Skip to main content

Advertisement

Log in

Should epistemology take the zetetic turn?

  • Published:
Philosophical Studies Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

What is the relationship between inquiry and epistemology? Are epistemic norms the norms that guide us as inquirers—as agents in the pursuit of knowledge and understanding? Recently, there has been growing support for what I, following Friedman (Philosophical Review 129(4):501–536, 2020), will call the zetetic turn in epistemology, the view that all epistemic norms are norms of inquiry. This paper investigates the prospects of an inquiry-centered approach to epistemology and develops several motivations for resisting it. First, I argue that the norms of inquiry are most plausibly seen as practical, not as distinctively epistemic. Second, I argue that a zetetically-grounded epistemology is unable to properly account for the rationality of belief. It fails to account for cases where intuitively irrational beliefs promote inquiry, or where intuitively rational beliefs are zetetically useless or counterproductive to inquiry. The main upshot is this: there must be a source of epistemic normativity that isn’t ultimately zetetic.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. This terminology follows (Friedman; 2020, 501). ‘Zetetic’ means roughly ‘proceeding by inquiry’, but for our purposes, it will mean something looser like, having to do with inquiry. Uses of the expression “zetetic” in contemporary epistemology are also found in Axell and Olson (2009), and Axell (2011).

  2. The phrase “zetetic turn” can also be used in a broader way, to refer simply to turning our attention more towards zetetic norms, see Thorstad (2021); Flores and Woodard (2023); McWilliams (2023). Here I’ll use it to refer to the more ambitious program of grounding all epistemic norms in zetetic ones, see Friedman (2020, Forth), Steglich-Petersen (2021), and Kelp (2021, 2020).

  3. Kelp (2020, 2021) indirectly argues for this view. He takes this position for granted and uses it to address several debates in epistemology concerning the nature of epistemic phenomena, the value of knowledge, and skepticism. I discuss Kelp’s approach to zetetic epistemology in §3 and §5.

  4. Friedman (2020, 526) argues for the view that zetetic norms and epistemic norms are identical. I will be targeting a weaker claim in the paper, namely, that all epistemic norms are zetetic. This leaves open the possibility of non-epistemic zetetic norms (e.g., moral norms of inquiry which tell one to inquire into the well-being of a loved one).

  5. For influential defenses of evidentialism see: Conee and Feldman (1985, 2004); Feldman (2000).

  6. However, Friedman notes that EP and KP are diachronic norms that concern acts (i.e., the processes of coming to believe or know that p), opposed to synchronic norms which evaluate epistemic states directly at a time (Friedman; 2020, 504). For related discussion see Haziza (2022).

  7. Friedman (2020), fn. 34, notes that Lasonen-Aarnio’s (2010) account of “unreasonable knowledge” might open space for the rejection of KP.

  8. Here I am granting, for the sake of argument, that there are instrumental or practical reasons to believe. However, see, for example, Berker (2018) and Arpaly (ms.) for arguments against this view.

  9. This traces back most prominently to the debate between Clifford (1877) and James (1897). For a contemporary overview of this debate see Marušić (2011) and Chignell (2018).

  10. This analogy follows arguments given in Arpaly (ms.), which argues that there are no epistemic reasons to perform actions. Also see related arguments from Kelly (2003); Raz (2009); Nelson (2010); Cohen (2016) and Simion (2018) against epistemic reasons to act.

  11. See Fleisher (2018, 2022), Singer and Aronowitz (Forth); Thorstad (2022) and Arpaly (ms.) for discussion of “sandwich reasons.”.

  12. There is an ongoing debate in the literature concerning what the aim of inquiry is. For defenses of the view that the aim of inquiry is true belief see, for example, Kvanvig (2003). For a defense of the view that the aim of inquiry is knowledge see, for example: Sartwell (1992); Whitcomb (2010); Rysiew (2012); Kelp (2014, 2020); Sapir and van Elswyk (2021). This view is also suggested in Friedman (2017). Also see, for example, Falbo (2021, 2022); Archer (2021); Woodard (2022) for defenses of the view that inquiry aims at epistemic improvement, and Goodman and Holguín (2022) who argue that inquiry aims at being sure, as well as Beddor (Manuscript), who argues that inquiry aims at maximizing epistemic value. For a critical discussion which casts doubt upon whether inquiry has a constitutive aim see Friedman (2023). The paper remains neutral on what the aim of inquiry is.

