Skip to main content

Advertisement

Log in

“Most Reasonable for Humanity”: Legitimation Beyond the State

  • Original Article
  • Published:
Jus Cogens Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Legal and political philosophers of a normative bent face an uphill struggle in keeping themes of global justice and cosmopolitan governance, at the forefront of their disciplinary debate, given the perceived urgency of confronting, at the domestic level, the populist upsurge in mature democracies and “democratizing societies” alike. In this paper, these two levels of analysis—national and transnational—mutually enrich one another through a reflection on the ground of legitimacy. In the first section (“Perfectionism Redux”), (a) neo-perfectionist approaches to the legitimation of transnational authority (rooted in Kantian or Hegelian notions, or in some natural law conception of human rights) and (b) public reason approaches rooted in the paradigm of “political liberalism” will be contrasted. In the second section (“From Balance to Separation of Powers”), a non-perfectionist and normative conception of the legitimacy of transnational authorities will be derived from Rawls’s “liberal principle of legitimacy” (renamed “legitimation by constitution by F. Michelman) and the difference with the application of the same principle at the domestic level will be elucidated. In the third section (“Legitimacy and the Flourishing of Humanity: Buchanan and Keohane on Global Institutions”), on the basis of such conception, one of the most complete and influential approaches to the legitimacy of transnational authorities—i.e., the “Complex Standard of Legitimacy” expounded by A. Buchanan and R. Keohane in “The Legitimacy of Global Governance Institutions”—will be critically assessed.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. See Walzer (2004), 178–179.

  2. See Rawls (2005) and Rawls (1999); see Habermas (1992), transl. by William Rehg (1996), translated, edited, and with an introduction by Pensky (2001); (2006).

  3. See Beitz (1979) and (1999), 269–296; Pogge (2008), 168–195 and (2010). See also Caney (2005).

  4. See Held (1995); Archibugi (2008); see also Archibugi and Held (eds), (1995).

  5. Bohman (2004), 336–352, and (2007); Laborde (2010), 48–69 and Pettit (2010), 70–94.

  6. Scheuerman (2014), 419–441.

  7. For the argument on the inevitability of the rise of a world state, see Wendt (2003), 491–542. For an argument concerning its desirability, see Wendt (2015).

  8. See Michelman (2003) and, more recently, Michelman (2015). For an insightful reconstruction of the nuances of what is meant by “constitution” in Rawls’s liberal principle of legitimacy, see Michelman (2018).

  9. The term “perfectionism” is used here as a synonym for the comprehensive quality of a conception of justice and its attendant notion of legitimacy. In that sense, its meaning is broader than the one associated by Rawls with perfectionism as a specific moral view in A theory of justice (325–332). Rather, it encompasses all the teleological conceptions that, regardless of the value(s) they posit as supreme, understand justice and legitimacy (qua standard for assessing the merits of institutions) as the maximal possible realization of that supreme value (see ibidem, 24–25). A “perfectionist” view of justice and legitimacy is then understood generically as the opposite of a “political-liberal” conception of justice and legitimacy, though it may take many specific forms. See also Quong (2011), 26–30.

  10. See Dworkin (2011), 332–344 and Griffin (2008) and the interesting collection by Crisp (2014).

  11. Pogge (2008), 54. Caney (2005), a similar way can be found of proceeding from “universal moral values” to principles of justice that specify what human rights follow from these antecedent moral entitlements (25–96). Caney then moves on to spell out distributive entitlements are required by justice on a global scale (102–140), to then finally derive an argument in favor of a specific “kind of world order” from these considerations (148–182). For an original attempt to avoid perfectionism and actually bypass both perfectionist and agreement-based conceptions of human rights, see Beitz’s “practical conception of human rights,” aimed at reconstructing the implicit meaning of human rights within the practice of international political interaction as carried out by the relevant actors, in Beitz (2009), 102–121. Beitz’s conception, however, falls short of articulating an understanding of the normativity of human rights (a point substantially conceded in ibid., 115). For one of the most interesting “political” approaches to human rights, and critique of the perfectionist approaches (based on the so-called “Mirror View”), see Buchanan (2013), 50–84.

