Skip to main content

Advertisement

Log in

Ubuntu philosophy and the consensus regarding incidental findings in genomic research: a heuristic approach

  • Scientific Contribution
  • Published:
Medicine, Health Care and Philosophy Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

This study adopts a heuristic technique to argue the thesis that a set of norms rooted in the African philosophy of Ubuntu can usefully supplement current research guidelines for dealing with incidental findings discovered in genomic research. The consensus regarding incidental findings is that there is an ethical obligation to return individual genetic incidental findings that meet the threshold of analytic and clinical validity, have clinical utility, and are actionable, provided that research contributors have not opted out from receiving such information. This study outlines the hurdles that may hinder the integration of this consensus in mainstream clinical practice, and shows how an ethical theory from the global south may be used to address the same. This will advance the field of ethical, legal and social issues of personalized medicine by providing exposure to the under-represented African perspective on the ethical, legal, and social issues of genomics.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. That is, the right drug/ treatment for the right patient, at the right dose, and at the right time.

  2. There is not yet a legal obligation for researchers to return incidental findings which meet the outlined threshold.

  3. IFs must be differentiated from individual research results and aggregate research results, both of which often fall within research objective and may have clinical and/or personal significances. Aggregate research results are general results drawn from samples of a group and concerns the group, while individual research result concerns an individual. The current debate largely focuses on the disclosure of IFs and the decisions about returning individual and aggregate research results dependly greatly on the agreement—usually stated on the consent form—between researchers and contributor/community; the type of study, relevant research guidelines, clinical relevance of result and the ethical approval. Also note that an IF may have one of the following clinical significances:1. clinically actionable—one is at a risk for a future preventable or manageable health problem or already has a health problem for which a clinical action is available; 2. not-clinically actionable—clinical action is not available or no clinical implication; and 3. no-known clinical significance, that is the implication for one’s health is at the moment unknown (Issues 2013; Pike et al. 2013, p. 4).

  4. Analytic validity refers to the reliability and accuracy of the test or the "capacity of the test to measure the characteristic it is designed to identify" (Thorogood et al. 2014, p. 8.). Clincal validity refers tothe accuracy with which the test predicts the condition. A mere a mere suspicion of a disease does not pass this criterion. Analytic and clinical validity significantly reduces the likelihood of false positive findings. Validation also need to be undertaken in laboratories optimized for clinical care.

  5. If finding has an implication for one's health or that of one's offspring or reveals an established disease-causing pathogenic variants, or the probability of a serious treatable condition occuring is high. For example, IFs which reveals a brain tumor.

  6. A condition for which a clinical intervention/treatment exists; or for which benefits associated with communication outweighs the risk of harm. Misattributed paternity, for example, has no clinical intervention, hence, it is not clinically actionable. But a predisposition to treatable breast cancer is clinically actionable.

  7. Usually a pre-defined list of 59 genes where most pathogenic variants are “known” to be associated with certain types of cancer and cardiac conditions.

  8. In a previous publication (Ewuoso 2019b), I asserted the heterogeneity of “African ethics” in general, and Ubuntu in particular, in sub-Saharan Africa. I shall do the same here in this article. For example, the intrinsic wrongness of lying in Kantian ethics has no parallel in the Ubuntu ethical system as a whole. This remains an open question rather than one settled a priori as in Kantian ethics.

  9. Clinically validation of incidental findings in genomic research does not negate their probabilistic nature generally. A validated finding simply means that it is confirmed, and less likely to be a false positive, that someone has a predisposition to a life-threatening disesease or could develop a condition owing to the presence of a pathogenic variant. But validation does not imply that they will certainly develop the condition in the future. For example, an individual with an increased risk of breast cancer owing to the presence of a variant of the breast cancer type 1 gene, may never live long enough to have the disease. This is in this sense in which most published studies have used the phrase probabilistic findings in relation to IFs in genomic research. I also find Sullivan and Berkmans’ (2018, p. 23) explanation on this issue very apt. According to them, “genetic findings are probabilistic, and disorders may not manifest for years. Because genes interact with other genes, the environment, and behavior, the development of a particular disease or phenotype is not certain or immediate.”.

