Skip to main content
Log in

Mary Shelley’s Justine and the Monstrous Miseducation of Exclusionary Punishment

  • Published:
Studies in Philosophy and Education Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

In this paper, I examine the miseducation that exclusionary punishment initiates through the significance of gender in the novel Frankenstein. I focus on the minor character of Justine and place her story at the center, as a major account of exclusionary punishment and miseducation in literature. I highlight Shelley’s story about Justine—in its philosophical and educational importance—as a tale about the significance of gender, exclusionary punishment, and miseducation. Justine’s exclusionary punishment is notable in that she is a young girl punished for the crimes of a man and his murderous creation. While Frankenstein and his creature feel themselves to be monstrous at times, Justine is made to be a monster as she is excluded and punished for the crimes of a man. As a result, she nearly begins to believe herself to be monstrous. This is her miseducation as she internalizes her own oppression and is excluded from belonging to human community. Justine’s story both reminds and cautions us that we make our own monsters. The making of Justine into a monster exposes exclusionary punishment as a false education—a miseducation. She is easily neglected through her youth, gender, and femininity as her story is couched within the toiling masculinity of Frankenstein and his creature. Through Justine, I claim that exclusionary punishment is miseducative as evidenced through the gendered experience of being educated to be more woman than person, more gender than human.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Data Availability

Not applicable.

Code Availability

Not applicable.

Notes

  1. I am grateful to the reviewers of this paper who helped push for this important development on the significance of gender and for nurturing the move of centering Justine and telling a different story.

  2. See Shuffelton (2018), Gómez (2012), and Richardson (1991).

  3. See Shalaby (2017), Thompson, Beneke and Mitchell (2020), Lamboy, Taylor and Thompson (2020), Scribner and Warnick (2021), andNussbaum (2005).

  4. For further reference see, Martha Nussbaum (1990), Max van Manen (2016), and Cara Furman (2014).

  5. I am grateful to the mentorship of an early reader who reminded me that in a text based on correspondence, “letters do things” and subsequently pushed me to question what Elizabeth’s letter enacts and signifies in relation to Justine.

  6. For a semiotic understanding of monster, the term monster comes from the Latin monstrare which means “to demonstrate,” “to reveal,” or “to teach.” In an etymological sense, a monster is already something of education insofar as it signifies a demonstration. The term demonstrative from demonstratif means the “showing or making manifest the truth or existence (of something)” (Online Etymology Dictionary). In this sense, monster is a demonstrative revealing that prompts a certain form of existence. There is also the more theological monster from the Latin monstrum meaning “divine omen,” as a warning from a God or gods. For instance, “A warning suggests that there is something one could do. By doing such, it stimulates… it summons choices to be made… The initial sign, then, warns of the catastrophe, but the disaster produces victims who … in effect, become signs, carrying… disaster wherever they go. They become, in other words, monsters. Monsters of disaster are special kinds of divine warning. They are harbingers of things we do not want to face… and we fear that they will bring such events upon us by coming to us” (Gordon and Gordon 2016). In this way, a monster is not necessarily a physical entity insomuch as it is a cautionary revealing.

  7. It is useful here to refer to Nietzsche’s understanding of punishment as the desire to cause suffering insofar as it functions “to make suffer was in the highest degree pleasurable, to the extent that the injured party exchanged for the loss he had sustained… that of making suffer—a genuine festival… To see others suffer does one good, to make others suffer even more: this is a hard saying but an ancient, mighty, human, all-too-human principle… Without cruelty there is no festival… in punishment there is so much that is festive!” (Nietzsche, 2000a, b, 501-503).

  8. Importantly, the demeaning and oppressive power over women becomes a “double jeopardy” for women of color (Bartky, 1990, 91–2).

  9. For instance, Biesta claims, “The means we use in education—our teaching styles, the ways in which we try to promote certain ways of doing and being—are not neutral with regard to the ends but potentially also teach something to students. Punishment is a good example of this as we may well have strong evidence about the effectiveness of some forms of punishment, and we may even have come to the value-judgement that with regard to the use of punishment in a particular situation the benefits outweigh the disadvantages. Yet still we may decide not to use punishment as it would teach children ‘that it is appropriate or permissible in the last resort to enforce one’s will or get one’s own way by the exercise of violence’ (Carr 2006, p. 249)… These points show that values are not simply an element of educational practices, but that they are actually constitutive of such practices” (Biesta 2010).

  10. For example, restraint and seclusion, in-school suspension, out-of-school suspension, expulsion with educational services, expulsion without educational services, expulsion under zero tolerance policies, referral to law enforcement, and transfer to alternative school are permissible forms of punishment within educational institutions. Furthermore, racialized students (predominantly Black students) and students with disabilities are disproportionately disciplined at higher rates (U.S. Department of Education Office for Civil Rights, (2016)).

References

  • Arendt, H. 1969. Between past and future: Six exercises in political thought. Cleveland, OH: World Publishing.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bartky, S.L. 1990. Femininity and domination: Studies in the phenomenology of oppression. New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Biesta, G. 2010. Why “what works” still won’t work: from evidence-based education to value-based education. Studies in Philosophy and Education 29: 491–503.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Butler, J. 1997. The psychic life of power: Theories in subjection. California: Stanford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Carr, D. 2006. Practical enquiry, values, and the problem of educational theory. Oxford Review of Education 18(3): 241–251.

  • Cavarero, A. 1995. In spite of plato: A feminist rewriting of ancient philosophy, trans. Serena Anderlini-D’Onofrio and Aine O’Healy, foreword by Rosi Braidotti. Cambridge: Polity Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dewey, J. 1997. Experience and education. New York: Touchstone.