  13. For a related discussion of similar detective-style cases see (Friedman; 2019b, 300–306).

  14. When defending this point Kelp draws upon the work of Sosa (2007).

  15. Thank you to an anonymous referee for encouraging me to consider this response.

  16. For a compelling defense of this point see Friedman (2023).

  17. United States Department of Agriculture Food and Nutrition Service: https://www.fns.usda.gov/.

  18. Thorstad (2021)’s discussion of evaluative focal points draws upon terminology developed in Kagan (2000).

  19. See the discussion in Friedman (2020, 521–522) which suggests a close connection between epistemic norms on belief states and norms on when one is permitted to inquire such that one enters into a belief state, and for related arguments see Steglich-Petersen (2021). Also see the related arguments in Fleisher (2022), who argues that there are zetetic reasons (or what he calls inquisitive reasons) to be in belief-like states such as acceptance or endorsement.

  20. While Thorstad (2021) adopts a value-based conception of epistemic normativity, in other work, Thorstad (2022), he is critical of this view. There is debate in the literature concerning what kinds of things count as having final epistemic value. For a sample of this debate see: Lynch (2009); Ahlstrom-Vij (2013); Pritchard (2014); Khalifa and Millson (2020). Also see Friedman (2019a) for related discussion. A value-based approach is also central to defenses of epistemic consequentialism. I discuss epistemic consequentialism in §5.1.

  21. Friedman (2019a, 680–681) discusses a similar example where a boss ignores strong evidence that he’s not loved by his employees, and refrains from coming to know this because it will interfere with his inquiry. She argues that the Boss isn’t rationally permitted to come to know that he’s unloved, despite being in a position to know this. Mr. Congeniality takes this style of case a step further by highlighting how the success of inquiry can be promoted by believing against the evidence too. See Thorstad (2021, 2915–2916) for related discussion of this case.

  22. For further discussion see the collection of papers in Ahlstrom-Vij and Dunn (2018). And for further discussions of epistemic trade-off cases see, for example, Christensen (2004) Ch. 6, Berker (2013a,b); Jenkins (2007); Littlejohn (2012); Singer (2019) and Aronowitz (2021).

  23. Also see: Friedman (Forth); Olsson and Westlund (2006); Enqvist (2012) for further discussion of research agendas.

  24. See Dallman (2017) for a discussion of how to prioritize our inquiries given our cognitive limitations.

  25. Thank you to an anonymous referee for encouraging me to consider this objection.

  26. See Kelp; (2021, 196–202) Appendix 2 for further discussion of how this view relates to virtue epistemology.

  27. I consider this point further in §5.2.

  28. Thank you to an anonymous referee for encouraging me to consider this point.

  29. Also, cf. (Friedman; 2019a, 2019b, 2019c, 684–685): “It’s understandable, I think, to want some sort of explanation as to why we should conform to our central epistemic norms.” And also, Friedman (Forth): “If our traditional epistemic norms are not the sorts of norms we ought to conform to in order to successfully figure things out, then why should we conform to them at all?” It’s worth reflecting upon whether the epistemologist is on the hook to answer the why conform question. Consider an analogous question in the moral domain: why should we conform to moral norms? We don’t conform to moral norms because they advance some antecedent goal of ours or because it’s always in our personal interest to do so. Indeed, moral norms apply to us regardless of—and even when they go against—our personal interests and goals. A similar point seems to hold in the epistemic domain: epistemic norms apply to us regardless of—and even when they go against—our personal interests and zetetic goals. Epistemic norms aren’t beholden to our wants and needs. So, one might plausibly resist the claim that epistemologists should be expected or able to provide an answer to the why conform question. See Kelly (2003) for related discussion. This topic merits further consideration but taking it up would take the paper too far afield. Thanks to David Christensen for helpful discussion, and for pointing out the comparison to the moral domain.

  30. There is a growing literature of fascinating work on salience and norms of attention. See, for example: Siegel (2017, 2022), Irving (2021), Yumusak (2022), Gardiner (2022), Saint-Croix (2022) and Munton (20222023).

  31. For discussion see: Friedman (2017), Whitcomb (2017), Sapir and van Elswyk (2021), Whitcomb and Millson (2023), Willard-Kyle (forthcoming).

  32. For further discussion see Friedman (Forth) on the distinction between accidental and intentional forms of learning. Friedman’s discussion draws upon a much earlier distinction between experiment and observation found in Hershel (1831).

  33. Thank you to an anonymous referee for encouraging me to consider this point.

  34. Hookway is primarily concerned with the value of knowledge, though his arguments carry over to the case of rational belief. Also see the related discussion in (Kelp; 2021, 57–58).

