Skip to main content

Neo-Pragmatism and Enactive Intentionality

  • Chapter
Action, Perception and the Brain

Abstract

Enactive approaches in cognitive science propose that perception, and more generally cognitive experience, are strongly mediated by embodied (sensory–motor) processes, and that our primary experience of the world is action-oriented or pragmatic (Noë, 2004; Thompson, 2007; Varela et al., 1991). Extended mind theorists propose that cognition supervenes on embodied and environmental processes such as gestures and the use of various technologies (Clark, 2008; Clark and Chalmers, 1998; Menary, 2010). Both enactive and extended conceptions of cognition suggest that the mind is not “in the head”–that cognitive processes are distributed over brain, body, and environment – but they also differ on a number of issues. Extended mind theorists defend a functionalist account of cognition and downplay the role of the body (e.g., Clark, 2008), and they argue that cognition and action can involve mental representations (e.g., Clark, 1997; Clark and Grush, 1999; Rowlands, 2006; Wheeler, 2005). In contrast, enactive theorists argue for radical embodiment (e.g., Thompson and Varela, 2001) and defend an antirepresentationalist view (e.g., Gallagher, 2008b; Hutto, in press; Thompson, 2007). There are also debates about how to define the boundaries, or lack of boundaries, involved in cognitive processes (e.g., Di Paolo, 2009; Wheeler, 2008).

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

eBook
USD 16.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 16.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 54.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

References

  • Adams, F. and Aizawa, K. (2001). The bounds of cognition. Philosophical Psychology, 14, no. 1, 43–64.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Adams, F. and Aizawa, K. (2008). The Bounds of Cognition. Malden, MA: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Adams, F. and Aizawa, K. (2009). Why the mind is still in the head. In P. Robbins and M. Aydede (Eds), The Cambridge Handbook for Situated Cognition. New York: Cambridge University Press, pp. 78–95.

    Google Scholar 

  • Baillargeon, R. and Song, H.-J.(2008). Infants’ reasoning about others’ false perceptions. Developmental Psychology, 44, no. 6, 1,789–95.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Baillargeon, R., Scott, R. M., and He, Z. (2010). False-belief understanding in infants. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 14, no. 3, 110–18.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Baird, J. A., and Baldwin, D. A. (2001). Making sense of human behavior: Action parsing and intentional inference. In B. F. Malle, L. J. Moses, and D. A. Baldwin (Eds), Intentions and intentionality: Foundations of social cognition. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, pp. 193–206.

    Google Scholar 

  • Baldwin, D. A., and Baird, J. A. (2001). Discerning intentions in dynamic human action. Trends in Cognitive Science, 5, no. 4, 171–8.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Baron-Cohen, S. (1991). Precursors to a theory of mind: Understanding attention in others. In A. Whiten (Ed.), Natural theories of mind: Evolution, development and simulation of everyday mindreading. Oxford, UK: Basil Blackwell, pp. 233–51.

    Google Scholar 

  • Baron-Cohen, S. (1995). Mindblindness: An Essay on Autism and Theory of Mind. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Beer, R. D. (2000). Dynamical approaches to cognitive science. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 4, no. 3, 91–9.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Beer, R. D. (2003). The dynamics of active categorical perception in an evolved model agent. Adaptive Behavior, 11, no. 4, 209–43.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brandom, R. B. (1994). Making It Explicit: Reasoning, Representing, and Discursive Commitment. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brandom, R. B. (2000). Articulating Reasons: An Introduction to Inferentialism. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brandom, R. B. (2008). Between Saying and Doing: Towards an Analytic Pragmatism. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Brentano, F. (2008/1862). Psychologie vom empirischen Standpunkte. Von der Klassifikation der psychischen Phänomene. (Mauro Antonelli, Ed.) Heusenstamm: Ontos.

