Skip to main content
Log in

Donald Davidson’s Critiques of Conceptual Relativism Applied to Non-adaptationist Evolutionary Epistemology and Refuted

  • Published:
Foundations of Science Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Over the last three decades, non-adaptationism has developed as an alternative model to more traditional, adaptationist approaches within Evolutionary Epistemology (EE). Despite its great explanatory strength, non-adaptationist EE finds a potential Achilles heel in its adherence to conceptual relativism, namely the idea that empirical content can be relative to many different and radically incommensurable conceptual schemes. In his seminal essay “On the Very Idea of a Conceptual Scheme” (1974), Donald Davidson did in fact prove the unintelligibility of an analogous form of conceptual relativism. Although Davidson’s original intent was to debunk a conceptual relativist position which he discerned in the works of authors such as Kuhn, Quine, and Whorf, given the apparent similarity between the conceptual relativism supported by non-adaptationist EE and the one criticised by Davidson, one might well wonder if Davidson’s objections would have the same debunking effect if applied to non-adaptationist EE. In this paper I propose to answer this question by directing Davidson’s critiques of conceptual relativism to non-adaptationist EE and by testing to what extent the latter is de facto undermined by Davidson’s attacks. I demonstrate that Davidson’s arguments do not detract from the reliability of non-adaptationist perspectives and, to some extent, they appear to substantiate the non-adaptationist evolutionary epistemological cause anew.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Parts of this article have been submitted in partial fulfilment of the requirements for the M.Sc. in History and Philosophy of Science at Utrecht University and have been extrapolated from my Master’s thesis “Evolution, Knowledge, and Reality: A Defence of Non-Adaptationist Evolutionary Epistemology”, https://dspace.library.uu.nl/handle/1874/353294.

  2. The discrimination between “specific” and “species-specific” hints at the existence of two distinct acknowledged forms of “complete incommensurability” among differing worldviews within non-adaptationist EE. As I will explain in Sect. 4, one form admits the possibility of completely incommensurable worldviews among the members of a same species, while the other acknowledges this possibility only among organisms with radically different biological phenotypes. As I will point out, whereas the former concerns “specific” (or particular) worldviews of different human beings who employ differing cognitive tools but present the same biological constitution, the latter regards “species-specific” worldviews of organisms belonging to different species which display different “species-specific” cognitive and biological sets.

  3. Just as “…the internal realism proposed by Hilary Putnam some years ago… strictly speaking is no realism at all…” (Vollmer 2004, 200), it must be noticed that although Wuketits and Ruse (whose position extensively draws upon Putnam’s internal realism [cf. Lemos 2002, 793]) variously resort to the term “realism” when defining their respective positions (“common-sense realism”, “internal realism”, and “functional realism”), their views are actually much closer to non-realism than realism. Their positions are indeed similarly characterized by the pragmatic rejection of a world-in-itself and by the idea that there is no world beyond our experience and thinking.

  4. In this article I intend to evaluate neither the accuracy of Davidson’s critiques against Kuhn, Quine, and Whorf nor the global coherence of Davidson’s discussion about conceptual schemes. For a detailed analysis of Davidson’s 1974 paper, the reader may refer to Beillard (2008) and Brons (2011, 2016).

  5. Whereas Brons (2016, 60) distinguishes between a general scheme idea (the “very idea”) and a particular one (the idea of “untranslatable schemes”) and claims that Davidson was concerned only with the latter, Beillard (2008, 10) argues that Davidson attacked the idea of untranslatable conceptual schemes in order to dismantle the “very idea”. According to Beillard (2008, 10–11), Davidson was convinced of the inherent dependency of the “intelligibility” of the “very idea” on the “intelligibility of the idea of a difference in scheme”. I prefer to follow Brons (2016) in this specific case, because, as he reports, Davidson did not completely dismiss the idea of a conceptual scheme as a whole, but he happened to use it, for example when he later admitted the possibility of tracing “differences or provincialisms in our conceptual schemes” (Davidson 1997, 128, quoted by Brons 2016, 61).

  6. “Complete incommensurability” identifies the impossibility of translating one conceptual scheme into the terms of another, while “partial incommensurability” admits the possibility of translating some parts of a scheme, albeit not all, into those of another. Although non-adaptationist thinkers do never resort to the expression “complete incommensurability”, I think we have good reasons for identifying the kind of untranslatability between schemes they support with a “complete” form of untranslatability. Diettrich (2001) excludes any prospect of meaningful communication between humans and aliens and, as framed in the words of Riegler (2012, 244), indicates the impossibility of “communication with beings equipped with…alternative [cognitive] operators”. Riegler (2012, 244) highlights the possibility of “a profound incommensurability among human beings”, while Clark, as reported by Vlerick (2017), supports the likelihood of “inaccessible” (48) or “unintelligible” (49) points of view (in this regard, since Ruse endorses Clark’s view, the same reading can be applied to his position [cf. footnote 7]). In light of this, since all the authors acknowledge the possibility of incommensurable schemes, without however pointing at the eventuality of a partial untranslatability, I take their positions as only endorsing the idea of a “complete incommensurability” and not that of a “partial incommensurability”.