  12. Habermas (2011), 296.

  13. See, for example, Held (1995), 232–233 and Archibugi (2008), 86–87.

  14. Bohman (2007), 173.

  15. Ibidem, 115.

  16. Ibidem, 120.

  17. Rawls (2005), 217.

  18. Kant (1957), 100.

  19. For useful commentaries on this issue, see Pettit (2006), 38–55, and Tan (2006), 76–94.

  20. Habermas (2012), 35.

  21. See Franzius (2010), 42 and Bogdandy (2003), 38.

  22. Habermas (2012), 38.

  23. Ibidem, 41.

  24. Ibidem, 42.

  25. Perju (2018), 32.

  26. Ibidem, 43.

  27. Kumm (2016), 14, 3, 704.

  28. Ibidem, 706.

  29. Ibidem, 708.

  30. Ibidem, 709.

  31. Ibidem, 706–707.

  32. See Rawls (1999), 68–70.

  33. On this point, see also Buchanan’s defense of the legitimacy of transnational orders and institutions as independent of democratic credentials, and best accounted for by his notion of “meta-coordination,” very close to public reason, in Buchanan (2013), 178–180. For an insightful appraisal of Buchanan’s proposal from the perspective of a discourse-theory of legitimacy, see Ingram (2018), 231 and 273.

  34. See Rawls (1999), 80.

  35. The identification of which human rights are “human rights proper” that have priority over state sovereignty is one of the weakest points in The Law of People. It burst the “political” credentials of the paradigm—in that human rights are said to be binding also for peoples who are not parties to the Society of Peoples and thus never subscribed to them. On the idea of a Second Declaration of Fundamental Human Rights as more responsive to the new historical function expected to be exerted by a declaration of human rights in the post-1989 world and as more in line with the paradigm of political liberalism, see Ferrara (2012), 173–187.

  36. For a more extended version of this argument, see Ferrara (2014), 105–108.

  37. In his “Introduction to the Paperback Edition,” Rawls explicitly acknowledges that while he continues to consider justice as fairness as the most reasonable view of justice “for us,” it is not to be denied that “other conceptions also satisfy the definition of a liberal conception” and thus that within a contemporary pluralistic society there co-exist not only several rival comprehensive conceptions of the good, but also “different and incompatible liberal political conceptions,” Rawls (2005), xlvii.

  38. For an interesting public-reason approach to the legitimacy of authority and coercion “in a world of states,” see Gaus (2011), 470–479.

  39. Rawls (1980), 88, 519. A similar view can be found in Rawls (2005), 28.

  40. Buchanan and Keohane (2006), 405–437.

  41. Ibidem, 417–418.

  42. Ibidem, 419–424.

  43. Interestingly, Buchanan and Keohane observe that “most global governance institutions... include mechanisms for accountability,” but that often these are “morally inadequate,” for example because they make an institution like the World Bank accountable mostly to the main donor countries, and not enough to the rest of the affected participants (see ibidem, 426). What is then needed, they conclude, is not accountability per se, but “the right sort of accountability” (ibidem). For this purpose, they distinguish “narrow accountability” (which does not include provisions for contestation of its own terms) and a broader version of it, which includes “provisions for revising existing standards of accountability” (ibidem, 427). On the relation of accountability to the legitimacy of structures of governance, see also Ferrara (2014), 178

  44. Buchanan and Keohane (2006), 427 point out that “transparency by itself is inadequate.” Understood narrowly as mere availability of information concerning the operation of the institution, it cannot even ensure “narrow accountability”. Broader accountability, designed to include provisions for revising its own operative standards, is going to require a “broad transparency,” with relevant information not just available, but available “at reasonable cost,” in a format properly understandable and directed to the addressees of accountability-reports as well as to those “who may contest the terms of accountability” (ibidem, 427). Most importantly, Buchanan and Keohane argue that “if national legislatures are to retain their relevance ... they must be able to review the policies of global governance institutions. For legislatures to have information essential to performing these functions, they need a flow of information from transnational civil society” (ibidem, 431).

  45. Ibidem, 432.

  46. Ibidem, 432–433.

  47. Ibidem, 435.

  48. Ibidem, 436.

  49. Ibidem, 436.

  50. Keohane (2015), 345.

  51. Ibidem, 350.

  52. Ibidem, 350.

  53. See ibidem (2018), 269 and 305–308. On the subsequent remarkable adjustments operated by the EU judiciary, see Riccardi (2018), 1–14.