    Google Scholar 

  • Buccino, G., Lui, F., Canessa, N., Patteri, I., Lagravinese, G., Benuzzi, F., Porro, C. A., and Rizzolatti, G. (2004). Neural circuits involved in the recognition of actions performed by non-conspecifics: an fMRI study. Journal of Cognitive Neuroscience, 16, no. 1, 114–126.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Buttelmann, D., Carpenter, M., and Tomasello, M. (2009). Eighteen-monthold infants show false belief understanding in an active helping paradigm. Cognition, 112, 337–42.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cash, M. (2008). Thought and Oughts. Philosophical Explorations, 11, no. 2, 93–119.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cash, M. (2009). Normativity is the mother of intentionality: Wittgenstein, normative practices and neurological representations. New Ideas in Psychology, 27, 133–47.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cash, M. (2010). Extended cognition, personal responsibility, and relational autonomy. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 9, no. 4, 645–71.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Catmur, C., Walsh, V., and Heyes, C. (2007). Sensorimotor learning configures the human mirror system. Current Biology, 17, no. 1, 527–31.

    Google Scholar 

  • Clark, A. (1997). Being There: Putting Brain, Body and World Together Again. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Clark, A. (2008). Supersizing the Mind: Embodiment, Action, and Cognitive Extension. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Clark, A. and Chalmers, D. (1998). The extended mind. Analysis, 58, no. 1, 7–19.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Clark, A. and Grush, R. (1999). Towards a cognitive robotics. Adaptive Behavior, 7, no. 1, 5–16.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Crane, T. (1998). Intentionality as the mark of the mental. In A. O’Hear (Ed.), Contemporary Issues in the Philosophy of Mind. Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement (No. 43). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Csibra, G. (2005). Mirror neurons and action observation. Is simulation involved? ESF Interdisciplines. http://www.interdisciplines.org/medias/confs/archives/ archive_8.pdf (accessed 3 October 2011).