  7. Ruse and Riegler are intended to support a weak form of incommensurability in so far as they respectively endorse Clark’s and Diettrich’s points of view on this matter.

  8. Whereas the weak form of incommensurability is explicitly acknowledged by Diettrich and Riegler, this point remains implicit in the works of Clark and Ruse. I follow Vlerick’s (2017) reading of Clark’s “hypothesis of the alien scientist” (41) as supporting the possibility of “inaccessible” (48) or “possibly unintelligible” (49) points of view. The same point can be applied to Ruse, since he endorses Clark’s view. That said, however, I am not entirely sure whether Vlerick’s overall interpretation of Clark’s position does agree with mine.

References

  • Beillard, J. (2008). Davidson on conceptual schemes. Doctoral dissertation. https://tspace.library.utoronto.ca/bitstream/1807/11129/1/Beillard_JC_J_200803_PhD_thesis.pdf. Accessed April 29, 2018.

  • Brons, L. L. (2011). Applied relativism and Davidson’s arguments against conceptual schemes. The Science of Mind,49, 221–240.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brons, L. L. (2012). Dharmakīrti, Davidson, and knowing reality. Comparative Philosophy,3(1), 30–57.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brons, L. L. (2013). Meaning and reality: A cross-traditional encounter. In B. Mou & R. Tieszen (Eds.), Constructive engagement of analytic and continental approaches in philosophy: From the vantage point of comparative philosophy (pp. 199–220). Leiden: Brill.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brons, L. L. (2016). Putnam and Davidson on coherence, truth, and justification. The Science of Mind,54, 51–70.

    Google Scholar 

  • Campbell, D. T. (1974). Evolutionary epistemology. In P. A. Schlipp (Ed.), The philosophy of Karl Popper (Vol. I, pp. 413–459). Illinois: La Salle.

    Google Scholar 

  • Clark, A. J. (1984). Natural anti-realism. Doctoral dissertation. https://dspace.stir.ac.uk/bitstream/1893/11925/1/Clark%20-%20thesis.pdf. Accessed June 13, 2017.

  • Clark, A. J. (1986). Evolutionary epistemology and the scientific method. Philosophica,37(1), 151–162.

    Google Scholar 

  • Davidson, D. (1974). On the very idea of a conceptual scheme. Proceedings and Addresses of the American Philosophical Association,47(1973–1974), 5–20.

    Google Scholar 

  • Davidson, D. (1997). Seeing through language. In D. Davidson (Ed.), Truth, language, and history (pp. 127–142). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Debernardi, M. (2015). Le radici dell’epistemologia evoluzionistica: Lorenz, Popper e Campbell. Doctoral dissertation. IRIS—Institutional Research Information System. https://boa.unimib.it/retrieve/handle/10281/77475/114659/phd_unimib_744893.pdf. Accessed April 29, 2018.

  • Diettrich, O. (1991). Induction and evolution of cognition and science. In G. Van de Vijver (Ed.), Teleology and selforganisation. Philosophica 47(2). Available at: http://cepa.info/5156. Accessed June 19, 2018.

  • Diettrich, O. (1992). Darwin, Lamarck and the evolution of science and culture. Evolution and Cognition, 1st series 2(3). Available at: http://cepa.info/5157. Accessed June 19, 2018.

  • Diettrich, O. (1998). On some relations between cognitive and biological evolution. In G. Van de Vijver, S. Salthe, & M. Delpos (Eds.), Evolutionary systems (pp. 319–340). Dordrecht: Kluwer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Diettrich, O. (2001). A physical approach to the construction of cognition and to cognitive evolution, Special issue on “The Impact of Radical Constructivism on Science”. Foundations of Science,6(4), 273–341.

    Google Scholar 

  • Diettrich, O. (2004). Cognitive evolution. In F. M. Wuketits & C. Antweiler (Eds.), Handbook of evolution (Vol. 1, pp. 25–75)., The evolution of human societies and cultures Weinheim: Wiley.

    Google Scholar 

  • Diettrich, O. (2006). The biological boundary conditions for our classical physical world view. In N. Gontier, et al. (Eds.), Evolutionary epistemology, language and culture (pp. 67–93). Dordrecht: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Farrell, F. B. (1994). Subjectivity, realism and postmodernism: The rediscovery of the world in recent philosophy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gontier, N. (2006a). Introduction to evolutionary epistemology, language and culture. In N. Gontier, et al. (Eds.), Evolutionary epistemology, language and culture (pp. 1–29). Dordrecht: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gontier, N. (2006b). Evolutionary epistemology. Internet Encyclopaedia of Philosophy. http://www.iep.utm.edu/evo-epis/#H6. Accessed November 13, 2016.

