  11. It now seems trivial to observe that one may know that a phoenix is a bird that can rise again from its own ashes without expecting that any individual that fills that description exists in fact. This distinction between “essence” and “existence” was much debated by the medievals—and was not nearly as clear to the ancients as it may be to us (Owens 2007, pp. 22–23).

  12. This usage should not be taken to suggest that “elements” (as such) have independent existence. Our present intuition that “elements” have independent existence stems from the unfortunate custom of referring to stable materials such as yellow sulfur as “elements,” rather than as “elementary substances.”

References

  • Armstrong, D.M.: Truth and Truthmakers. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge (2004)

    Google Scholar 

  • Barnes, J. (ed.): The Complete Works of Aristotle. Princeton University Press, Princeton (1984)

    Google Scholar 

  • Buchler, J.: Chemistry seen as molecular architecture and notes on the German term ‘Stoff’. In: Sobczyńska, D., Zeidler, P., Zielonaka-Lis, E. (eds.) Chemistry in the Philosophical Melting Pot (Dia-Logos 5). Frankfurt am Main, Peter Lang (2004)

    Google Scholar 

  • Earley, J.: Chemical ‘substances’ that are not ‘chemical substances’. Philos. Sci. 73(5), 841–852 (2006). doi:10.1086/518743

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Earley, J.: How philosophy of mind needs philosophy of chemistry. HYLE Int. J. Philos. Chem. 14(1), 1–26 (2008). http://www.hyle.org/journal/issues/14-1/earley.htm

    Google Scholar 

  • Hardison Jr., O.B.: Disappearing Through the Skylight. Viking/Penguin, New York (1989)

    Google Scholar 

  • Harré, R.: Trope theory and the ontology of chemistry. Found. Chem. (2008). doi:10.1007/s10698-008-9052-7

    Google Scholar 

  • Hochberg, H., Mulligan, K. (eds.): Relations and Predicates. Ontos Verlag, Frankfurt (2004)

  • Kahn, C.: The Verb "Be" in Ancient Greek. Reidel, Dordrecht (1973)

  • Kant, I., Meiklejohn, J.M.D., Hutchins, R. (ed.): The Critique of Pure Reason trans. Great Books of the Western World, vol. 42. Britannica, Chicago (1781/1952)

  • Kohl, M.: Substancehood and subjecthood in Aristotle’s categories. Phronesis 53, 152–179 (2008). doi:10.1163/156852808X278712

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Long, A.A., Sedley, D.N.: The Hellenistic Philosophers, 2 vols., pp. 165, 172–174. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge (Quoted in Luhtala 2005, p. 85) (1987)

  • Luhtala, A.: Grammar and Philosophy in Late Antiquity: A Study of Priscian’s Sources. John Benjamin, Amsterdam (2005)

    Google Scholar 

  • Millikan, R.: On Clear and Confused Ideas: An Essay on Substance Concepts. Cambridge University Press, New York (2000)

    Google Scholar 

  • Owens, J.: Aristotle’s Gradations of Being in Metaphysics E-Z. St. Augustine, South Bend (2007)

    Google Scholar 

  • Page, T., et al. (eds.): Aristotle, the metaphysics, vols. 1 and 2. In: The Loeb Classical Library. Harvard University Press, Cambridge, (1933/1935)

  • Paneth, F.: The epistemological status of the concept of element. Found. Chem. 5(2), 111–145 (1931/2003)

    Google Scholar 

  • Paneth, F.: Über die erkenntnistheoretische Stellung des chemischen Elementbegriffs. Schriften der Königsberger Gelehrten Gesellschaft. 8(4), Halle: Max Niemeyer (1931)

  • Robb, D.: Qualitative unity and the bundle theory. Monist 88(4), 466–492 (2005)

    Google Scholar 

  • Scerri, E.: Realism, reduction, and the intermediate position. In: Bhushan, N., Rosenfeld, S. (eds.) Of Minds and Molecules: New Philosophical Perspectives on Chemistry, pp. 51–72. Oxford University Press, New York (2000)

    Google Scholar 

  • Scerri, E.: Response to Vollmer’s review of minds and molecules. Philos. Sci. 70, 391–398 (2003)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shimizu, T.: Words and concepts in Anselm and Abelard. In: Biard, J. (ed.) Langage, sciences, philosophie au XIIe siècle, pp. 177–197. Vrin, Paris (1999). http://www.l.u-Tokyo.ac.jp/~shimizu/medieval/word_concept.pdf

  • Tomarchio, J.: The emergence of the supposit in a metaphysics of creation. In: Paidia: Papers of the 20th World Congress of Philosophy, Boston, MA (1991). http://www.bu.edu/wcp/Papers/Medi/MediToma.htm

  • Whitehead, A.N.: Science and the Modern World. Macmillan, New York (1925/1967)

Download references

Acknowledgements

This research was supported, in part, by a grant from the Graduate School of Arts and Sciences of Georgetown University. The author is grateful to two anonymous reviewers for helpful suggestions, to Prof. Klaus Ruthenberg and to Dr. Martin Holzhaus for providing the German text of Paneth’s original paper, and to Prof. James J. O’Donnell for help with Latin philology.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Joseph E. Earley Sr..

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Earley, J.E. How chemistry shifts horizons: element, substance, and the essential. Found Chem 11, 65–77 (2009). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10698-008-9054-5

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10698-008-9054-5

Keywords

Navigation