  • Csibra, G. and Gergely, G. (2009). Natural pedagogy. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 13,148–53.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Currie, G. (2008). Some ways to understand people. Philosophical Explorations, 11, no. 3, 211–18.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • De Jaegher, H. and Di Paolo, E. A. (2007). Participatory sense-making: An enactive approach to social cognition. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 6, no. 4, 485–507.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • De Jaegher, H., Di Paolo, E. A., and Gallagher, S. (2010). Can social interaction constitute social cognition? Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 14, no. 10, 441–7.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dennett, D. (1971). Intentional systems. The Journal of Philosophy, 68, no. 4, 87–106.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dennett, D. (1987). The Intentional Stance. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dennett, D. (1991). Consciousness Explained. Boston: Little, Brown, and Co.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dewey, J. (1934). Art as Experience. New York: Perigee/Berkley.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dinstein, I., Thomas, C., Behrmann, M., and Heeger, D. J. (2008).A mirror up to nature. Current Biology, 18, no. 1,R13–R18.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Di Paolo, E. (2009). Extended life. Topoi, 28, no. 1, 9–21.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dittrich, W.H., Troscianko, T., Lea, S.E.G., and Morgan, D. (1996). Perception of emotion from dynamic point-light displays represented in dance. Perception, 25, 727–38.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Froese, T. and Di Paolo, E. A. (2010). Modeling social interaction as perceptual crossing: An investigation into the dynamics of the interaction process. Connection Science, 22, no. 1, 43–68.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Froese, T. and Di Paolo, E. A. (in press). Toward Minimally Social Behavior: Social Psychology Meets Evolutionary Robotics. Advances in Artificial Life: Proc. of the 10th Euro. Conf. on Artificial Life. Berlin, Germany: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Froese, T. and Gallagher, S. (2010). Phenomenology and Artificial Life: Toward a Technological Supplementation of Phenomenological Methodology. Husserl Studies, 26, no. 2, 83–106.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Froese, T. and Gallagher, S. (submitted). Being together: Strong interaction and dynamical systems theory.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gallagher, S. (2001). The Practice of Mind: Theory, Simulation or Primary Interaction? Journal of Consciousness Studies, 8, no. 5–7, 83–108.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gallagher, S. (2005). How the Body Shapes the Mind. New York, NY: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Gallagher, S. (2007). Simulation trouble. Social Neuroscience, 2, no. 3–4, 353–65.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gallagher, S. (2008a). Are minimal representations still representations? International Journal of Philosophical Studies, 16, no. 3, 351–69.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gallagher, S. (2008b). Neural simulation and social cognition. In J. A. Pineda (Ed.), Mirror Neuron Systems: The Role of Mirroring Processes in Social Cognition. Totowa, NJ: Humana Press, pp. 355–71.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Gallagher, S. (2011). Narrative competency and the massive hermeneutical background. In P. Fairfield. Education, Dialogue, and Hermeneutics. (21–38) New York: Continuum.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gallagher, S. and Hutto, D. (2008). Understanding others through primary interaction and narrative practice. In J. Zlatev, T. P. Racine, C. Sinha, and E. Itkonen (Eds), The Shared Mind: Perspectives on Intersubjectivity. Amsterdam: John Benjamins, pp. 17–38.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Gallagher, S. and Meltzoff, A. (1996). The earliest sense of self and others: Merleau-Ponty and recent developmental studies. Philosophical Psychology, 9, 213–36.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gallagher, S. and Zahavi, D. (2008). The Phenomenological Mind: An Introduction to Philosophy of Mind and Cognitive Science. London, UK: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gallese, V. (2005). ‘Being like me’: Self-other identity, mirror neurons and empathy. In S. Hurley and N. Chater (Eds), Perspectives on Imitation I. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, pp. 101–18.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gallese, V. (2009). The Two Sides of Mimesis: Girard’s Mimetic Theory, Embodied Simulation and Social Identification. Journal of Consciousness Studies, 16, no. 4, 21–44.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gallese, V. (2010). Embodied Simulation and its Role in Intersubjectivity. In T. Fuchs, H. C. Sattel, and P. Henningsen (Eds), The Embodied Self: Dimensions, Coherence and Disorders. Stuttgart, Germany: Schattauer, pp. 78–92.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gallese, V., and Goldman, A. (1998). Mirror neurons and the simulation theory of mind-reading. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 2, 493–501.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Goldman, A. I. (2006). Simulating Minds: The Philosophy, Psychology, and Neuroscience of Mindreading. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Gopnik, A. and Meltzoff, A. N. (1997). Words, Thoughts, and Theories. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Harvey, I., Di Paolo, E.A., Wood, R., Quinn, M., and Tuci, E. A. (2005). Evolutionary Robotics: A new scientific tool for studying cognition. Artificial Life, 11, no. 1–2, 79–98.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Haugeland, J. (1990). Intentionality all-stars. Philosophical Perspectives, 4, 383–427. Reprinted in J. Haugeland, Having Thought: Essays in the Metaphysics of Mind. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, pp. 127–70.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Heider, F., and Simmel, M. (1944). An experimental study of apparent behavior. The American Journal of Psychology, 57, no. 2, 243–59.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hickok, G. (2009). Eight problems for the mirror neuron theory of action understanding in monkeys and humans. J CognNeurosci, 21, no. 7, 1,229–43.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hobson, P. (1993). The emotional origins of social understanding. Philosophical Psychology, 6, 227–49.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hobson, P. (2002). The Cradle of Thought. London: Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hobson, P. and Lee, A. (1999). Imitation and identification in autism. Journal of Child Psychology and Psychiatry, 40, 649–59.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Horgan, T. E. and Kriegel, U. (2008). Phenomenal intentionality meets the extended mind. The Monist, 91, 353–80.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Horgan, T. E., and Tienson, J. L. (2002). The intentionality of phenomenology and the phenomenology of intentionality. In D. J. Chalmers (Ed.), Philosophy of Mind: Classical and Contemporary Readings. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Husserl, E. (1977). Phenomenological Psychology. (J. Scanlon, Trans.). The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Husserl, E. (1982/1913). Ideas Pertaining to a Pure Phenomenology and to a Phenomenological Philosophy – First Book.(F. Kersten, Trans.). The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Hutto, D. (in press). Philosophy of mind’s new lease on life: Autopoietic enactivism meets teleosemiotics. Journal of Consciousness Studies (Spring 2011).