  10. The rescue principle requires individuals to take reasonable steps to help those in life-threatening situation, provided that such rescue is necessary, and does not come at a significant risk of harm to themselves; is likely to succeed; and the benefit to the victim outweighs likely harm to the helper. To this end, a researcher acts ethically when s/he returns a significant IF to consenting individual contributors who have a predisposition to a life-threatening disease owing to the presence of a pathogenic variant.

  11. I note here that an equally compelling counter-argument may also be advanced. One may argue for example, that returning IFs about misattributed paternity will constitute a violation of one’s right not to know. This is why the discussion regarding whether to return IFs to participants generates a dilemma.

  12. I note here that there are other sources of obligations beyond what is specified in the consent form, such as the primary duty to promote communal relationship or the partial-entrustment mode of Belsky and Richardson (2004).

  13. One may argue that based on the duty to rescue, an obligation to research participants persists beyond the grant period. In response I answer that a duty to rescue will exist if the cost of rescue does not come at a significant cost to the researcher/research team. Ubuntu philosophy complements the rescue principle by providing clarification on how to weigh obligations and assess cost. As I argued in the article, Ubuntu philosophy is not an impartial philosophy. In this philosophy (as pointed out on page19),long-standing on-going relationships have moral importance over present relationships that may not be longstanding; and current or existing relationships have moral importance over future relationships or a previous relationship that was terminated in the past. A researcher may not be burdened to provide for the cost of paying for the validation of an IFs of a past participant if this would undermine his ability to fulfill his/her obligation towards current research participants or to the research project itself. The researcher should, however, pay for this validation if this will not jeopardize his/her more pressing obligations.

References

  • Battle, M. 2000. A theology of community the ubuntu theology of Desmond Tutu. Interpretation 54 (2): 173–182.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Behrens, K.G. 2013. Towards an indigenous African bioethics. The South African Journal of Bioethics and Law 6 (1): 32–35. https://doi.org/10.7196/SAJBL.255.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Behrens, K.G. 2017. A critique of the principle of ‘respect for autonomy’, grounded in African thought. Dev World Bioeth 17 (2): 126–134. https://doi.org/10.1111/dewb.12145.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Belsky, L., and H.S. Richardson. 2004. Medical researchers' ancillary clinical care responsibilities. BMJ 328 (7454): 1494–1496. https://doi.org/10.1136/bmj.328.7454.1494.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cilliers, J. 2008. In search of meaning between Ubuntu and Into: Perspectives on preaching in post-apartheid South Africa. Paper presented at the eigth international conference of societas (Societas Homiletica).

  • Darnell, A.J., H. Austin, D.A. Bluemke, R.O. Cannon 3rd, K. Fischbeck, W. Gahl, et al. 2016. A clinical service to support the return of secondary genomic findings in human research. American Journal of Human Genetics 98 (3): 435–441. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.ajhg.2016.01.010.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dreyer, J.S. 2015. Ubuntu. International Journal of Practical Theology 19 (1): 189–209. https://doi.org/10.1515/ijpt-2015-0022.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Edwards, L.B., and L.E. Greeff. 2017. Exploring grassroots feedback about cancer challenges in South Africa: A discussion of themes derived from content thematic analysis of 316 photo-narratives. The Pan African Medical Journal 28: 173–173. https://doi.org/10.11604/pamj.2017.28.173.11894.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ewuoso, C. 2016. A systematic review of the management of incidental findings in genomic research. BEOnline: Journal of the West African Bioethics Training Program 3 (1): 1–21.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ewuoso, C. 2019a. Addressing the conflict between partner notification and patient confidentiality in serodiscordant relationships: How can Ubuntu help? Developing world bioethics. https://doi.org/10.1111/dewb.12232.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ewuoso, C. 2019b. Paltering and an african moral theory: Contributing an African perspective to the ethical literature on paltering. South African Journal of Philosophy 38 (1): 55–67.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ewuoso, C., and S. Hall. 2019. Core aspects of ubuntu: A systematic review. South African Journal of Bioethics and Law 12 (2): 93–103.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gade, C. 2011. The historical development of the written discourses on Ubuntu 1. South African Journal of Philosophy 30 (3): 303–329.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gade, C. 2012. What is Ubuntu ? Different interpretations among South Africans of African descent. South African Journal of Philosophy 31 (3): 484–503.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hellwig, L.D., C. Turner, T.A. Manolio, M. Haigney, C.A. James, B. Murray, et al. 2019. Return of secondary findings in genomic sequencing: Military implications. Molecular Genetics & Genomic Medicine 7 (2): e00483. https://doi.org/10.1002/mgg3.483.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hoffmann, N., and T. Metz. 2017. What can the capabilities approach learn from an Ubuntu ethic? A relational approach to development theory. World Development 97 (2017): 153–164. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.worlddev.2017.04.010.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Issues, P.C.F.T.S.O.B. 2013. Anticipate and communicate: Ethical management of incidental and secondary findings in the clinical, research and direct-to-consumer contexts. Washington, DC: US Government. https://bioethics.gov/sites/default/files/FINALAnticipateCommunicate_PCSBI_0.pdf.