    Google Scholar 

  • Furman, C. 2014. Reflective teacher narratives: the merging of practical wisdom, narrative, and teaching, [Doctoral dissertation, Columbia University].

  • Gómez, C.R. 2012. Strangers and orphans: Knowledge and mutuality in Mary Shelley’s Frankenstein. Educational Philosophy and Theory 45: 360–370.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gordon, J.A., and L. Gordon. 2016. Of divine warning: Disaster in a modern age. New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hoeveler, D. 2004. Frankenstein, feminism, and literary theory. In The Cambridge companion to Mary Shelley, ed. S. Esther, 45–62. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jantzen, G.M. 2003. Eros and the abyss: Reading medieval mystics in postmodernity. Literature & Theology 17 (3): 244–264.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kennedy, J.E. 2000. Monstrous offenders and the search for solidarity through modern punishment. Hastings Law Journal 51 (5): 829–908.

    Google Scholar 

  • Laird, S. and Bailey, R. 2008. Mary Wollstonecraft Philosophical Mother of Coeducation. London: Continuum, p. 158.

  • Lamboy, L., A. Taylor, and W.C. Thompson. 2020. Paternalistic aims and (mis)attributions of agency: What the over-punishment of black girls in US classrooms teaches us about just school discipline. Theory and Research in Education 18 (1): 59–77.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lepore, J. 2018 The strange and twisted life of Frankenstein. The New Yorker, https://www.newyorker.com/magazine/2018/02/12/the-strange-and-twisted-life-of-frankenstein.

  • Lesser, W. 1992. Introduction to Frankenstein. Everyman’s Library.

  • Lispector, C. 2011. Trans Benjamin Moser. The hour of the star. New York: New Directions Books.

  • Martínez-Alfaro, M.J. 2010. A look into the abyss: The unsolvable enigma of the self and the challenges of metaphysical detection in Martin Amis’s “night train.” Journal of Narrative Theory 40 (1): 124.

    Google Scholar 

  • Moers, E. 1974. Female gothic: The monster’s mother. The New York Review. https://www.nybooks.com/articles/1974/03/21/female-gothic-the-monsters-mother/.

  • Moers, E. 1979. The endurance of frankenstein: essays on Mary Shelley's novel, ed. L. George, U. C. Knoeflmacher. University of California Press.

  • Myers, D. 1999. Monster. New York: Harper Collins.

    Google Scholar 

  • Natanson, M. 1998. The erotic bird: Phenomenology in literature. Princeton University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Nietzsche, F. 2000a. Beyond good and evil: Prelude to a philosophy of the future, trans. Walter Kaufmann. New York: Modern Library Edition.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nietzsche, F. 2000b. On the genealogy of morals, trans. Walter Kaufmann, 2000b. New York: Modern Library.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nussbaum, M. 1990. Love’s knowledge: Essays on philosophy and literature. Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nussbaum, M. 2005. Inscribing the face: Shame, stigma, and punishment. Political Exclusion and Domination 45: 259–302.

    Google Scholar 

  • Richardson, A. 1991. From Emile to Frankenstein: The education of monsters. European Romantic Review 1 (2): 147–162.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rukeyser, M. 2006. Käthe Kollwitz. In The collected poems of Muriel Rukeyser, 460. Pittsburgh, PA: University of Pittsburgh Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Scribner, C., and B. Warnick. 2021. Spare the rod: Punishment and the moral community of schools. University of Chicago Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Sedgwick, E.K. 1985. Between men: English literature and male homosocial desire. New York: Columbia University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Shalaby, C. 2017. Troublemaker: Lessons in freedom from foung children at school. New York: The New Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shelley, M. 1992. Frankenstein. New York: Everyman’s Library.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shuffelton, A. 2018. The monstrosity of parental involvement: Formation through reading in Shelley and Rousseau. Philosophy of Education Yearbook 1: 74–76.

    Google Scholar 

  • Thompson, W.C., J.B. Abigail, and S. Garry. 2020. Mitchell. Legitimate concerns: On complications of identity in school punishment. Theory and Research in Education 18 (1): 78–97.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • U.S. Department of education, office for civil rights. 2016. 2013–2014 civil rights data collection LEA form and all schools form definitions, https://www2.ed.gov/about/offices/list/ocr/docs/2013-14-first-look.pdf.

  • van Manen, M. 2016. Art as a source of lived experience. From Researching lived experience: human science for an active sensitive pedagogy. New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Winters, J.W. 2017. The horrifying sacred: Hip-hop, blackness, and the figure of the monster. Journal of Africana 5 (2): 291–299.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wollstonecraft, M. 2010. A vindication of the rights of woman. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Woodson, C. 2005. The miseducation of the negro. Mineola, NY: Dover Publications.

    Google Scholar 

  • Yousef, N. 2002. The monster in a dark room: Frankenstein, feminism, and philosophy. Modern Language Quarterly 63: 197–226.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Funding

The author did not receive support from any organization for the submitted work.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Contributions

Not applicable.

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Addyson Frattura.

Ethics declarations

Conflict of interest

The author received mentorship on the paper from Dr. Sam Rocha, Dr. Amy Shuffelton, and Dr. Cara Furman.

Ethical Approval

Not applicable.

Consent to Participate

Not applicable.

Consent for Publication

Not applicable.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Frattura, A. Mary Shelley’s Justine and the Monstrous Miseducation of Exclusionary Punishment. Stud Philos Educ 41, 669–685 (2022). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11217-022-09854-4

Download citation

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11217-022-09854-4

Keywords

Navigation