    Google Scholar 

  • Iizuka, H. and Di Paolo, E. A. (2007). Minimal agency detection of embodied agents. In F. Almeida e Costa, L. M. Rocha, E. Costa, I. Harvey, and A. Coutinho (Eds), Advances in Artificial Life: Proc. of the 9th Euro. Conf. on Artificial Life. Berlin, Germany: Springer, pp. 485–94.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Issartel, J., Marin, L., and Cadopi, M. (2007). Unintended interpersonal coordination: ‘can we march to the beat of our own drum?’ Neuroscience Letters, 411, no. 3, 174–9.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Johnson, M. (2008). The Meaning of the Body: Aesthetics of Human Understanding. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kendon, A. (1990). Conducting Interaction: Patterns of behavior in focused encounters. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Keysers, C. and Gazzola, V. (2006). Towards a unifying neural theory of social cognition. In S. Anders, G. Ende, M. Junghofer, and J. Kissler (Eds), Understanding Emotions. Amsterdam: Elsevier, 379–402.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Lindblom, J. (2007). Minding the Body – Interacting socially through embodied action. Dissertation, University of Linköping and University of Skövde.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lindblom, J. and Ziemke, T. (2008). Interacting socially through embodied action. In F. Morganti, A. Carassa, and G. Riva (Eds), Enacting Intersubjectivity: A Cognitive and Social Perspective on the Study of Interactions. Amsterdam, Netherlands: IOS Press, pp. 49–63.

    Google Scholar 

  • Maurer, D. and Barrera, M. E. (1981). Infants’ perception of natural and distorted arrangements of a schematic face. Child Development, 52, no. 1, 196–202.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Meltzoff, A. N. and Moore, M. K. (1977). Imitation of facial and manual gestures by human neonates. Science, 198, 75–8.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Meltzoff, A. N. and Moore, M. K. (1994). Imitation, memory, and the representation of persons. Infant Behavior and Development, 17, 83–99.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Menary, R. (Ed.) 2010. The Extended Mind. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Merleau-Ponty, M. (1962/1945). Phenomenology of Perception. (C. Smith, Trans.). London: Routledge and Kegan Paul.

    Google Scholar 

  • Merleau-Ponty, M. (1968). The Visible and the Invisible. (A. Lingis, Trans.). Evanston: Northwestern University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Michotte, A. (1963). The Perception of Causality. (T. Miles, and E. Miles, Trans.). New York: Basic Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Miyahara, K. (2011). Neo-pragmatic intentionality and enactive perception: A compromise between extended and enactive minds. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences (DOI: 10.1007/s11097-011-9212-4). Pre-published online.

  • Murray, L. and Trevarthen, C. (1985). Emotional regulations of interactions between two-month-olds and their mothers. In T. M. Field and N. A. Fox (Eds), Social perception in infants. Norwood, NJ: Ablex Publishing, pp. 177–97.