  • Levine, R.J. 2003. Research and practice. In Ethical and regulatory aspects of clinical research: Readings and commentary, ed. E.J. Emmanuel, R.A. Crouch, J.D. Arras, J.D. Moreno, and C. Grady. Baltimore: The John Hopkins University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lutz, D.W. 2009. African "Ubuntu" philosophy and global management. Journal of Business Ethics 84 (3): 313–328.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mackley, M.P., and B. Capps. 2017. Expect the unexpected: Screening for secondary findings in clinical genomics research. British Medical Bulletin 122 (1): 109–122. https://doi.org/10.1093/bmb/ldx009.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Metz, T. 2007. Toward an african moral theory. Journal of Political Philosophy 15 (3): 321–341.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Metz, T. 2009. African moral theory and public governance: Nepotism, preferential hiring and other partiality. In African ethics: An anthology for comparative and applied ethics, ed. M.F. Murove, 335–356. Scottsville: UKZN Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Metz, T. 2011a. The African ethic of Ubuntu/Botho. In Moral education in sub-Saharan Africa, ed. S. Swarz and M. Taylor, 7–24. New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Metz, T. 2011b. Ubuntu as a moral theory and human rights in South Africa. African Human Rights Law Journal 11 (2): 532–559.

    Google Scholar 

  • Metz, T. 2012. An African theory of moral status: A relational alternative to individualism and holism. Ethical Theory and Moral Practice 15 (3): 387–402.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Metz, T. 2014. Just the beginning for Ubuntu: Reply to Matolino and Kwindingwi. South African Journal of Philosophy 33 (1): 65–72.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Metz, T. 2016. Recent philosophies of social protection: From capability to Ubuntu. Global Social Policy 16 (2): 132–150.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Metz, T. 2017. Ancillary care obligations in light of an African bioethic: From entrustment to communion. Theoretical Medicine and Bioethics 38 (2): 111–126. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11017-017-9404-1.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Middleton, A., K. Morley, E. Bragin, H. Firth, M. Hurles, C. Wright, and M. Parker. 2016. Attitudes of nearly 7000 health professionals, genomic researchers and publics toward the return of incidental results from sequencing research. European Journal of Human Genetics 24: 9. https://doi.org/10.1038/ejhg.2015.58.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Molefe, M. (2011). What can the socio-political ethic of ubuntu contribute to contemporary conceptions of “development”?

  • Molefe, M. 2014. Reflections on 'A Report on Ubuntu'. Acta Academica 46: 157–164.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mugumbate, J. 2013. Exploring African philosophy: The value of ubuntu in social work. African Journal of Social Work 3 (1): 82–100.