  35. Although see Steglich-Petersen (2021) who offers distinct motivations for the zetetic turn.

  36. See, for example, Feldman (2000), Kelly (2003, 2007), Berker (2018), Steglich-Petersen and Skipper (2019) and Howard (2020).

  37. A useful list of topics is given in the “Inquiry” page on PhilPapers, which was created in 2020, and is edited by Joshua Habgood-Coote. URL: https://philpapers.org/browse/inquiry.

References

  • Ahlstrom-Vij, H. K., & Dunn, J. (Eds.). (2018). Epistemic consequentialism. Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ahlstrom-Vij, K. (2013). In defense of veritistic value monism. Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, 94(1), 19–40.

    Google Scholar 

  • Archer, A. (2021). The aim of inquiry. Disputatio, 13(61), 95–119.

    Google Scholar 

  • Aronowitz, S. (2021). Exploring by believing. The Philosophical Review, 130(3), 339–383.

    Google Scholar 

  • Arpaly, N. (ms.). Epistemology and the baffled action theorist.

  • Axell, G. (2011). Recovering responsibility. Logos and Episteme, 2(3), 249–454.

    Google Scholar 

  • Axell, G., & Olson, P. (2009). Three independent factors in epistemology: A neo-Deweyan approach to the nature and sources of epistemic value. Contemporary Pragmatism, 6(2), 89–109.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ballantyne, N. (2019). Knowing our limits. Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Beddor, B. (Manuscript). Inquiry beyond knowledge.

  • Berker, S. (2013a). Epistemic teleology and the separateness of propositions. Philosophical Review, 122(3), 337–393.

    Google Scholar 

  • Berker, S. (2013b). The rejection of epistemic consequentialism. Philosophical Issues, 23(1), 363–387.

    Google Scholar 

  • Berker, S. (2018). A combinatorial argument against practical reasons for belief. Analytic Philosophy, 59(4), 427–470.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chignell, A. (2018). The ethics of belief, in E. N. Zalta (ed.), Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. URL: https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2018/entries/ethics-belief/

  • Christensen, D. (2004). Putting Logic in its Place. Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Clifford, W. (1877). The ethics of belief. In T. Madigan (Ed.), The ethics of belief and other essays (pp. 70–96). Prometheus.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cohen, S. (2016). Reasons to believe and reasons to act. Episteme, 13(4), 427–438.

    Google Scholar 

  • Conee, E., & Feldman, R. (1985). Evidentialism. Philosophical Studies, 48(1), 15–34.

    Google Scholar 

  • Conee, E., & Feldman, R. (2004). Evidentialism. Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dallman, J. (2017). When obstinacy is a better (cognitive) policy. Philosophers’ Imprint, 17(24), 1–18.

    Google Scholar 

  • Enqvist, S. (2012). Interrogative belief revision based on epistemic strategies. Studia Logica, 100(3), 453–479.

    Google Scholar 

  • Falbo, A. (2021). Inquiry and confirmation. Analysis, 81(4), 622–631.

    Google Scholar 

  • Falbo, A. (2022). Inquiring minds want to improve. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 101(2), 298–312.

    Google Scholar 

  • Feldman, R. (2000). The ethics of belief. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 63(3), 667–695.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fleisher, W. (2018). Rational endorsement. Philosophical Studies, 175(10), 2649–2675.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fleisher, W. (2022). Pursuit and inquisitive reasons. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science, 94, 17–30.

    Google Scholar 

  • Flores, C. and Woodard, E. (2023). Epistemic norms on evidence-gathering, Philosophical Studies.

  • Foot, P. (1967). The problem of abortion and the doctrine of double effect. Oxford Review, 5, 5–15.

    Google Scholar 

  • Friedman, J. (2023). The aim of inquiry?, Philosophy and Phenomenological Research.

  • Friedman, J. (2017). Why suspend judging? Noûs, 51(2), 302–326.

    Google Scholar 

  • Friedman, J. (2019a). Teleological epistemology. Philosophical Studies, 176(3), 673–691.

    Google Scholar 

  • Friedman, J. (2019b). Checking again. Philosophical Issues, 29(1), 84–96.

    Google Scholar 

  • Friedman, J. (2019c). Inquiry and belief. Noûs, 53(2), 296–315.

    Google Scholar 

  • Friedman, J. (2020). The epistemic and the zetetic. Philosophical Review, 129(4), 501–536.