  54. Keohane (2015), 352.

  55. Ibidem, 352.

  56. Ibidem, 353.

  57. See Wendt (2015), 2.

  58. Mead (1974), 154–55. On this point, see also Ferrara (2008), 144.

  59. The Association of Southeast Asian Nations, founded in 1967, includes Indonesia, Malaysia, Philippines, Singapore, Thailand, Brunei Darussalam, Vietnam, Laos, Myanmar, and Cambodia.

  60. The South Asian Association for Regional Cooperation was founded in 1985 among Afghanistan, Bangladesh, Bhutan, India, Maldives, Nepal, Pakistan, and Sri Lanka.

  61. The African Union was founded in Addis Ababa in 2001. It includes Algeria, Angola, Benin, Botswana, Burkina–Faso, Burundi, Cameroun, Cap Vert, Central African Republic, Chad, Comoros, Congo, RD Congo, Côte d’Ivoire, Djibouti, Egypt, Equatorial Guinea, Eritrea, Ethiopia, Gabon, Gambia, Ghana, Guinea Bissau, Guinea, Kenya, Lesotho, Liberia, Libya, Madagascar, Malawi, Mali, Mauritania, and Mauritius, Mozambique, Namibia, Niger, Nigeria, Rwanda, Saharawi Arab Democratic Republic, Sao Tome and Principe, Senegal, Seychelles, Sierra Leone, Somalia, South Africa, Sudan, Swaziland, Tanzania, Togo, Tunisia, Uganda, Zambia, and Zimbabwe.

  62. The Union of South American Nations, founded in 2008, includes Argentina, Bolivia, Brazil, Chile, Colombia, Ecuador, Guyana, Paraguay, Peru, Surinam, Uruguay, Venezuela and Mexico and Panama as observers.

References

  • Archibugi D (2008) The global commonwealth of citizens: toward cosmopolitan democracy. Princeton University Press, Princeton

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Archibugi D, Held D (eds) (1995) Cosmopolitan democracy: an agenda for a New World order. Polity Press, Cambridge

  • Beitz C (1979) Political theory and international relations. Princeton University Press, Princeton, p 1999

    Google Scholar 

  • Beitz C (1999) International liberalism and distributive justice: a survey of recent thought. World Polit 51(2):269–296

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Beitz C (2009) The idea of human rights. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • von Bogdandy A (2003) Grundprinzipien. In: von Bogdandy A, Bast J (eds) Europäisches Verfassungsrecht. Springer, Dordrecht

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Bohman J (2004) Republican Cosmopolitanism. J Polit Philos 12(3):336–352

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bohman J (2007) Democracy across borders: from Dêmos to Dêmoi. MIT Press, Cambridge

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Buchanan A (2013) The heart of human rights. Oxford University Press, New York

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Buchanan A, Keohane RO (2006) The legitimacy of global governance institutions. Ethics Int Aff 20(49):405–437

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Caney S (2005) Justice beyond borders: a global political theory. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Crisp R (ed) (2014) Griffin on human rights. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Dworkin R (2011) Justice for Hedgehogs. Harvard University Press, Cambridge, Ma

  • Ferrara A (2008) The force of the example. Explorations in the paradigm of judgment. Columbia University Press, New York

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Ferrara A (2012) The idea of a charter of fundamental human rights. In: Corradetti C (ed) Philosophical dimensions of human rights. Springer, Dordrecht, pp 173–187

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Ferrara A (2014) The democratic horizon. Hyperpluralism and the renewal of political liberalism. Cambridge University Press, New York

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Franzius C (2010) Europäisches Verfassungsreschtsdenken. Mohr Siebeck, Tübingen

  • Gaus G (2011) The order of public reason. A theory of freedom and morality in a diverse and bounded world. Cambridge University Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Griffin J (2008) On human rights. Oxford University Press, New York

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Habermas J (1996) Between facts and norms. Contributions to a discourse theory of law and democracy (1992), transl. by William Rehg, Polity Press, Cambridge

  • Habermas J (2001) The postnational constellation. Political essays (1998), translated, edited and with an introduction by M. Pensky. MIT Press, Cambridge, MA

  • Habermas J (2006) The divided west. Polity Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Habermas J (2011) Reply to my critics. In: Finlayson JG, Freyenhagen F (eds) Habermas and Rawls: disputing the political. Routledge, New York and London