    Google Scholar 

  • Munung, N.S., B.M. Mayosi, and J. de Vries. 2018. Genomics research in Africa and its impact on global health: Insights from African researchers. Global Health, Epidemiology and Genomics 3: e12. https://doi.org/10.1017/gheg.2018.3.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Muwanga-Zake, J. 2009. Building bridges across knowledge systems: Ubuntu and participative research paradigms in Bantu communities. Discourse: Studies in the Cultural Politics of Education 30 (4): 413–426. https://doi.org/10.1080/01596300903237198.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nembaware, V., African Genomic Medicine Training, Initiative, N. Mulder. 2019. The African Genomic Medicine Training Initiative (AGMT): Showcasing a community and framework driven genomic medicine training for nurses in Africa. Frontiers in Genetics. https://doi.org/10.3389/fgene.2019.01209.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • O'Sullivan, J.W., T. Muntinga, S. Grigg, and J.P.A. Ioannidis. 2018. Prevalence and outcomes of incidental imaging findings: Umbrella review. BMJ 361: k2387. https://doi.org/10.1136/bmj.k2387.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pike, E.R., K. Rothenberg, and B.E. Berkman. 2013. Finding fault?: Exploring legal duties to return incidental findings in genomic research, 1–47. XX: Law Journal.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ramose, M.B. 2002. The philosophy of ubuntu and ubuntu as a philosophy. In Philosophy from Africa: A text with readings, ed. P.H. Coetzee and A.P.J. Roux, 230–237. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Romanycia, M., and F. Pelletier. 1985. What is Heuristic? Computational Intelligence 1: 47–58.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schaefer, G.O., and J. Savulescu. 2018. The right to know: A revised standard for reporting incidental findings. Molecular Genetics & Genomic Medicine 48 (2): 22–32. https://doi.org/10.1002/hast.836.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Solberg, B., and K.S. Steinsbekk. 2012. Managing incidental findings in population based biobank research. Norsk Epidemiologi 21 (2): 195–201.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Solomon, B.D., D.W. Hadley, D.E. Pineda-Alvarez, N.C.S. Program, A. Kamat, J.K. Teer, et al. 2012. Incidental medical information in whole-exome sequencing. Pediatrics 129 (6): e1605–1611. https://doi.org/10.1542/peds.2011-0080.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sullivan, H.K., and B.E. Berkman. 2018. Incidental findings in low-resource settings. Hastings Center Report 48 (3): 20–28. https://doi.org/10.1002/hast.851.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sundby, A., M.W. Boolsen, K.S. Burgdorf, H. Ullum, T.F. Hansen, A. Middleton, and O. Mors. 2017. Stakeholders in psychiatry and their attitudes toward receiving pertinent and incident findings in genomic research. The American Journal of Medical Genetics Part A 173 (10): 2649–2658. https://doi.org/10.1002/ajmg.a.38380.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Thorogood, A., Y. Joly, B.M. Knoppers, T. Nilsson, P. Metrakos, A. Lazaris, and A. Salman. 2014. An implementation framework for the feedback of individual research results and incidental findings in research. BMC medical ethics 15: 88.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tutu, D. 1999. No future without forgiveness. London: Rider Random House.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Viberg, J., P. Segerdahl, S. Langenskiold, and M.G. Hansson. 2016. Freedom of choice about incidental findings can frustrate participants' true preferences. Bioethics 30 (3): 203–209. https://doi.org/10.1111/bioe.12160.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Vos, S., J.J. van Delden, P. van Diest, and A. Bredenoord. 2017. Moral duties of genomics researchers: Why personalized medicine requires a collective approach. Trends in Genetics 33 (2): 118–128. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.tig.2016.11.006.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Woermann, M., and S. Engelbrecht. 2019. The Ubuntu challenge to business: From stakeholders to relationholders. Journal of Business Ethics 157 (1): 27–44. https://doi.org/10.1007/s10551-017-3680-6.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

The author would like to thank Prof Thaddeus Metz and the two reviewers for their critical comments. The author is also grateful to the James F. Drane Institute of Bioethics, Edinboro University of Pennsylvania for the research support which contributed greatly to the completion of this article.

Funding

No source of funding to be declared.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Contributions

Cornelius Ewuoso is entirely responsible for the intellectual content of this paper.

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Cornelius Ewuoso.

Ethics declarations

Competing interest

The author declares that he has no competing interests.

Ethical approval

This study is a concept paper and does not require ethical approval.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Ewuoso, C. Ubuntu philosophy and the consensus regarding incidental findings in genomic research: a heuristic approach. Med Health Care and Philos 23, 433–444 (2020). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11019-020-09953-4

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11019-020-09953-4

Keywords

Navigation