    Google Scholar 

  • Friedman, J. (Forth). Zetetic epistemology, in B. Reed and A. Flowerree (eds), Towards an Expansive Epistemology: Norms, Action, and the Social Sphere, Routledge.

  • Firth, R. (1980). Epistemic merit, intrinsic and instrumental, Presidential Address delivered before the Seventy-Seventh Annual Eastern Meeting of the American Philosophical Association.

  • Gardiner, G. (2022). Attunement: On the cognitive virtues of attention. In C. K. Mark Alfano & J. de Ridder (Eds.), Social virtue epistemology. Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Goodman, J., & Holguín, B. (2022). Thinking and being sure. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research., 106(3), 634–654.

    Google Scholar 

  • Haziza, E. (2022). Reconciling the epistemic and the zetetic. Thought: A Journal of Philosophy, 11(2), 93–100.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hershel, J. (1831). A preliminary discourse on the study of natural philosophy. Longman.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hookway, C. (2006). Epistemology and inquiry: The primacy of practice. In S. C. Hetherington (Ed.), Epistemology futures (pp. 94–110). Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Horowitz, S. (2019). Predictably misleading evidence. In M. S. Rasmussen & A. Steglich-Petersen (Eds.), Higher-order evidence: New essays. Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Howard, C. (2020). Weighing epistemic and practical reasons for belief. Philosophical Studies, 177, 2227–2243.

    Google Scholar 

  • Irving, Z. C. (2021). Drifting and directed minds: The significance of mind-wandering for mental agency. Journal of Philosophy, 118(11), 614–644.

    Google Scholar 

  • James, W. (1897). The will to believe and other essays in popular philosophy. Longmans, Green, and Co.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jenkins, C. (2007). Entitlement and rationality. Synthese, 157(1), 25–45.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kagan, S. (2000). Evaluative focal points. In D. M. B. Hooker & E. Mason (Eds.), Morality, rules and consequences (pp. 134–155). Rowman & Littlefield.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kelly, T. (2003). Epistemic rationality as instrumental rationality: A critique. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 66(3), 612–640.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kelly, T. (2007). Evidence and normativity: A reply to Leite. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 75(2), 465–474.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kelp, C. (2020). Theory of inquiry, Philosophy and Phenomenological Research.

  • Kelp, C. (2014). Two for the knowledge goal of inquiry. American Philosophical Quarterly, 51(227), 232.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kelp, C. (2021). Inquiry, knowledge, and understanding. Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Khalifa, K., & Millson, J. A. (2020). Perspectives, questions, and epistemic value. In M. Massimi & A.-M. Cretu (Eds.), Knowledge from a human point of view (pp. 87–106). Springer Verlag.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kvanvig, J. (2003). The value of knowledge and the pursuit of understanding. Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lasonen-Aarnio, M. (2010). Unreasonable knowledge. Philosophical Perspectives, 24(1), 1–21.

    Google Scholar 

  • Littlejohn, C. (2012). Justification and the truth connection. Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lynch, M. (2009). Truth, value, and epistemic expressivism. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 79(1), 76–97.

    Google Scholar 

  • Marušić, B. (2011). The ethics of belief. Philosophical Compass, 6(1), 33–43.

    Google Scholar 

  • McWilliams, E. (2023). Evidentialism and epistemic duties to inquire. The Philosophical Quarterly. https://doi.org/10.1093/pq/pqad061

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Munton, J. (2022). Answering machines How to (epistemically) evaluate a search engine. Inquiry: an Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy. https://doi.org/10.1080/0020174X.2022.2140707

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Munton, J. (2023). Prejudice as the misattribution of salience. Analytic Philosophy, 64(1), 1–19.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nelson, M. (2010). We have no positive epistemic duties. Mind, 119(473), 83–102.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nozick, R. (1993). The nature of rationality. Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Olsson, E., & Westlund, D. (2006). On the role of the research agenda in epistemic change. Erkenntnis, 65(2), 165–183.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pritchard, D. (2014). Truth as the fundamental epistemic good. In J. Matheson & R. Vitz (Eds.), The ethics of belief. Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Raz, J. (2009). Reasons: Practical and adaptive. In D. S. S. Wall (Ed.), Reasons for action (pp. 37–57). Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rysiew, P. (2012). Epistemic scorekeeping. In J. Brown & M. Gerken (Eds.), Knowledge ascriptions. Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Saint-Croix, C. (2022). Rumination and wronging: The role of attention in epistemic morality. Episteme, 19(4), 491–514.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sapir, Y., & van Elswyk, P. (2021). Hedging and the ignorance norm on inquiry. Synthese, 199(3–4), 5837–5859.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sartwell, C. (1992). Why knowledge is merely true belief. Journal of Philosophy, 89(4), 167–180.