  • Gould, S. J., & Lewontin, R. (1979). The spandrels of San Marco and the panglossian paradigm: A critique of the adaptationist programme. Proceedings of the Royal Society of London, Series B: Biological Sciences,205, 581–598.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kuhn, T. (1970). Reflection on my critics. In I. Lakatos & A. Musgrave (Eds.), Criticism and the growth of knowledge. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lemos, J. (2002). Theism, evolutionary epistemology, and two theories of truth. Zygon,37(4), 789–801.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lorenz, K. (1941). Kant’s doctrine of the a priori in the light of contemporary biology. https://archive.org/details/KantsDoctrineOfTheAPrioriInTheLightOfContemporaryBiologyKonradLorenz. Accessed November 06, 2016.

  • Lorenz, K. (1977). Behind the mirror: A search for a natural history of human knowledge. London: Methuen.

    Google Scholar 

  • Malpas, J. (2011). Triangulation and philosophy: A Davidsonian landscape. In M. C. Amoretti & G. Preyer (Eds.), Philosophische analyse/philosophical analysis: Triangulation: From an epistemological point of view (pp. 257–279). Berlin: De Gruyter.

    Google Scholar 

  • Munz, P. (2001). [1993] Philosophical Darwinism: On the origin of knowledge by means of natural selection. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Piaget, J. (1970). Genetic epistemology (E. Duckworth, Trans.). New York: Columbia University Press.

  • Popper, K. R. (1972). Objective knowledge: An evolutionary approach. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Putnam, H. (1981). Reason, truth and history. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Quine, W. V. O. (Ed.). (1961). Two dogmas of empiricism. In From a logical point of view (2nd ed.). Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Quine, W. V. O. (Ed.). (1969). Speaking of objects. In Ontological relativity and other essays. New York: Columbia University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Riegler, A. (2001). Towards a radical constructivist understanding of science. Foundations of Science,6, 1–30.

    Google Scholar 

  • Riegler, A. (2006). Like cats and dogs: Radical constructivism and evolutionary epistemology. In N. Gontier, et al. (Eds.), Evolutionary epistemology, language and culture (pp. 47–65). Dordrecht: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Riegler, A. (2007). Is Glasersfeld’s constructivism a dangerous intellectual tendency? In R. Glanville & A. Riegler (Eds.), The importance of being ernst (pp. 263–275). Vienna: Echoraum.

    Google Scholar 

  • Riegler, A. (2012). Constructivism. In L. L’Abate (Ed.), Paradigms in theory construction (pp. 235–255). New York: Springer Verlag.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ruse, M. (1989). The view from somewhere: A critical defense of evolutionary epistemology. In K. Hahlweg & C. A. Hooker (Eds.), Issues in Evolutionary epistemology (pp. 185–228). Albany, NY: State University of New York Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ruse, M. (1995). Evolutionary naturalism. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Simpson, G. G. (1963). This view of life: The world of an evolutionist. New York: Harper.

    Google Scholar 

  • Vlerick, M. (2017). How our biology constrains our science. Kairos. Journal of Philosophy and Science,18, 31–53.

    Google Scholar 

  • Vollmer, G. (1984). Mesocosm and objective knowledge: On problems solved by evolutionary epistemology. In F. M. Wuketits (Ed.), Concepts and approaches in evolutionary epistemology: Towards an evolutionary theory of knowledge (pp. 69–121). Doredrecht: D. Reidel.

    Google Scholar 

  • Vollmer, G. (1987). [1975] Evolutionäre Erkenntnistheorie (4th ed.). Stuttgart: Hirzel.

    Google Scholar 

  • Vollmer, G. (2004). New arguments in evolutionary epistemology. Ludus Vitalis XII,21, 197–212.

    Google Scholar 

  • von Glasersfeld, E. (1991). Knowing without metaphysics: Aspects of the radical constructivist position. In F. Steier (Ed.), Research and reflexivity Inquiries into social construction (pp. 12–29). London: Sage Publications.

    Google Scholar 

  • von Glasersfeld, E. (2001). Radical constructivism: A way of knowing and learning. London: Palmer Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wheeler, S. C. I. I. I. (2014). Neo-Davidsonian metaphysics: From the true to the good. New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Whorf, B. L. (1956). In J. B. Carroll (Ed.), Language, thought and reality: Selected writings of Benjamin Lee Whorf. New York: Wiley.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wuketits, F. M. (1992). Adattamento, rappresentazione e costruzione. Un saggio di epistemologia evolutiva. In M. Ceruti (Ed.), Evoluzione e conoscenza (pp. 121–133). Lubrina: Bergamo.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wuketits, F. M. (2000). Functional realism. In A. Carsetti (Ed.), Functional models of cognition (pp. 27–38). Dordrecht: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wuketits, F. M. (2006). Evolutionary epistemology: The non-adaptationist approach. In N. Gontier, et al. (Eds.), Evolutionary epistemology, language and culture (pp. 33–46). Dordrecht: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

I would like to express my sincere gratitude to Nathalie Gontier for providing constructive criticism of the paper.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Marta Facoetti.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Facoetti, M. Donald Davidson’s Critiques of Conceptual Relativism Applied to Non-adaptationist Evolutionary Epistemology and Refuted. Found Sci 25, 357–374 (2020). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10699-019-09606-7

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10699-019-09606-7

Keywords

Navigation