    Google Scholar 

  • Habermas, J. The crisis of the European Union. A response, transl. by Ciaran Cronin (Cambridge: Polity Press, 2012)

  • Held D (1995) Democracy and the global order: from the modern state to cosmopolitan governance. Stanford University Press, Stanford

    Google Scholar 

  • Ingram D (2018) World crisis and underdevelopment. A critical theory of poverty, agency, and coercion. Cambridge University Press, New York

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Kant, I., “Perpetual Peace”, in On History, edited, with an introduction, by L.W. Beck (Indianapolis-New York: Bobbs-Merrill, 1957)

  • Keohane RO (2015) Nominal democracy? Prospects for Democratic Global Governance. I-CON 13(2):343–353

    Google Scholar 

  • Kumm M (2016) Constituent power, cosmopolitan constitutionalism, and post-positivist law. I-CON 14(3):697–711

    Google Scholar 

  • Laborde C (2010) Republicanism and global justice: a sketch. Eur J Polit Theo 9:48–69

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mead GH (1974) Mind, self, and society from the standpoint of a social behaviorist. University of Chicago Press, Chicago

  • Michelman F I (2003) “Constitutional legitimation for political acts”, 66 MOD. L. REV. 1

  • Michelman, FI (2015) “Legitimacy, the social turn, and constitutional review: what political liberalism suggests” (May 6, 2015). Critical Quarterly for Legislation and Law, No. 3, 2015; Harvard Public Law Working Paper No. 16–28. Available at SSRN: https://ssrn.com/abstract=2783525

  • Michelman, FI 2018 “«Constitution (written or unwritten): legitimacy and legality in the thought of John Rawls», 2018, ms on file with the author

  • Perju V (2018) “Double sovereignty in Europe? A critique of Habermas’s defense of the nation-state”, 2018, Ms on file with the author

  • Pettit P (2006) Rawls’s peoples. In: Martin R, Reidy DA (eds) Rawls’s law of peoples. A realistic utopia? Blackwell, Oxford, pp 38–55

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Pettit P (2010) A republican law of peoples. Eur J Polit Theo 9:70–94

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pogge T (2008) World poverty and human rights. Cosmopolitan responsibilities and reforms (2002). Polity Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Pogge T (2010) Politics as usual. What lies behind the pro-poor rhetoric. Polity Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Quong J (2011) Liberalism without perfection. Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp 26–30

    Google Scholar 

  • Rawls J (1980) Kantian constructivism in moral theory. J Philos 88:512–572

    Google Scholar 

  • Rawls J (1999) The law of peoples, with the idea of public reason revisited. Harvard University Press, Cambridge, Mass

  • Rawls J (2005) Political liberalism (1993), Expanded edn. Columbia University Press, New York

  • Riccardi A (2018) Revisiting the role of the EU judiciary as the stronghold for the protection of human rights while countering terrorism. Global Jurist 18(2):1–14

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Scheuerman WE (2014) Cosmopolitanism and the world state. Rev Int Stud 40:419–441. https://doi.org/10.1017/S0260210513000417

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tan K-C (2006) The problem of decent peoples. In: Martin R, Reidy DA (eds) Rawls’s law of peoples. A realistic utopia? Blackwell, Oxford, pp 76–94

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Walzer M (2004) Governing the globe (2000). In: Arguing about war. Yale University Press, New Haven and London, pp 178–179

    Google Scholar 

  • Wendt A (2003) Why a world state is inevitable? Eur J Int Relat 9:491–542

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wendt A (2015) “Why a world state is democratically necessary?”, transcript of a presentation given by Alexander Wendt at Hiram College, 2 July 2015, accessed at http://wgresearch.org/why-a-world-state-is-democratically-necessary/ on 17.3.2018

Download references

Acknowledgements

Earlier drafts were presented in 2018 at the Workshops “The Legitimacy of Transnational Orders: The Idea of a World State”, held at the Clough Center for the Study of Constitutional Democracy, Boston College, and “Hegemony in the International Order”, Luigi Sturzo Institute, Rome. Thanks are due to the organizers, Vlad Perju and Claudio Corradetti, and to the participants for their feedback.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Alessandro Ferrara.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Ferrara, A. “Most Reasonable for Humanity”: Legitimation Beyond the State. Jus Cogens 1, 111–128 (2019). https://doi.org/10.1007/s42439-019-00001-1

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s42439-019-00001-1

Keywords

Navigation