    Google Scholar 

  • Siegel, S. (2017). The Rationality of Perception. Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Siegel, S. (2022). Salience principles for democracy. In S. Archer (Ed.), Salience (pp. 235–266). Taylor and Francis.

    Google Scholar 

  • Simion, M. (2018). No epistemic norm for action. American Philosophical Quarterly, 55(3), 231–238.

    Google Scholar 

  • Singer, D. (2019). Permissible epistemic trade-offs. The Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 97(2), 281–293.

    Google Scholar 

  • Singer, D. J. and Aronowitz, S. (Forth). What epistemic reasons are for: Against the belief-sandwich distinction, in B. Dunaway and D. Plunkett (eds), Meaning, Decision, and Norms: Themes from the Work of Allan Gibbard, Maize Books (Michigan Publishing).

  • Sosa, E. (2007). A virtue epistemology. Apt belief and reflective knowledge (Vol. 1). Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Steglich-Petersen, A. (2021). An instrumentalist unification of zetetic and epistemic reasons, Inquiry.

  • Steglich-Petersen, A., & Skipper, M. (2019). An instrumentalist account of how to weigh epistemic and practical reasons for belief. Mind, 129(516), 1071–1094.

    Google Scholar 

  • Thorstad, D. (2021). Inquiry and the epistemic. Philosophical Studies, 178, 2913–2928.

    Google Scholar 

  • Thorstad, D. (2022). There are no epistemic norms of inquiry. Synthese, 200(5), 1–24.

    Google Scholar 

  • Whitcomb, D. (2010). Curiosity was framed. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 81(3), 664–687.

    Google Scholar 

  • Whitcomb, D. (2017). One kind of asking. Philosophical Quarterly, 67(266), 148–168.

    Google Scholar 

  • Whitcomb, D., & Millson, J. (2023). Inquiring attitudes and erotetic logic: Norms of restriction and expansion. Journal of the American Philosophical Association. https://doi.org/10.1017/apa.2023.13

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Willard-Kyle, C. (forthcoming). The knowledge norm for inquiry, Journal of Philosophy.

  • Woodard, E. (2022). Why double-check?, Episteme, 1–24.

  • Yumusak, E. (2022). Perspectival clashes: Salience as a site of contestation, Doctoral dissertation, Harvard University Graduate School of Arts and Sciences.

Download references

Acknowledgements

Thank you to Abdul Ansari, Zach Barnett, Bob Beddor, Jennifer Carr, Jamie Drier, Ying Huang, Anton Johnson, Chris Kelp, Emily Kress, Sam McGrath, Haigen Messerian, Elizabeth Miller, Jared Millson, Luis Rosa, Joshua Schechter, Mona Simion, David Thorstad, Anna Tsvetkov, Peter van Elswyk, Dennis Whitcomb, Chris Willard-Kyle, and Orfeas Zormpalas for helpful conversations and feedback. The paper has benefited from the questions and comments of audience members at the Dissertation Workshop at Brown University (2021), the Southampton-Humboldt Normativity Conference (2021), the Brown Bag Seminar at CONCEPT at the University of Cologne (2022), the Northeast Normativity Workshop at the University of Pennsylvania (2022), the Inquiry Conference at the COGITO Epistemology Research Centre at the University of Glasgow (2022), and the Eastern APA in Montreal (2023); I'm especially grateful to Tez Clark and Kate Nofli for their commentary at the Eastern APA. I would also like to thank two anonymous reviewers from Philosophical Studies for very helpful constructive comments and suggestions. Special thanks to David Christensen for feedback on many earlier drafts of the paper, and for having countless conversations with me about these ideas over the past few years.

Funding

No funding was received to assist with the preparation of this manuscript.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Arianna Falbo.

Ethics declarations

Conflict of interest

The author has no competing interests to declare that are relevant to the content of this article.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Springer Nature or its licensor (e.g. a society or other partner) holds exclusive rights to this article under a publishing agreement with the author(s) or other rightsholder(s); author self-archiving of the accepted manuscript version of this article is solely governed by the terms of such publishing agreement and applicable law.

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Falbo, A. Should epistemology take the zetetic turn?. Philos Stud 180, 2977–3002 (2023). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-023-02016-3

Download citation

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-023-02016-3

Keywords

Navigation