Skip to main content
Log in

On Theory Construction in Physics: Continuity from Classical to Quantum

  • Original Research
  • Published:
Erkenntnis Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

It is well known that the process of quantization—constructing a quantum theory out of a classical theory—is not in general a uniquely determined procedure. There are many inequivalent methods that lead to different choices for what to use as our quantum theory. In this paper, I show that by requiring a condition of continuity between classical and quantum physics, we constrain and inform the quantum theories that we end up with.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. As we will see later, I specifically propose the requirement that the weak topology on a quantum algebra of observables preserves the information encoded in the classical topology of pointwise convergence, which can be understood itself as a weak topology.

  2. In particular, this rules out nonregular representations of the Weyl algebra.

  3. For more on C*-algebras and W*-algebras, see Kadison and Ringrose (1997), Sakai (1971), and Landsman (1998). For more on algebraic quantum theory, see Haag (1992), Bratteli and Robinson (1987), and Emch (1972). For philosophical introductions, see Halvorson (2006) and Ruetsche (2011).

  4. One could restrict attention here to sequences because the norm topology is second countable, but for the weak topologies considered later, which are not second countable, one must work with arbitrary nets.

  5. A complete normed vector space is called a Banach space. A C*-algebra is thus a Banach algebra whose norm is, in a certain sense, compatible with multiplication and involution.

  6. A linear functional \(\rho \in {\mathfrak {A}}^*\) is positive if \(\rho (A^*A)\ge 0\) for all \(A\in {\mathfrak {A}}\) and normalized if \(||\rho || = 1\).

  7. See Feintzeig (2016) for more on the completion of a C*-algebra into a W*-algebra.

  8. See Landsman (1998, 2006) for a description of classical and quantum theories in the algebraic framework and a detailed investigation of quantization.

  9. We include complex-valued functions for generality. One typically restricts to the self-adjoint functions, which are real-valued, for describing observable quantities.

  10. Of course there are other possible choices for the algebra of classical observables that one may use if one wanted to admit, e.g., unbounded observables.

  11. Throughout this paper we work in units such that \(\hbar = 1\).

  12. This definition captures as a special case the usual commutation relations

    $$\begin{aligned}{}[{\mathcal {Q}}(q),{\mathcal {Q}}(p)] = i \end{aligned}$$

    for the quantized position observable \({\mathcal {Q}}(q)\) and the quantized momentum observable \({\mathcal {Q}}(p)\).

  13. The Weyl algebra can also be uniquely characterized through its Hilbert space representations (see Clifton and Halvorson 2001).

  14. The Weyl operators admit a unique maximal C*-algebra norm (Manuceau et al. 1974).

  15. These are not the only interpretive positions available (see Ruetsche 2011). Albeit extreme views, they are illustrative for the purposes of this paper.

  16. One gets this notion of pointwise convergence immediately for abelian C*-algebras of all continuous functions on a compact Hausdorff space (see Kadison and Ringrose 1997, p. 270). However, when we consider functions on a locally compact (not necessarily compact) manifold \({\mathcal {M}}\), the correspondence of weak convergence and pointwise convergence on \({\mathcal {M}}\) only holds for the algebra \(C_0({\mathcal {M}})\), rather than the algebra of all continuous functions, \(C({\mathcal {M}})\). The reason is that it is only for \(C_0({\mathcal {M}})\) that the pure states correspond to precisely the points in \({\mathcal {M}}\). Other algebras of bounded continuous functions allow for ‘states at infinity’—pure states that cannot be represented as points of \({\mathcal {M}}\)—which forces the weak topology to diverge from the topology of pointwise convergence on \({\mathcal {M}}\). Another way to state the main issue of this paper is as the question of whether these ‘states at infinity’ are physically significant.

  17. On the other hand, if we started with a C*-algebra other than \(C_0({\mathcal {M}})\), then completing in the weak topology would give rise to functions that cannot even be understood as measurable functions on \({\mathcal {M}}\) because of their values ‘at infinity’ (cf. footnote 15).

  18. Even though \({\mathcal {Q}}\) is only required to be linear and not to be a homomorphism (i.e., it is not required to preserve multiplication and thus not required to preserve functional relations in general), it seems natural to expect \({\mathcal {Q}}\) to preserve functional relations on abelian subalgebras of its range. In other words, it seems natural to expect \({\mathcal {Q}}(g(f)) = g({\mathcal {Q}}(f))\) for \(f\in C_0({\mathcal {M}})\) and any Borel function \(g:{\mathbb {R}}\rightarrow {\mathbb {R}}\), as in the usual functional calculus.

  19. This is meant only for the case of finitely many degrees of freedom on a simply connected phase space. It is well known that for systems with infinitely many degrees of freedom or with superselection rules, one requires a different algebra.

  20. Landsman (1998, 2006) also discusses another quantization map that he calls Weyl quantization. This map does not have the Weyl algebra as its image, and so it should be distinguished from the quantization map defined above from \({\mathcal {W}}_C\) to \({\mathcal {W}}\). It is worth reiterating that what is at issue in this paper is the quantum algebra that is the image of a quantization map, but we have not discussed the details of the different mappings one might use once we have fixed some quantum algebra.

  21. I thank an anonymous referee for this point.

References

  • Ashtekar, A. (2009). Some surprising implications of background independence in canonical quantum gravity. General Relativity and Gravitation, 41, 1927–1943. doi:10.1007/s10714-009-0802-1.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ashtekar, A., & Isham, C. (1992). Inequivalent observable algebras. Another ambiguity in field quantisation. Physics Letters B, 274, 393–398.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bratteli, O., & Robinson, D. (1987). Operator algebras and quantum statistical mechanics. New York: Springer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Clifton, R., & Halvorson, H. (2001). Are Rindler quanta real? Inequivalent particle concepts in quantum field theory. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 52, 417–470.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Corichi, A., Vukašinac, T., & Zapata, J. (2007). Polymer quantum mechanics and its continuum limit. Physical Review D, 76, 044016-1-16. doi:10.1103/PhysRevD.76.044016.

    Google Scholar 

  • Earman, J., & Fraser, D. (2006). Haag’s theorem and its implications for the foundations of quantum field theory. Erkenntnis, 64, 305344. doi:10.1007/s10670-005-5814-y.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Emch, G. (1972). Algebraic methods in statistical mechanics and quantum field theory. New York: Wiley.

    Google Scholar 

  • Emch, G. (1997). Beyond irreducibility and back. Reports on Mathematical Physics, 40(2), 187–193.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Feintzeig, B. (2016). Toward an understanding of parochial observables. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science. doi:10.1093/bjps/axw010.

  • Fell, G., & Doran, R. (1988). Representations of *-algebras, locally compact groups, and Banach *-algebraic bundles. Boston: Academic Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Haag, R. (1992). Local quantum physics. Berlin: Springer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Halvorson, H. (2004). Complementarity of representations in quantum mechanics. Studies in the History and Philosophy of Modern Physics, 35, 4556. doi:10.1016/j.shpsb.2003.01.001.

    Google Scholar 

  • Halvorson, H. (2006). Algebraic quantum field theory. In J. Butterfield & J. Earman (Eds.), Handbook of the philosophy of physics (pp. 731–864). New York: North Holland.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kadison, R., & Ringrose, J. (1997). Fundamentals of the theory of operator algebras. Providence, RI: American Mathematical Society.

    Google Scholar 

  • Landsman, N. P. (1998). Mathematical topics between classical and quantum mechanics. New York: Springer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Landsman, N. P. (2006). Between classical and quantum. In J. Butterfield & J. Earman (Eds.), Handbook of the philosophy of physics (pp. 417–553). New York: North Holland.

    Google Scholar 

  • Manuceau, J., Sirugue, M., Testard, D., & Verbeure, A. (1974). The smallest C-algebra for the canonical commutation relations. Communications in Mathematical Physics, 32, 231–243.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Petz, D. (1990). An invitation to the algebra of canonical commutation relations. Leuven: Leuven University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Reed, M., & Simon, B. (1980). Functional analysis. New York: Academic Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ruetsche, L. (2003). A matter of degree: Putting unitary inequivalence to work. Philosophy of Science, 70(5), 1329–1342.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ruetsche, L. (2011). Interpreting quantum theories. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Sakai, S. (1971). C*-algebras and W*-algebras. New York: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Simonnet, M. (1996). Measures and probabilities. New York: Springer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

I would like to thank Sam Fletcher, Zacharias Flouris, Hans Halvorson, John Manchak, Sarita Rosenstock, Jim Weatherall, and an anonymous referee for the many helpful comments and conversations that led to this paper. This material is based upon work supported by the National Science Foundation Graduate Research Fellowship under NSF Grant No. DGE-1321846. Any opinions, findings, and conclusions or recommendations expressed in this material are those of the author and do not necessarily reflect the views of the National Science Foundation.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Benjamin H. Feintzeig.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Feintzeig, B.H. On Theory Construction in Physics: Continuity from Classical to Quantum. Erkenn 82, 1195–1210 (2017). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10670-016-9865-z

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10670-016-9865-z

Navigation