    Google Scholar 

  • Newman-Norlund, R.D., Noordzij, M.L., Meulenbroek, R.G.J., and Bekkering, H. (2007). Exploring the brain basis of joint attention: Co-ordination of actions, goals and intentions. Social Neuroscience, 2, no. 1, 48–65.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Noë, A. (2004). Action in Perception. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Oberman, L. M. and Ramachandran, V. S. (2007). The simulating social mind: The role of the mirror neuron system and simulation in the social and communicative deficits of autism spectrum disorders. Psychological Bulletin, 133, no. 2, 310–27.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Onishi, K.H., and Baillargeon, R. (2005). Do 15-month-old infants understand false beliefs?Science, 308, 255–8.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pettit, P. (1996). The Common Mind. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Ratcliffe, M. (2007). Rethinking Commonsense Psychology: A Critique of Folk Psychology, Theory of Mind and Simulation. Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Reddy, V. and Morris, P. (2004). Participants don’t need theories: Knowing minds in engagement. Theory and Psychology, 14, no. 5, 647–65.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rizzolatti, G., Fogassi, L., and Gallese, V. (2001). Neurophysiological mechanisms underlying the understanding and imitation of action. Nature Reviews Neuroscience, 2, 661–70.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rowlands, M. (2006). Body Language. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rupert, R. (2004). Challenges to the hypothesis of extended cognition. The Journal of Philosophy, 101, no. 8, 389–428.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schulkin, J. (2008). Cognitive Adaptation: A Pragmatist Perspective. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Searle, J. (1992). The Rediscovery of the Mind. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Senju, A., Johnson, M. H., and Csibra, G. (2006). The development and neural basis of referential gaze perception. Social Neuroscience, 1, no. 3–4, 220–34.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shapiro, L. (in press). Review of Fred Adams and Ken Aizawa, The Bounds of Cognition (Malden, MA: Blackwell, 2008). Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences.

    Google Scholar 

  • Song, H.-J., Onishi, K. H., Baillargeon, R., and Fisher, C. (2008). Can an agent’s false belief be corrected by an appropriate communication? Psychological reasoning in 18-month-old infants. Cognition, 109, no. 3, 295–315.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Southgate, V., Senju, A., and Csibra, G. (2007). Action anticipation through attribution of false belief by 2-year-olds. Psychological Science, 18, no. 7, 587–92.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Southgate, V., Chevallier, C., and Csibra, G. (2010). Seventeen-month-olds appeal to false beliefs to interpret others’ referential communication. Developmental Science, 13, no. 6, 907–12.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Spaulding, S. (2010). Embodied cognition and mindreading. Mind and Language, 25, no. 1, 119–40.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Thompson, E. (2007). Mind in Life: Biology, Phenomenology, and the Sciences of Mind. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Thompson, E. and Varela, F. (2001). Radical embodiment: Neural dynamics and consciousness. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 5, no. 10, 418–25.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Träuble, B., Marinović, V., and Pauen, S. (2010). Early theory of mind competencies: Do infants understand others’ beliefs? Infancy, 15, no. 4, 434–44.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Trevarthen, C. B. (1979). Communication and cooperation in early infancy: A description of primary intersubjectivity. In M. Bullowa (Ed.), Before Speech. Cambridge, MA: Cambridge University Press, pp. 321–47.

    Google Scholar 

  • Trevarthen, C. and Hubley, P. (1978). Secondary intersubjectivity: Confidence, confiding and acts of meaning in the first year. In A. Lock (Ed.), Action, Gesture and Symbol: The Emergence of Language. London: Academic Press, pp. 183–229.

    Google Scholar 

  • Varela, F., Thompson, E., and Rosch, E. (1991). The Embodied Mind. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Walker, A. S. (1982). Intermodal perception of expressive behaviors by human infants. Journal of Experimental Child Psychology, 33, 514–35.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wheeler, M. (2005). Reconstructing the Cognitive World: The Next Step. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wheeler, M. (2008). Mind, things and materiality. In Renfrew C. and Malafouris L. (Eds.), The Cognitive Life of Things: Recasting the Boundaries of the Mind. Cambridge: McDonald Institute for Archaeological Research Publications.

    Google Scholar 

  • Woodward, A. L., and Sommerville, J. A. (2000). Twelve-month-old infants interpret action in context. Psychological Science, 11, 73–7.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Authors

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Copyright information

© 2012 Shaun Gallagher and Katsunori Miyahara

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Gallagher, S., Miyahara, K. (2012). Neo-Pragmatism and Enactive Intentionality. In: Schulkin, J. (eds) Action, Perception and the Brain. New Directions in Philosophy and Cognitive Science. Palgrave Macmillan, London. https://doi.org/10.1057/9780230360792_6

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics