Skip to main content
Log in

Alexander, Joshua. Experimental Philosophy: An Introduction

Malden, MA: Polity Press, 2012. 154pp. Paperback, $22.95, ISBN 978–0745649184

  • Book Review
  • Published:
Philosophia Aims and scope Submit manuscript

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Notes

  1. Alexander apologizes for having to leave out recent experimental work on consciousness and some other big issues. He provides further reading (e.g., Gray et al. 2007; Knobe and Prinz 2008; Arico 2010; Huebner et al. 2010; Sytsma and Machery 2010; Arico et al. 2011). An undergraduate syllabus would want to add the work of Doris (1998, 2002), Haidt (2001) and Greene (2003, 2008).

  2. These quotations are culled from Knobe and Doris (2010).

  3. http://www.youtube.com/watch?v=tt5Kxv8eCTA and http://www.youtube.com/watch?v=sHoyMfHudaE

  4. “Against Intuition,” Christopher Shea, The Chronicle of Higher Education, October 3, 2008.

  5. “Philosophy’s Great Experiment,” David Edmonds, Prospect Magazine, March 1, 2009.

References

  • Adams, F., & Steadman, A. (2004a). Intentional action in ordinary language: Core concept or pragmatic understanding? Analysis, 64, 173–181.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Adams, F., & Steadman, A. (2004b). Intentional action and moral considerations: Still pragmatic. Analysis, 64, 268–276.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Alicke, M. (2000). Culpable control and the psychology of blame. Psychological Bulletin, 126, 556–574.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Arico, A. (2010). Folk psychology, consciousness, and context effects. Review of Philosophy and Psychology, 1, 371–393.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Arico, A., Fiala, B., Goldberg, R., & Nichols, S. (2011). The folk psychology of consciousness. Mind & Language, 22, 21–35.

    Google Scholar 

  • Buckwalter, W. (2011). Experiments in Metaphysics, solving the puzzle of causation by absence. Unpublished Manuscript, City University of New York Graduate Center.

  • Cover, J., & O’Leary-Hawthorne, J. (1996). Free agency and materialism. In J. Jordan & D. Howard-Snyder (Eds.), Faith, freedom and rationality (pp. 47–71). Lanham, MD: Roman and Littlefield.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cushman, F., & Mele, A. (2008). Intentional action: Two-and-a-half folk concepts? In J. Knobe & S. Nichols (Eds.), Experimental Philosophy (pp. 171–188). New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cushman, F., Knobe, J., & Sinnott-Armstrong, W. (2008). Moral appraisals affect doing/allowing judgments. Cognition, 108, 353–380.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Doris, J. (1998). Persons, situations, and virtue ethics. Nous, 32, 504–530.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Doris, J. (2002). Lack of Character. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ekstrom, L. (2002). Libertarianism and Frankfurt-style cases. In R. Kane (Ed.), The oxford handbook of free will. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Feltz, A.,Cokely, E. (2007). An anomaly in intentional action ascription: more evidence of folk diversity. Proceedings of the Cognitive Science Society 1748.

  • Feltz, A., & Cokely, E. (2009). Do judgments about freedom and responsibility depend on who you are? Personality differences in intuitions about compatibilism and incompatibilism. Consciousness and Cognition, 18, 342–350.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gettier, E. (1963). Is justified true belief knowledge? Analysis, 23, 121–123.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gray, H., Gray, K., & Wegner, D. (2007). Dimensions of mind perception. Science, 315, 619.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Greene, J. (2003). From neural ‘is’ to moral ‘ought’: What are the moral implications of neuroscientific moral psychology? Nature Reviews Neuroscience, 4, 846–850.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Greene, J. (2008). The secret joke of Kant’s soul. In W. Sinnott-Armstrong (Ed.), Moral psychology, volume 3: The neuroscience of morality: emotion, brain disorders, and development (pp. 35–80). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Haidt, J. (2001). The emotional dog and its rational tail: A social intuitionist approach to moral judgment. Psychological Review, 108, 814–834.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hitchcock, C., & Knobe, J. (2011). Cause and norm. Journal of Philosophy, 106, 587–612.

    Google Scholar 

  • Huebner, B., Bruno, M., & Sarkissian, H. (2010). What does the nation of China think about phenomenal consciousness. Review of Philosophy and Psychology, 1, 225–243.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kane, R. (1999). The significance of free will. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Kaupinnen, A. (2007). The rise and fall of experimental philosophy. Philosophical Explorations, 10, 95–118.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Knobe, J. (2003). Intentional action and side effects in ordinary language. Analysis, 63, 190–194.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Knobe, J. (2006). The concept of intentional action: A case study in the uses of folk psychology. Philosophical Studies, 130, 203–231.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Knobe, J. (2007a). Experimental philosophy. Philosophy Compass, 2, 81–92.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Knobe, J. (2007b). Experimental philosophy and philosophical significance. Philosophical Explorations, 10, 119–122.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Knobe, J. (2010). Person as scientist, person as moralist. The Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 33, 315–365.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Knobe, J., & Burra, A. (2006). Intention and intentional action: A cross-cultural study. Journal of Culture and Cognition, 6, 113–132.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Knobe, J., & Doris, J. (2010). Strawsonian variations: Folk morality and the search for a unified theory. In J. Doris et al. (Eds.), The handbook of moral psychology. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Knobe, J., & Fraser, B. (2008). Causal judgment and moral judgment: two experiments. In W. Sinnott-Armstrong (Ed.), Moral psychology, vol. 2: The cognitive science of morality: Intuition and diversity (pp. 441–448). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Knobe, J., & Nichols, S. (2008). An experimental philosophy manifesto. In J. Knobe & S. Nichols (Eds.), Experimental philosophy. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Knobe, J., & Prinz, J. (2008). Intuitions about consciousness. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 1, 67–83.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Knobe, J., & Roedder, E. (2009). The ordinary concept of valuing. Philosophical Issues, 19, 131–147.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Knobe, J., Buckwalter, W., Nichols, S., Robbins, P., Sarkissian, H., & Sommers, T. (2012). Experimental Philosophy. Annual Review of Psychology, 63, 81–99.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kornblith, H. (2007). Naturalism and intuitions. Grazer Philosophische Studien, 72, 27–49.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kripke, S. (1980). Naming and necessity. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Leslie, A., Knobe, J., & Cohen, A. (2006). Acting intentionally and the side-effect effect: ‘Theory of mind’ and moral judgment. Psychological Science, 17, 421–427.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ludwig, K. (2007). The epistemology of thought experiments: First person versus third person approaches. Midwest Studies in Philosophy, 31, 128–159.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Machery, E. (2008). Understanding the folk concept of intentional action: Philosophical and experimental issues. Mind and Language, 23, 165–189.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Machery, E., Mallon, R., Nichols, S., & Stich, S. (2004). Semantics, cross-cultural style. Cognition, 92, B1–B12.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mallon, R. (2008). Knobe versus Machery: Testing the trade-off hypothesis. Mind and Language, 23, 247–255.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mallon, R., Machery, E., Nichols, S., & Stich, S. (2009). Against arguments from reference. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 79, 332–356.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nadelhoffer, T. (2004a). On praise, side effects, and folk ascriptions of intentionality. Journal of Theoretical and Philosophical Psychology, 24, 196–213.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nadelhoffer, T. (2004b). Blame, badness, and intentional action: A reply to Knobe and Mendlow. Journal of Theoretical and Philosophical Psychology, 24, 259–269.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nadelhoffer, T. (2005). Skill, luck, control, and folk ascriptions of intentional action. Philosophical Psychology, 18, 343–354.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nadelhoffer, T. (2006). Bad acts, blameworthy agents, and intentional actions: some problems for jury impartiality. Philosophical Explorations, 9, 203–220.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nahmias, E., Morris, S., Nadelhoffer, T., & Turner, J. (2006). Is incompatibilism intuitive? Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 73, 28–53.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nichols, S., Stich, S., & Weinberg, J. (2003). Metaskepticism: meditations in ethno-epistemology. In S. Luper (Ed.), The skeptics: Contemporary debates (pp. 227–248). Burlington, VT: Ashgate Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nichols, S., & Knobe, J. (2007). Moral responsibility and determinism: The cognitive science of folk intuitions. Nous, 43, 663–685.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nichols, S., & Ulatowski, J. (2007). Intuitions and individual differences: The Knobe effect revisited. Mind and Language, 22, 346–365.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pellizzoni, S., Siegal, M., & Surian, L. (2009). Foreknowledge, caring, and the side-effect effect in young children. Developmental Psychology, 45, 289–295.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Petrinovich, L., & O’Neill, P. (1996). Influence of wording and framing effects on moral intuitions. Ethology and Sociobiology, 17, 145–171.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pettit, D., & Knobe, J. (2009). The pervasive impact of moral judgment. Mind and Language., 24(5), 586–604.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Phelan, M., & Sarkissian, H. (2009). Is the trade-off hypothesis worth trading for? Mind and Language, 24, 164–180.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Phillips, J., Nyholm, S., & Liao, S. (2011). The ordinary concept of happiness. Yale University: Unpublished manuscript.

    Google Scholar 

  • Roxborough, C., & Cumby, J. (2009). Folk psychological concepts: Causation. Philosophical Psychology, 22, 205–213.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Solan, L., & Darley, J. (2001). Causation, contribution, and legal liability: An empirical study. Law and Contemporary Problems, 64, 265–298.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sytsma, J., & Machery, E. (2010). Two conceptions of subjective experience. Philosophical Studies, 151, 299–327.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tannenbaum, D., Ditto, P., & Pizarro, D. (2009). Different moral values produce different judgments of intentional action. Irvine: Unpublished Manuscript, University of California.

    Google Scholar 

  • Weinberg, J. (2007). How to challenge intuitions empirically without risking skepticism. Midwest Studies in Philosophy, 31, 318–343.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Weinberg, J., Nichols, S., & Stich, S. (2001). Normativity and epistemic intuitions. Philosophical Topics, 29, 429–460.

    Google Scholar 

  • Williamson, T. (2007). The philosophy of philosophy. Oxford: Blackwell Publishing.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Williamson, T. (2011). Philosophical expertise and the burden of proof. Metaphilosophy, 42, 215–229.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Zamzow, J., & Nichols, S. (2009). Variations in ethical intuitions. Philosophical Issues, 19, 368–388.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to David J. Frost.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Frost, D.J. Alexander, Joshua. Experimental Philosophy: An Introduction . Philosophia 40, 903–917 (2012). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11406-012-9392-3

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11406-012-9392-3

Navigation